[][]

OBSERVATIONS ON SOAME JENYNS'S VIEW OF THE INTERNAL EVIDENCE OF THE CHRISTIAN RELIGION; ADDRESSED TO ITS ALMOST-CHRISTIAN AUTHOR, BY W. KENRICK, LL. D.

I would to God that not only thou, but alſo all that hear me this day, were both almoſt and altogether, Chriſtians. PAUL TO AGRIPPA.

LONDON: PRINTED FOR THE AUTHOR; AND SOLD BY T. EVANS, PATER-NOSTER ROW, AND G. CORRALL, CATHERINE-STREET, STRAND. M DCC LXXVI.

TO SOAME JENYNS, ESQ.

[]
SIR,

APOLOGIES, for the liberties we take with individuals, when the intereſts of all mankind are at ſtake, are as frivolous as they are impertinent. I ſhall make none, therefore, for ſuch as are taken in the following Obſervations on your late View of the Internal Evidence of the Chriſtian Religion.—The ſubject, indeed, is of ſuch high debate, and its deſign of ſuch ſuperior dignity, that even the decency of decorum requires the baniſhment of unmeaning ceremony.—St. Paul, tho a priſoner and in bonds, ſtood upon none, even with King Agrippa on his judgment-ſeat; when, on the preſumption of that princely perſonage's being almoſt a Chriſtian, he wiſhed that not only he, but all his hearers, were altogether ſuch.

[iv]Whether my arguments are ſufficiently forcible, or are properly calculated, to be in any degree inſtrumental to the accompliſhment of a ſimilar wiſh, muſt be determined by their influence on my readers; among whom, I preſume, Sir, you will be one of the moſt reſpectable. Whatever be the reſult, therefore, I ſhall add to the other liberties I have taken, that of congratulating you, who once confeſſedly believed as little as others, on the promiſing progreſs you have already made, in becoming almoſt, what I confidently truſt you will, thro ſuperior influence, ſooner or later, altogether be, a CHRISTIAN: as far as is conſiſtent with which character,

I am, Sir, Your moſt obedient, Humble Servant, W. KENRICK.

ADVERTISEMENT.

[]

THE extraordinary demand, for the Appendix to the third volume of the London Review, in which a ſlight ſketch of the following Obſervations was firſt printed, having ſuggeſted to the author that their republication, in a more commodious form, would be acceptable to the Public, he was led to a more conſiderate reviſal of the tract, which gave riſe to them. The ſlips and inadvertencies, which appeared, on ſuch reviſal, to have eſcaped him in the hurry of compoſition, acquiring conſequence from the importance of the ſubject, urged alſo a kind of neceſſity for ſuch republication.

The deſire of atoning, for the defects of that haſty critique, induced him, therefore, to enlarge on the more intereſting parts of the View, and to digeſt the whole of his Obſervations on it, into a more methodical and regular form.

[vi]The Obſerver was the more readily induced to this, by an apparent deficiency of method in Mr. Jenyns's tract; though profeſſedly calculated for the peruſal of "the Buſy and the Idle," who may be comprized under thoſe who have but little time to read, and thoſe who read but little at a time; for whoſe convenience, therefore, the matter is here ſo managed, by a proper ſubdiviſion of the ſubject, that the reader, be he as buſy or as idle as he will, may take up or lay down the book at pleaſure, without running any riſk of loſing, without recovery, the thread of its argument.

CONTENTS.

[]
  • SECT I. On the ſubject, ſcope, and deſign of the writer's argument in general, viz. ‘To prove the truth, by demonſtrating the divine origin of the Chriſtian Religion,’The moſt convincing proofs pretended to, amount but to a mere probability. Page 1
  • SECT. II. On the definition of the ſubject, and diviſion of the argument into four propoſitions.— The firſt "That there is now extant a book entitled the New Teſtament," ſhewn to be futile and frivolous. Page 22
  • SECT. III. On the ſecond propoſition, viz. ‘That from this book may be extracted a ſyſtem of religion entirely new, both with regard to the object and the doctrines, not only ſuperior to, but unlike every thing, which had ever before entered the human mind,’This propoſition ſhewn to be very obſcurely illuſtrated, inconſiſtently explained, and even of little conſequence to the general argument, were it capable of being proved. Page 27
  • SECT. IV. On the third propoſition. ‘That from this book may likewiſe be collected a ſyſtem [viii] of Ethicks, in which every moral precept, founded on reaſon, is carried to a higher degree of perfection, than in any other of the wiſeſt philoſophers of preceding ages; every precept founded on falſe principles is totally omitted, and many new precepts added, peculiarly correſponding with the new object of this religion.’This propoſition ſhewn to be very exceptionably illuſtrated; affording at beſt rather a proof of the ſublimity and purity of Chriſtian morals, and of the advantages, rather than the truth of the Chriſtian religion. Page 44
  • SECT. V. On the fourth or concluſive propoſition. ‘That ſuch a ſyſtem of religion and morality could not poſſibly have been the work of any man or ſet of men: much leſs of thoſe obſcure and illiterate perſons, who actually did diſcover and publiſh it to the world; and that, therefore, it muſt undoubtedly have been effected by the interpoſition of divine power, that is, it muſt derive its origin from God.’This propoſition ſhewn to contain only corollaries of the preceeding propoſitions; and, though true as to fact and therefore admitted ex gratia, ſtill problematical in argument. Page 83
  • [ix] SECT. VI. On the writer's general concluſions and his notions concerning the eſſential objects of the Chriſtian faith.—Till theſe objects are preciſely determined, the determination of the queſtion reſpecting their divine origin of little importance. Page 101
  • SECT. VII. On the objections, that have been made to the divinity and veracity of the Chriſtian religion: and particularly to objection the FIRST, viz. ‘That divine Revelation is incredible becauſe unneceſſary, becauſe the reaſon, which God has beſtowed on mankind is ſufficiently able to diſcover all the religious and moral duties, which he requires of them; if they will but attend to her precepts and be guided by her friendly admonitions.’This objection ſhewn to be neither properly ſtated nor ſatisfactorily removed. Page 113
  • SECT. VIII. On his reply to a ſecond objection, ‘That the Old and New Teſtament cannot be a revelation from God, becauſe in them are to be found errors and inconſiſtencies, fabulous ſtories, falſe facts and falſe philoſophy; which can never be derived from the Fountain of all [x] Truth.’This objection ſhewn to be rather enforced by the author's conceſſions, than removed by his concluſions. Page 125
  • SECT. IX. On his reply to a third objection. ‘That a wiſe and benevolent Creator ſhould have conſtituted a world upon one plan and a religion for it on another.’ Under the term religion in this objection, the author is ſhewn to include morals alſo; but the purity of the Chriſtian morals is ſhewn not to be calculated for the conſtitution of this world, and therefore not required of Chriſtians in their preſent ſtate of probation. Page 129
  • SECT. X. On his reply to a fourth objection, ‘That if this revelation had really been from God, his infinite power and goodneſs could never have ſuffered it to have been ſo ſoon perverted from its original purity, to have continued in a ſtate of corruption through the courſe of ſo many ages; and at laſt to have proved ſo ineffectual to the reformation of mankind.’The manner, in which this objection is attempted to be removed, ſhewn to reflect the higheſt indignity on the divine Author of the Chriſtian religion as well as on that religion itſelf. Page 142
  • [xi] SECT. XI. On his reply to the fifth objection, ‘The incredibility of ſome of its doctrines, particularly thoſe concerning the Trinity, and atonement for ſin by the ſufferings and death of Chriſt; the one contradicting all the principles of human reaſon, and the other all our ideas of natural juſtice.’This objection ſhewn to be rather evaded than ſolved; the author not having fairly and fully ſtated the difficulties it really contains. Page 147
  • SECT. XII. On his reply to the ſixth objection. ‘That, however true theſe doctrines may be, yet it muſt be inconſiſtent with the juſtice and goodneſs of the Creator, to require from his creatures the belief of propoſitions, which contradict, or are above the reach of that reaſon, which he has thought proper to beſtow on them.’This objection anſwered by denying that genuine Chriſtianity requires any ſuch belief.—The nature of the Chriſtian faith inveſtigated and its latitude defined: Chriſtianity, as it requires nothing impracticable, to be performed, ſo it requires nothing impoſſible to be believed. Page 160
  • [xii] [...]ECT. XIII. On his reply to the ſeventh objection. ‘That the whole ſcheme of Revelation is partial, falſe, fluctuating, unjuſt, and unworthy of an omniſcient and omnipotent Author.’ Page 199
  • SECT. XIV. General Reflections on the whole argument, and concluſion in favour of univerſal candour, in judging of the faith and morals of others, or the exertion of Chriſtian charity toward all mankind. Page 203

OBSERVATIONS ON A VIEW Of THE INTERNAL EVIDENCE OF THE CHRISTIAN RELIGION.

[]

SECT. I.

On the ſubject, ſcope, and deſign of the writer's argument in general, viz. ‘To prove the truth, by demonſtrating the divine origin, of the Chriſtian Religion,’—The moſt convincing proofs pretended to, amount but to a mere probability.

AMONG the many attempts, to recommend and accommodate the profound myſteries of divine wiſdom to the ſhallow comprehenſion of the human underſtanding, the preſent is by no means the leaſt promiſing or plauſible. [2] But the Impoſſible, neceſſarily includes the Impracticable, and all attempts, to reconcile objects, that are in their very eſſence irreconcileable, muſt ever be ineffectual.

In pride, in reaſoning pride, our errour lies;
All quit their ſphere and ruſh into the ſkies:
Aſpiring to be gods if angels fell,
Aſpiring to be angels, men rebel.

Hence nothing can be more reprehenſible, than the arrogance of our modern Rationaliſts, in cavilling at every thing in Revelation, that is not reconcileable to Reaſon, and in denying every thing to be religious that is not rational. Tenacious of the name of Chriſtians, as they are of the principles of Heathens, they want to newmodel the ſyſtem of Chriſtianity, by expunging all thoſe doctrines, which they cannot reconcile to their newſangled ſcheme of Rationality. But, [3] alas! their reaſoning faculties are too confined, to ſoar above ‘—this viſible, diurnal ſphere;’ ſo that, after all, they muſt ſit down content with a religion, which entitles them to no better an appellation than that of honeſt heathens, or give up even their nominal title to Chriſtianity, and honeſtly confeſs themſelves real Infidels.

Let them chuſe; but the time ſeems to be approaching when they muſt make their choice. The Chriſtian world is no longer to be deceived by theſe wolves in ſheep's cloathing; theſe believers in the name of a Saviour, whoſe power of ſalvation they openly deny.

There is ſo much diſingenuouſneſs and ſophiſtry in the practices of theſe minute philoſophers, that we are particularly ſorry to ſee them kept in countenance by the miſapplied abilities of [4] more ingenious and ingenuous writers.

It has, indeed, been publicly hinted, that this little work is a mere controverſial bubble, blown up to amuſe well-meaning Chriſtians, in order to impoſe on their credulity, and raiſe a ſneer at the expence of their ſimplicity and ſincerity.

For our own part, we have a better opinion of the author, than to give credit to ſuch a ſuggeſtion. His rank and reputation in life, as well as in literature, forbid our entertaining a thought ſo derogatory to his character, as a man of ſenſe, honour, and probity. For his Chriſtianity, it is true, we have hitherto given him credit; but, as he now profeſſes himſelf religiouſly ſolvent, we ſhall take the liberty of inveſtigating the terms of payment, by a particular and impartial review of his preſent performance.

[5]Before we begin this inveſtigation, however, it may not be amiſs to enter a caveat, againſt the reader's giving credit to the argument merely on the authority of the writer. The good faith of the latter, reſpects himſelf alone, the validity of his, reaſoning only reſpects the reader.

Should his work, he ſays, ever have the honour to be admitted into ſuch good company as the buſy or the idle, they will immediately determine it to be that of ſome enthuſiaſt or methodiſt, ſon beggar, or ſome madman. "I ſhall, therefore," ſays he, ‘beg leave to aſſure them, that the author is very far removed from all theſe characters: that he once perhaps believed as little as themſelves, * but [6] having ſome leiſure and more curioſity, he employed them both in reſolving a queſtion which ſeemed to him of ſome importance, —Whether Chriſtianity was really an impoſture founded on an abſurd, incredible, and obſolete fable, as many ſuppoſe it? Or whether it is, what it pretends to be, a revelation communicated to mankind by the interpoſition of ſupernatural power? On a candid enquiry, he ſoon found, that the firſt was an abſolute impoſſibility, and that its pretenſions to [7] the latter were founded on the moſt ſolid grounds: In the further purſuit of his examination, he perceived, at every ſtep, new lights ariſing, and ſome of the brighteſt from parts, of it the moſt obſcure, but productive of the cleareſt proofs, becauſe equally beyond the power of human artifice to invent, and human reaſon to diſcover.’

That the brighteſt lights, and cleareſt proofs Should ariſe from the moſt obſcure parts of ſcripture, is as ſingular as is the reaſon given for it; viz.‘becauſe they are beyond the power of human artifice to invent, and human reaſon to diſcover.’ But, may we not aſk here, how our author could aſſign ſo notable a reaſon, without having himſelf, carried human artifice and human reaſon to their utmoſt extent of diſcovery and invention? How elſe [8] ſhould he find this diſcovery and invention to be an abſolute impoſſibility? —If, indeed, he meant to infinuate that he hath carried the powers of inveſtigation ſo far as this; well and good! The improvements of art, the progreſs of ſcience, are at an end!— But we muſt have ſtronger proof of the fact than a mere ipſe-dixit, in a matter of ſo much importance.

That it is of conſequence to the reader to know, that the author is not an enthuſiaſt or a madman, we admit; but why we are told he is not a methodiſt or a beggar we do not readily conceive. Is any doctrine the leſs true becauſe it is taught by a methodiſt? Is any argument the leſs valid becauſe it is urged by a beggar? Or would the ſame doctrine be more true if maintained by a metropolitan? Or the ſame argument more valid if urged [9] by a Nabob?—Our Saviour and his apoſtles were men of eminence neither in church nor ſtate. They were neither high-prieſts nor lords of trade; neither men of credit nor men of fortune. Nor do we ſee any incongruity in a very credible man's being a methodiſt and a very ſound reaſoner's being as poor as Job.

It is more to the purpoſe that we are told, the author is not an enthuſiaſt or a madman. But who tells us this?—The very man himſelf.—And who ever took a man's own word for his not being in a ſtate of inſanity or intoxication?—"I drunk!" ſays drunken Caſſio in the play, ‘No, Sir, — This is my right hand and this is my left’—at the ſame time miſtaking one for the other.

We do not ſay, this is actually the caſe with our author; but, we ſay, [10] that his own aſſeveration merely cannot be admitted as evidence to the contrary. From his own confeſſion it appears, he is a convert from infidelity: now all converts are apt to run into extremes and from exceſs of incredulity to become too credulous. From doubting and diſbelieving what is probably true, they affect to believe what is palpably falſe. Nay, from denying almoſt every thing, they come really to believe almoſt any thing.

New Converts, we ſay, are apt, thro' inordinate zeal, to give into exceſs of credulity: a conduct, which, however pious, certainly borders on Enthuſiaſm. Indeed, we cannot help thinking our author betrays a little tincture of it in his paradoxical obſervation, reſpecting Divine Revelation in general; when, he ſays, all circumſtances conſidered, ‘if it were in every [11] part familiar to our underſtandings, and conſonant to our reaſon, we ſhould have great cauſe to ſuſpect its divine authority; and, therefore, had this revelation been leſs incomprehenſible, it would certainly have been more incredible.That is, in plainer terms, ‘If we underſtood it more, we ſhould be apt to believe it leſs.—Is not this on the plan of Credo quia impoſſibile eſt?[I believe it becauſe it is impoſſible.] And does our author give this, as a proof that he is in no degree, touched with enthuſiaſm or inſanity?—Credat Judoeus Appella!—We ſay not haud nos, becauſe Charity, though it feareth all things, hopeth all things.

‘To prove the truth of the Chriſtian religion’, ſays he, ‘we ſhould begin by ſhewing the internal marks of Divinity, which are ſtamped upon [12] it , becauſe on this the credibility of the prophecies and miracles in a great meaſure depends: for if we have once reaſon to be convinced that this religion is derived from a ſupernatural origin; prophecies and miracles will become ſo far from being incredible, that it will be highly probable, that a ſupernatural revelation ſhould be foretold, and inforced by ſupernatural means.’

Not that our author profeſſedly, means to depreciate the proofs of the truth of the Chriſtian religion ariſing from either prophecies or miracles. They both, have, or ought to have, he ſays, their proper weight. Let us weigh them then in his own ballance.

Prophecies, he ſays, are permanent miracles, whoſe authority is ſufficiently [13] confirmed by their completion, and are therefore ſolid proofs of the ſupernatural origin of a religion, whoſe truth they were intended to juſtify; ſuch are thoſe to be found in various parts of the ſcriptures relative to the coming of the Meſſiah, the deſtruction of Jeruſalem, and the unexampled ſtate in which the Jews have ever ſince continued, all ſo circumſtantially deſcriptive of the events, that they ſeem rather hiſtories of paſt, than predictions of future tranſactions; and whoever will ſeriouſly conſider the immenſe diſtance of time between ſome of them and the events which they foretell, the uninterrupted chain by which they are connected for many thouſand years, how exactly they correſpond with thoſe events, and how totally unapplicable they are to all others in the [14] hiſtory of mankind; I ſay, whoever conſiders theſe circumſtances, he will ſcarcely be perſuaded to believe, that they can be the productions of preceding artifice, or poſterior application, or can entertain the leaſt doubt of their being derived from ſupernatural inſpiration.’

Now, this is ſo far from being true, that we ourſelves, and we dare ſay many others, have ſeriouſly conſidered all theſe circumſtances; and, notwithſtanding the pains ingenious interpreters have taken to develope, conciliate and harmonize them, we do ſtill look upon them (taken in a mere rational view) to be ſo imperfectly aſcertained and ſo doubtfully applied that, judging of them merely from reaſon, they do not ſtrike us with any thing like that force of conviction which they appear to carry with our author.

[15]As to the miracles, recorded in the New Teſtament to have been performed by Chriſt and his apoſtles, he ſays, ‘they were certainly convincing proofs of their divine commiſſion to thoſe who ſaw them; and as they were ſeen by ſuch numbers, and are as well atteſted, as other hiſtorical facts, and above all, as they were wrought on ſo great and ſo wonderful an occaſion, they muſt ſtill be admitted as evidence of no inconſiderable force.’

Here again this writer either equivocates or ſins againſt the truth. The miracles performed by Chriſt and his Apoſtles were not certainly convincing proofs of their divine miſſion to many of thoſe who ſaw them. Witneſs our viour's dreadful denunciation to whole cities of impenitent unbelievers, to Choraizin, Bethſaida and Capernaum; [16] in which his mighty works had been diſplayed: unleſs, indeed, we are to ſuppoſe their impenitency not the conſequence of their unbelief; but that they were ſo much worſe than the devils, who believe and tremble, in that they believed and trembled not. But, with the Scribes and Phariſees; who, ſeeing him work miracles, immediately conſulted to deſtroy him and ſaid, he caſt out devils, through Beelzebub, the prince of devils; were thoſe miracles, we ſay, convincing proofs of his divine miſſion to them?

It even appears that our Saviour wrought his miracles and preached his doctrines, in the ſight and hearing of many who were never intended to be convinced by them. This our author himſelf obſerves, in accounting for that want of irreſiſtible evidence of their truth, by which they might poſſibly [17] have been enforced:’ quoting from the Evangeliſt Mark the following declaration of Jeſus to his deſciples. "To you it is given to know the myſtery of the kingdom of God; but unto them that are without, all theſe things are done in parables, that ſeeing they may ſee, and not perceive, and hearing they may hear and not underſtand; and left at any time they ſhould be converted, and their ſins ſhould be forgiven them."

What weight or degree of force, then, doth our author give to the evidence of miracles? Surely, no conſiderable weight, if he thinks, as he ſays that ‘they muſt now depend, for much of their credibility, on the truth of that religion whoſe credibility they were at firſt intended to ſupport.’

[18]How! are the religion and the miracles to be made reciprocally the criterion of each other? Are the pillars of ſupport, on which the truth of Chriſtianity hath ſo long reſted, to be now themſelves ſupported by the ſtrength and ſymmetry of its ſuperſtructure? This is making the whole hang by Geometry indeed!—

The internal marks of the divine origin of Chriſtianity, are to give a credibility to the prophecies and miracles; which they, in turn are to reflect back on Chriſtianity, to do credit to its divine origin. If this be not reaſoning in a circle, and beating round the buſh of argument to no end, we, at leaſt, ſee no end to ſuch a mode of argument. It is like that of the world's being ſupported by an elephant, the elephant by a tortoiſe, the [19] tortoiſe by another elephant, and the other elephant by another world!

In regard to the prediction of prophecies and the working of miracles, it may indeed be juſtly objected, as it has often been, that the completion of a prophecy or the performance of a miracle, taken merely as a fact, however wonderful, does not neceſſarily infer the interpoſition of a ſupernatural agent. *

[20]But, granting that it did, and that ſuch completion of the prophecies and performance of miracles are as well atteſted as other hiſtorical facts. Such atteſtation they may have; and yet, if they have no more, they cannot lay claim to more than a mere moral probability of truth.

The difficulty of aſcertaining the truth of probable and ordinary facts, which happen daily almoſt under our immediate obſervation, is ſo notorious, that it is a ſufficient caution againſt the putting implicit faith in the hiſtorical [21] relation of facts improbable and extraordinary, which are ſaid to have happened at ſuch a conſiderable diſtance of time and place.

The weight or degree of force, therefore, which our author gives to the evidence of prophecies, muſt, notwithſtanding he ſtiles it not inconſiderable, be little worth conſideration.

The utmoſt that he propoſes indeed, is, a high probability; and even this depends on our having other reaſons to be convinced that Chriſtianity is of divine origin. A foundation itſelf far ſhort of the neceſſary proof in ſome caſes; for men may often have reaſon to believe what is, nevertheleſs, not actually true.

Even the internal evidence, this writer attempts to inveſtigate, appears hence to amount to a mere probability; ſo that, by adding this evidence to [22] thoſe of both prophecies and miracles, he is at beſt only adding one probability to another.

SECT. II.

On the definition of the ſubject, and diviſion of the argument into four propoſitions.—The firſt "That there is now extant a book entitled the New Teſtament," ſhewn to be futile and frivolous.

‘WHAT pure Chriſtianity is (ſays this writer) diveſted of all its ornaments, appendages, and corruption, I pretend not to ſay; but what it is not, will venture to affirm, which is, that it is not the offspring of fraud or fiction: that however fraud and fiction may have grown up with it, yet it never could have been grafted [23] on the ſame ſtock, nor planted by the ſame hand.’

This our author undertakes to ſhew by ſtating the following plain and, as he ſtiles them, undeniable * propoſitions.

Firſt, that there is now extant a book intitled the New Teſtament.

Secondly, that from this book may be extracted a ſyſtem of religion intirely new, both with regard to the object and the doctrines, not only infinitely ſuperior to, but unlike every thing, which had ever before entered into the mind of man.

Thirdly, that from this book may likewiſe be collected a ſyſtem of ethics, in which every moral precept founded on reaſon is carried to a higher degree of purity and perfection, than in any other of the [24] wiſeſt philoſophers of preceding ages; every moral precept founded on falſe principles is totally omitted, and many new precepts added peculiarly correſponding with the new object of this religion.

Laſtly, that ſuch a ſyſtem of religion and morality could not poſſibly have been the work of any man, or ſet of men; much leſs of thoſe obſcure, ignorant, and illiterate perſons, who actually did diſcover, and publiſh it to the world; and that therefore it muſt undoubtedly have been effected by the interpoſition of divine power, that is, that it muſt derive its origin from God.

Such is this writer's plan, as exhibited by himſelf; on which we beg leave firſt to obſerve that, the terms, in which it is laid down, are too vague and the ſtyle too metaphorical for a [25] logical eſſay; the form of which it affects to aſſume.

One would imagine that a caſuiſt, ſo rigid as to think it neceſſary to offer ‘the mere exiſtence of a book entitled the New Teſtament’, as a formal propoſition, would have been ſtrict enough to ſet out with as formal a definition of the enthymeme, or object itſelf in contemplation.

The deſign in view is profeſſedly ‘to prove the truth of the Chriſtian religion,’ and yet ‘what pure chriſtianity is, diveſted of all its ornaments, appendages and corruption, the writer will not pretend to ſay.’

Does our logician then predicate nothing of his ſubject?—Yes, though he will not pretend to ſay what pure chriſtianity is, he will venture to affirm what it is not. His affirmation, how ever is not even a negative predicate [26] of its eſſence or property, but an aſſertion relative to its derivation ‘it is not the offspring of fraud or fiction.’‘Fraud and fiction may have grown up with it, yet it never could have been grafted upon the ſame ſtock, nor planted by the ſame hand.’—Theſe metaphorical expreſſions, we ſay, are ill adapted to the ſubject in hand; which requires ſimple, unequivocating and preciſe terms, not liable to miſconception or miſtake. We cannot help thinking it, alſo, extremely illogical to undertake to prove what any thing may be imputed to, as its cauſe, without being able to give ſome definition of the thing itſelf, as an effect. To affirm poſitively what and ſhew whence it is not derived, without pretending to know what IT is, is certainly not a very philoſophical, [27] however popular, mode it may be of theological controverſy.

But to accommodate our Review to the view itſelf. As to this propoſition the firſt, very little, as the author hints, need be ſaid. It is a plain fact, which cannot be denied, ſuch writings do now exiſt: the leſs need, therefore, as before obſerved, to give it the formality of a propoſition, either to be proved or granted; we paſs it over therefore as futile and frivolous.

SECT. III.

On the ſecond propoſition, viz. ‘That from this book may be extracted a ſyſtem of religion entirely new, both with regard to the object and the doctrines, not only ſuperiour to, but unlike every thing, which had ever before entered the [28] human mind,’—This propoſition ſhewn to be very obſcurely illuſtrated, inconſiſtently explained, and even of little conſequence to the general argument, were it capable of being proved.

‘MY ſecond propoſition, ſays our author, is not quite ſo ſimple, but, I think, not leſs undeniable than the former, and is this: that from this book may be extracted a ſyſtem of religion entirely new, both with regard to the object, and the doctrines, not only infinitely ſuperior to, but totally unlike every thing, which had ever before entered into the mind of man: I ſay extracted, becauſe all the doctrines of this religion having been delivered at various times, and on various occaſions, and here only hiſtorically recorded, no uniform or regular ſyſtem of theology is here [29] to be found; and better perhaps it had been, if leſs labour had been employed by the learned, to bend and twiſt theſe divine materials into the poliſhed forms of human ſyſtems, to which they never will ſubmit, and for which they were never intended by their Great Author. Why he choſe not to leave any ſuch behind him we know not, but it might poſſibly be, becauſe he knew that the imperfection of man was incapable of receiving ſuch a ſyſtem, and that we are more properly, and more ſafely conducted by the diſtant, and ſcattered rays, than by the too powerful ſunſhine of divine illumination.’

Our author expreſſes himſelf here, alſo, in terms very vague and equivovocal. ‘A ſyſtem of religion, he ſays, may be extracted from the New [30] Teſtament infinitely ſuperior [ſuperior in what reſpect?] to every other; and yet no uniform or regular ſyſtem of theology is to be found there: and it had been better perhaps if the learned had never attempted to form ſuch ſyſtems; being probably incompatible with the divine oeconomy reſpecting mankind.’

Here is a probability ſuggeſted that is very high indeed! He might almoſt as well have ſuggeſted that the divine oeconomy itſelf is not ſyſtematical.

Equally paradoxical with a former illuſtration * alſo is the preſent. As, before, the brighteſt lights aroſe from the moſt obſcure parts of revelation, ſo here we are to be more ſafely conducted in the dark, than we ſhould be in the brighteſt ſunſhine of divine illumination!

[31]There is likewiſe a palpable inconſiſtency on the very face of the propoſition itſelf. How can a ſyſtem of religion be extracted from a book, in which no ſuch ſyſtem is to be found? —Or means our author only that the form of that ſyſtem is not to be found there? But, what of that? Every doctrine that is ſound muſt be ſyſtematical, whether the declaration or explication of it be formally ſo or not.

It is cuſtomary for writers, either from literary incapacity, or to ſave themſelves trouble, to deliver their ſentiments, however conſiſtent and connected with each other, in a looſe, unconnected and deſultory manner. Hiſtorians * in particular, muſt, from [32] the very nature of their compoſition, blend doctrinal precepts with practical narration. But, if the precepts, thus interſperſed in the courſe of the narrative, are inconſiſtent in themſelves, or incompatible with each other, they can neither be truly doctrinal nor doctrinally true.

Men may write as looſely and deſultorily as they pleaſe; but, if they think juſtly they muſt think conſiſtently, and, of courſe, ſyſtematically. Nor do we ſee the leaſt reaſon (except that of our author's deſire to accommodate things, at any rate, to his own ſyſtem) for ſuppoſing that mankind are, through any imperfection more incapable of receiving doctrines in a ſyſtematical form than they are of receiving them in no form at all. As good a logician and as good a Chriſtian as our author, [33] tells us ‘the beſt way to learn any ſcience is to begin with a ſyſtem. *

As to this author's metaphorical alluſion to the rays of light, it elucidates nothing. That a moderate portion of light is better adapted to weak optics than an exceſſive blaze of it, is undoubtedly true; but the ſuppoſition, thence deduced, of our ſeeing better by means of diſtant, ſcattered rays, than by a regular emanation, is a rhetorical flouriſh altogether inconſiſtent with ſound logic and true philoſophy.

In regard to the bending and twiſting of the materials of divine revelation ‘into the poliſhed forms of human ſyſtems, to which they never will ſubmit;’ the attempt ſo to twiſt and bend them is certainly an unjuſtifiable violence, which it might have been better the learned had never made: but this is no reaſonable objection [34] to their forming a plain, unpoliſhed ſyſtem; ſuch as is really contained in the Scriptures.

Whether any ſyſtem of ſcriptural thinking already reduced to form in writing, be in all reſpects unexceptionable, it is not our buſineſs here to enquire. But if there be not, it is in this particular we trace the ſource of imperfection: it lies in the incapacity of men to form ſuch a divine ſyſtem, to connect detached and deſultory doctrines into a regular and conſiſtent theory; and not to their incapacity of comprehending ſuch a theory, had it been formally digeſted and in ſuch form firſt given them.

In reſpect to the total novelty and unheard of ſingularity of the doctrines of revelation when firſt promulgated, our author affirms that thoſe doctrines are equally ‘new with the object; and [35] contain ideas of God, and of man, of the preſent, and of a future life; and of the relations which all theſe bear to each other totally unheard of and quite diſſimilar from any which had ever been thought on, previous to its publication.’

"But," continues he, ‘Whether theſe wonderful doctrines (which he enumerates) are worthy of our belief muſt depend on the opinion, which we entertain of the authority of thoſe who publiſhed them to the world; certain it is, that they are all ſo far removed from every tract of the human imagination, that it ſeems equally impoſſible, that they ſhould ever have been derived from the knowledge or artifice of man.’

Now to us there ſeems no ſuch impoſſibility. Even granting, in oppoſition to the Son of Wiſdom, that there [36] is any thing new under the ſun, and that there is nothing in the tract entitled "Chriſtianity as old as the creation;" admitting, we ſay, that the Chriſtian religion, when promulgated by our Saviour, was as new and ſtrange as our author repreſents it, we think little ſtreſs of argument is to be laid upon ſuch ſingularity or novelty.

We ſhall not go about to enquire whether the extravagancies of the Pagan Mythology, many of which certainly bear ſome reſemblance to the ſublime myſteries of Chriſtianity, were of later or earlier origin. Yet, wonderful as are the latter and firmly as we believe them derived from God, being in their execution ſuperior to human comprehenſion, and totally incompatible with human reaſon; we do not ſee any thing, merely in the idea or deſign of the ſublimeſt of them, ſo far ſuperior to the [37] powers of human invention or diſſimular to its ſublimer conceptions. On the contrary, man hath made to himſelf ſo many inventions, human genius hath ſoared ſo high into the region of impoſſibilities, that nothing which can come within the aſſociation of the moſt incongruous ideas, can in our opinion be juſtly ſaid to exceed the artifice of the human imagination *.

[38]To attend, however, a little to the author's mode of proving his propoſition. "To ſay the truth, ſays he, before the appearance of Chriſtianity there exiſted nothing like religion on the face of the earth; the Jewiſh only excepted: all other nations were immerſed in the groſſeſt idolatry."

‘At this time Chriſtianity broke forth from the eaſt like a riſing ſun, and diſpelled this univerſal darkneſs, which obſcured every part of the globe, and even at this day prevails in all thoſe remoter regions, to which its ſalutary influence has not as yet extended. From all thoſe which it has reached, it has, notwithſtanding its corruptions, baniſhed all thoſe enormities, and introduced a more rational [39] tional devotion, and purer morals: It has taught men the unity, and attributes of the ſupreme Being, the remiſſion of ſins, the reſurrection of the dead, life everlaſting, and the kingdom of heaven; doctrines as inconceivable to the wiſeſt of mankind antecedent to its appearance, as the Newtonian ſyſtem is at this day to the moſt ignorant tribes of ſavages in the wilds of America: doctrines, which human reaſon never could have diſcovered, but, which when diſcovered, coincide with, and are confirmed by it; and which, though beyond the reach of all the learning and penetration of Plato, Ariſtotle, and Cicero, are now clearly laid open to the eye of every peaſant and mechanic with the Bible in his hand. Theſe are all plain facts too glaring [40] to be contradicted, and thereſore, whatever we may think of the authority of theſe books, the relations which they contain, or the inſpiration of their authors, of theſe facts, no man, who has eyes to read, or ears to hear, can entertain a doubt; becauſe there are the books, and in them there is this religion.’

Doubtleſs all this is well ſaid. It is pity it is not all quite ſo true. But the truth is, that theſe plain facts which our author ſays are too glaring to be contradicted, are glaringly contradicted every day.—It is not only denied that the doctrines of the Chriſtian faith coincide with, and are confirmed, by reaſon, but it is denied by many that the devotion actually introduced by Chriſtianity is more rational or the morals purer than thoſe profeſſed and practiſed by ſome people [41] who never heard of Chriſtianity *.

[42]We urge nothing againſt the purity of thoſe morals now in practice throughout Chriſtendom, nor compare them with thoſe of other nations now exiſting, who have not embraced Chriſtianity. —The compariſon might be looked upon as too ſevere a libel on the good Chriſtians of the age! But might not an able caſuiſt, and as good a rhetorician as our author, as plauſibly declaim in favour of the conquerors, legiſlators, and moraliſts of unenlightened paganiſm, to the ſhame of the immorality of profeſſed Chriſtians.

Might he not exhibit a picture of horror, faithfully drawn from the hiſtory of Chriſtianity and the propagation of our holy religion, ſtill more ſhocking to humanity, and contradictory to its divine precepts, than is afforded [43] from that of the moſt horrid aera in the annals of heatheniſm?

Hath the ſavage fury of hoſtile barbarians, the avarice of inſatiable tyrants, or the boundleſs ambition of heathen conquerors been the cauſe of more blood-ſhed or greater cruelty, than the zeal of religious fanatics, the phrenzy of pious enthuſiaſm, or the pride and avarice of Chriſtian prieſts?

Might not an artful declaimer, we ſay, very reaſonably pretend that a religion, whoſe profeſſors have been guilty of ſo much wickedneſs, could not poſſibly merit the epithets of divine or, holy? Would he not rather derive it from Hell, as its moſt natural ſource, than from Heaven, the declared fountain of mercy and goodneſs?

Declamations of this kind, prove nothing.

[44]We ſhall proceed, therefore, to the conſideration of the author's third propoſition; leaving that of his farther proof of the ſecond, till we come to his ſolving of objections; where indeed, much of it would have with more propriety found a place.

SECT. IV.

On the third propoſition. ‘That from this book may likewiſe be collected a ſyſtem of Ethicks, in which every moral precept, founded on reaſon, is carried to a higher degree of perfection, than in any other of the wiſeſt philoſophers of preceding ages; every precept founded on falſe principles is totally omitted, and many new precepts added, peculiarly correſponding with the new object of this [45] religion.’—This propoſition ſhewn to be very exceptionably illuſtrated; affording at beſt rather a proof of the ſublimity and purity of Chriſtian morals, and of the advantages, rather than the truth, of the Chriſtian Religion.

IN proof of this third propoſition, our author begins by making a diſtinction, between the moral precepts of Chriſtianity (founded, as he obſerves, on reaſon) and thoſe precepts, which, being founded on falſe principles, inculcate in fact no virtues at all. Under the former he includes piety to God, benevolence to man, juſtice, charity, temperance and ſobriety, with all thoſe which prohibit the contrary vices, and all that debaſe our natures, and, by mutual injuries, introduce univerſal diſorder, and conſequently univerſal miſery. Under the latter he [46] claſſes thoſe fictitious virtues, which, he ſays, produce no ſalutary effects; and however admired, are no virtues at all, ſuch as Valour, Patriotiſm and Friendſhip.

The Monthly Reviewers, in their critique on our author's work, obſerve, on this diſtinction, that they ‘never conceived that the virtues of friendſhip, fortitude, and patriotiſm, do not form a part of the moral ſyſtem of the goſpel: much leſs could they have urged the want of theſe virtues as a peculiar recommendation of its excellence. They are conſpicuouſly illuſtrated," ſay they, "in the character of its author, and it would be eaſy to produce ſtriking inſtances in which his courage and friendſhip, and concern for the welfare of his country, were actually diſplayed. But this is needleſs; the [47] advocates of the Chriſtian religion, in anſwer to Lord Shafteſbury and others, have ſufficiently vindicated it in this reſpect. Theſe are unqueſtionably virtues of conſiderable importance; and ſo far as they do not interfere with the general principles of benevolence which Chriſtianity inculcates, they conſtitute a part of Chriſtian morality.’

It is well for theſe diſtinguiſhing critics that they bring in the ſalvo, at the at the cloſe of the above paragraph, reſpecting theſe popular virtues not interfering with the general principles of benevolence, which Chriſtianity inculcates.

This is the very point in queſtion; and, however ſucceſsfully the advocates for Chriſtianity may have combated Shaftſbury and others, there is ſome [48] room ſtill left for oppoſing our author's argument.

Valour, ſays he, for inſtance, or active courage, is for the moſt part conſtitutional, and therefore can have no more claim to moral merit, than wit, beauty, health, ſtrength, or any other endowment of the mind or body; and ſo far is it from producing any ſalutary effects by introducing peace, order, or happineſs into ſociety, that it is the uſual perpetrator of all the violences, which from retaliated injuries diſtract the world with bloodſhed and devaſtation. It is the engine by which the ſtrong are enabled to plunder the weak, the proud to trample upon the humble, and the guilty to oppreſs the innocent; it is the chief inſtrument which Ambition employs in her unjuſt purſuits of wealth [49] and power, and is therefore ſo much extolled by her votaries: it was indeed congenial with the religion of pagans, whoſe gods were for the moſt part made out of deceaſed heroes, exalted to heaven as a reward for the miſchiefs which they had perpetrated upon earth, and therefore with them this was the firſt of virtues, and had even engroſſed that denomination to itſelf; but, whatever merit it may have aſſumed among pagans, with Chriſtians it can pretend to none.’

There would be ſome argument in all this, if, becauſe valour be the occaſional inſtrument of oppreſſion, it be alſo the neceſſary cauſe of it; or if men were always miſchievous in proportion as they are bold. But we preſume that this is not the caſe; cruelty being characteriſtic of cowardice, and benevolence [50] of bravery. Perſonal valour may, therefore, be juſtly eſteemed to have ſome moral merit; although, as it is allowed to be in a great degree conſtitutional, it is certainly no farther to be deemed a moral virtue, than it is to be perſonally acquired. For a virtue, notwithſtanding the plauſibility of our author's reaſoning, we preſume it may juſtly be ſtiled.

Our author, indeed, ſays, that few, or none are the occaſions in which Chriſtians are permitted to exert their courage or valour. "They are ſo far," ſays he, ‘from being allowed to inflict evil, that they are forbid even to reſiſt it; they are ſo far from being encouraged to revenge injuries, that one of their firſt duties is to forgive them; ſo far from being incited to deſtroy their enemies, that they are commanded [51] to love them, and to ſerve them to the utmoſt of their power.’

Surely our author here miſtakes the nature of that evil which Chriſtians are forbid to reſiſt. It certainly is not the moral evil of injuſtice! Admitting they are not to revenge injuries, ſurely they may exert their valour to prevent the execution of them! If not, a good Chriſtian muſt not reſiſt the violence of a robber, a houſe-breaker, or a murderer!

But, granting that individuals, anxious to copy after Chriſtian perfection, are juſtified in thus ſubmitting to (though it be in fact conniving at) the commiſſion of acts of injuſtice; valour may be yet a neceſſary virtue to the ſupport and defence of Chriſtian communities; as we ſhail ſhew, when we come to treat of Patriotiſm.

But though our author will not admit [52] active courage to be a real virtue; paſſive courage, or fortitude, he allows to be conſiſtent with the pureſt Chriſtian morality.

‘Paſſive courage, ſays he, is frequently, and properly inculcated by this meek and ſuffering religion, under the titles of patience and reſignation: a real and ſubſtantial virtue this, and a direct contraſt to the former; for paſſive courage ariſes from the nobleſt diſpoſitions of the human mind, from a contempt of misfortunes, pain, and death, and a confidence in the protection of the Atmighty; active from the meaneſt: from paſſion, vanity, and ſelf-dependence: paſſive courage is derived from a zeal for truth, and a perſeveranee in duty; active is the offspring of pride and revenge, and the parent of cruelty and injuſtice: in ſhort; [53] paſſive courage is the reſolutiot of a philoſopher, active the ferocity of a ſavage. Nor is this more incompatible with the precepts, than with the object of this religion, which is the attainment of the kingdom of heaven; for valour is not that ſort of violence, by which that kingdom is to be taken; nor are the turbulent ſpirits of heroes and conquerors admiſſibleinto thoſe regions of peace, ſubordination, and tranquility.’

This is, on the whole, well ſaid; though we cannot agree that valour or active courage is always the offſpring of pride and revenge, or the parent of cruelty and injuſtice.—Paſſivecourage may, alſo, be juſtly ſtiled the reſolution of a philoſopher and yet active courage be very unjuſtly called the ferocity of a ſavage. Not but that the activity of [54] ſome men is fierce and ferocious, as the paſſiveneſs of others is tame and irreſolute.

On Patriotiſm our author declaims thus:

Patriotiſm, that celebrated virtue ſo much practiſed in ancient, and ſo much profeſſed in modern times, that virtue, which ſo long preſerved the liberties of Greece, and exalted Rome to the empire of the world: this celebrated virtue, I ſay, muſt alſo be excluded; becauſe it, not only falls ſhort of, but directly counteracts, the extenſive benevolence of this religion. A Chriſtian is of no country, he is a citizen of the world; and his neighbours and countrymen are the inhabitants of the remoteſt regions, whenever their diſtreſſes demand his friendly aſſiſtance: Chriſtianity commands [55] us to love all mankind, Patriotiſm to oppreſs all other countries to advance the imaginary proſperity of our own: Chriſtianity enjoins to imitate the univerſal benevolence of our Creator, who pours forth his bleſſings on every nation upon earth; Patriotiſm to copy the mean partiality of an Engliſh pariſh-officer, who thinks injuſtice and cruelty meritorious, whenever they promote the intereſts of his own inconſiderable village. This has ever been a favourite virtue with mankind, becauſe it conceals ſelf-intereſt under the maſk of public ſpirit, not only from others, but even from them ſelves, and gives a licence to inflict wrongs and injuries mot only with impunity, but with applauſe; but it is ſo diametrically oppoſite to the great, characteriſtic of this inſtitution, [56] that it never could have been admitted into the liſt of Chriſtian virtues.’

Without recurring to what other writers may have advanced in favour of the Chriſtianity of patriotiſm, we ſhall offer a few reaſons, that ſuggeſt themſelves to us, to ſhew that the love of one's ſelf and one's country, is not ſo inconſiſtent with that univerſal philanthropy inculcated by Chriſtianity, as this writer here ſuppoſes.

True ſelf-love and ſocial, fays the Poet, are one and the ſame.

Self-love But ſerves the virtuous mind to wake,
As the ſmall pebble ſtirs the peaceful lake,
Still from the central point the circle ſpreads;
And wider grows as ſtill the next ſucceeds;
Thus father, brother, friend we firſt embrace,
Our country next, next all the human race *

[57]What philoſophy there is in this poetry will appear in the courſe of our argument.

To the judicious omiſſion of theſe falſe virtues, Valour, Patriotiſm, and Friendſhip, our author ſays, ‘We may add that remarkable ſilence, which the Chriſtian legiſlator every where preſerves on ſubjects, eſteemed by all others of the higheſt impotance, civil government, rational policy, and the rights of war and peace; of theſe he has not taken the leaſt notice; probably for this plain reaſon, becauſe it would have been [58] impoſſible to have formed any explicit regulations concerning them, which muſt not have been inconſiſtent with the purity of his religion, or with the practical obſervance of ſuch imperfect creatures as men ruling over and contending with each other: For inſtance, had he abſolutely forbid all reſiſtance to the reigning powers, he had conſtituted a plan of deſpotiſm, and made men ſlaves; had he allowed it, he muſt have authoriſed diſobedience and made them rebels: had he in direct terms prohibited all war, he muſt have left his followers for ever an eaſy prey to every infidel invader; had he permitted it, he muſt have licenſed all that rapine and murder, with which it is unavoidably attended.’

Now, not to dwell on the impropriety in the laſt ſentence of charging, the [59] power, permitting war, with the licenſing of all the rapine and murder attending it; we object to the matter of fact, as ſtated in the whole paſſage.

Without inſiſting, with the Monthly Reviewers, that the character of our Saviour was conſpicuouſly illuſtrious as a patriot, we may ſafely deny that he has not taken the leaſt notice of matters of patriotiſm and civil polity, as our author aſſerts. His reply to the Phariſees, who tempted him on the ſubject of paying tribute—‘Give unto Caeſar the things that are Caeſar's, and to God the things that are of God’—is an irrefragable inſtance of the diſtinction he made between religion and politics.

Civil government, national policy, and the rights of war and peace, were ſubjects, indeed, that appear not to have come directly under his deciſion. [60] Had they ſo done, we have no reaſon to think our Saviour lay under any kind of impoſſibility, to give a very explicit and ſatisfactory anſwer.

If he was not explicit, however, in precept, reſpecting the authority of civil government, it muſt be admitted he was illuſtriouſly ſo in example, by his ſubmiſſion to the forms of juſticiary trial and juridical condemnation; which ſurely were not neceſſary to his death, if, no ſuch example was intended to be given, or precept thence to be inculcated!

But had our Saviour himſelf given neither precept nor example on this head; his inſpired Apoſtles, Peter and Paul, have more than ſufficiently done it; by enjoining their diſciples to the moſt unreſerved obedience to the municipal laws and civil magiſtracy [61] of their times; and thence inſtructing Chriſtians in general to a ſimilar obedience to the reigning powers that be in all times.

In this, however, they have made men no farther ſlaves in this world than they are Chriſtians, whoſe faith is fixed and whoſe hopes are centered in another. So far as they are ſtill men, and bound to take part in the concerns of this world, while on their journey to the next, they are at liberty to reſiſt oppreſſion, and combat injuſtice, whether that of a domeſtic tyrant or a foreign invader.

"Had my kingdom," ſays our Saviour to Pilate, ‘been of this world, then would my ſervants have fought, that I ſhould not be delivered to the Jews.’

Granting that Chriſtians, therefore, are not to propagate their religion by [62] force of arms, or to fight for Chriſt's kingdom, which is not of this world, they are not forbidden to fight for their own ſhare in the kingdoms, which are of this world.—If men may not fight for their religion, they may fight for their liberty and property; and, in our opinion, they act the part of brave men and good Chriſtians in ſo doing.

And yet our author ſays, ‘If Chriſtian nations were nations of Chriſtians, all war would be impoſſible and unknown among them, and valour could be neither of uſe or eſtimation, and therefore could never have a place in the catalogue of Chriſtian virtues; being irreconcileable with all its precepts.’

Of a piece with this reaſoning of our author's is that of Rouſſeau, in his Social compact; where he inſinuates that [63] a Chriſtian ſoldier is a kind of a contradiction in terms. But we have here given our reaſons for thinking otherwiſe; from which it follows, that even active valour appears to be a real, and not a fictitious, virtue.

For if a good Chriſtian be a good patriot, he muſt be, ready to act, as well as ſuffer, for his country. He muſt at leaſt be ready to fight, if neceſſary, in its defence; and valour is as requiſite to repel an invader as it is to invade the foe. There is as much active courage required in defence as in offence; and hence, as loyalty and patriotiſm are the virtues of a good ſubject, valour muſt have ſome merit even with Chriſtians as a moral virtue, at leaſt active courage muſt be as much a moral virtue as paſſive .

[64]But be that as it may, our author certainly falls into an error, in ſuppoſing it neceſſary for a good Chriſtian to renounce his country to become a citizen of the world, a mere coſmopolite!

[65]In regard to the virtue of Friendſhip, our author, either wilfully or negligently impoſes a change of terms upon us; reaſoning very inaccurately on the ſubject.—

"Friendſhip," ſays he, ‘likewiſe, although more congenial to the principles of Chriſtianity ariſing from more tender and amiable diſpoſitions, could never gain admittance amongſt her benevolent precepts for the ſame reaſon; becauſe it is too narrow and confined, and appropriates that benevolence to a ſingle object, which is here commanded to be extended over all: Where friendſhips ariſe from ſimilarity of ſentiments, and diſintereſted affections, they are advantageous, agreeable, and innocent, but have little pretenſions to merit;’ for it is juſtly obſerved, ‘if ye love them, which love you, [66] what thanks have ye? for ſinners love thoſe, that love them. But if they are formed from alliances in parties, factions, and intereſts, or from a participation of vices, the uſual parents of what are called friendſhips among mankind, they are then both miſchievous and criminal, and conſequently forbidden, but in their utmoſt purity deſerve no recommendation from this religion.’

In reply, however, to what is here advanced on friendſhip and the text quoted from Luke in ſupport of it, may be oppoſed the precept inculcated in John xiii. 34. quoted alſo by our author in favour of that Chriſtian virtue Charity: ‘A new commandment I give unto you, That ye love one another; as I have loved you, that ye alſo love one another; by this ſhall all [67] men know that ye are my diſciples, if ye have love one to another.’— Here we ſee that brotherly-love, or mutual friendſhip (which in the former text is repreſented as of little merit, being the virtue of ſinners) is made the teſt, or criterion of chriſtianity, the virtue one ſhould imaging characteriſtic of ſaints.

Chriſtian charity, in its utmoſt extent is certainly ſomething more than mere friendſhip; but we cannot help thinking that reciprocal affection, or, as our author ſtiles it, that "benevolent diſpoſition" which is here made the characteriſtic of Chriſt's diſciples, the teſt of their obedience and the mark by which they are to be diſtinguiſhed, is too near a-kin to friendſhip, to admit of friendſhip's being with propriety diſcarded as a fictitious virtue, or as no virtue at all.

[68]Our author, indeed, is far from reaſoning accurately on this head. For, after depreciating, as above, the virtue ſpecified, he tells us, he ‘means not by this to paſs any cenſure on the principles of valour, patriotiſm and honour.’

The attentive reader will here obſerve that, in this reſpecification of the ſpurious or falſe virtues, our author hath ſubſtituted the term honour inſtead of friendſhip. The reaſon is, that, having changed his ground, he found that more pertinent to the ſtate of his argument. Of that phantom modern honour, indeed, to which the moſt ſolid and ſubſtantial friendſhips are ſometimes ſacrificed, he may ſay juſtly, that ‘a man, who makes this his ruling principle, however virtuous he may be, cannot be a Chriſtian, becauſe [69] he erects a ſtandard of duty, and deliberally adheres to it, diametrically oppoſite to the whole tenor of that religion.’

That the laws of ſuch honour are incompatible with the rules of Chriſtianity we readily allow, though we cannot allow that the ſirmeſt friendſhip for an individual is incompatible with that univerſal philanthropy, which Chriſtianity inculcates for all mankind. Nay, we do not hold patriotiſm or even valour to be ſuch mere heatheniſh virtues as our author would repreſent them.

"They may be uſeful," ſayshe, ‘and perhaps neceſſary, in the commerce and buſineſs of the preſent turbulent and imperfect ſtate; and thoſe who are actuated by them may be virtuous, honeſt, and even religious men: all that I aſſert is, that they cannot be chriſtians.—And yet, in a ſubſequent [70] page of the work, we are expreſsly told that in the preſent ſtate as enlightened by the goſpel, ‘if we will not accept of chriſtianity, we can have no religion at all’. *

After degrading the falſe virtues of paganiſm, he proceeds to enhance the true virtues of chriſtianity. Theſe are poverty of ſpirit—Chriſtian charity—Penitence—Faith—Self-abaſement and detachment from the world.—

Admitting all that is ſaid in favour of moſt of theſe, as being founded on ſcriptural authority, the virtue of faith, that which is the moſt immediately connected with the evidence of the divine origin of chriſtianity demands our more particular attention.

"Faith," ſays our author, ‘is another moral duty injoined by this [71] inſtitution, of a ſpecies ſo new, that the philoſophers of antiquity had no words expreſſive of this idea, nor nor any ſuch idea to be expreſſed; for the word [...] or fides, which we tranſlate faith, was never uſed by any pagan writer in a ſenſe the leaſt ſimilar to that, to which it is applied in the New Teſtament: where in general it ſignifies an humble, teachable, and candid diſpoſition, a truſt in God, and confidence in his promiſes; when applied particularly to Chriſtianity, it means no more than a belief of this ſingle propoſition, that Chriſt was the ſon of God, that is in the language of thoſe writings, the Meſſiah, who was foretold by the prophets, and expected by the Jews; who was ſent by God into the world to preach righteouſneſs, judgment, and everlaſting life, and [72] to die as an atonement for the ſins of mankind. This was all that Chriſt required to be believed by thoſe who were willing to become his diſciples: he, who does not believe this, is not a Chriſtian, and he who does, believes the whole that is eſſential to his profeſſion, and all that is properly comprehended under the name of faith.’

We ſee here that, though our author ſcrupled at firſt ſetting out, to ſay what pure Chriſtianity was, he has reduced it, in this illuſtration of Faith, to what he calls a ſingle propoſition. But he cannot be ignorant that this ſingle propoſition is ſufficiently multifarious and complicated.

He cannot be ignorant that the expreſſion, Son of God, is differently underſtood by different interpreters; that ſome think it conſiſtent with his being [73] a mere man, while others think it exalts him to an equality with the Deity.

He cannot be ignorant that his atonement by death for the ſins of mankind, is controverted and even boldly denied by a conſiderable number of profeſſed Chriſtians.

To what purpoſe is it that our author tells us this propoſition is the eſſential creed of a Chriſtian, if other writers of equal authority tell us otherwiſe. Nay to what purpoſe is it, we are told that the ſame propoſition is to be found in the Scriptures, whoſe truth we admit, if they are liable to various interpretation?

It is in vain to ſay, that "when we are once convinced the Scriptures are of divine original, we have nothing more to do but implicitly believe what they tell us." How many thouſand volumes of controverſy have [74] there not been written to determine what they do tell us! And is it not ſtill left as indeterminate as ever.

Granting that implicit faith in divine revelation be our duty; by what means are we to trace from the hiſtory of that revelation, what is really revealed? Surely it muſt be by the ſame means as thoſe by which we become convinced of its divine original! And if reaſon be competent in the one caſe, it ſurely muſt be ſo in the other.

At the ſame time, if the operation of grace be neceſſary to impreſs the true ſenſe and meaning of the ſcriptures on the mind and heart of the unconverted ſinner, why ſhould it be leſs neceſſary, as it is evidently equally expedient, to convince him of the divine origin of revelation in general?— We firmly believe that, admitting the reality of our author's converſion to [75] Chriſtianity (of which we have no reaſon to doubt) he is much more indebted for it to the efficacious and irreſiſtible impulſe of divine grace, than to all the pains he has taken, and the ingenuity he has exerted, in inveſtigating the moral proofs of its divine inſtitution.

But we ſhall in this ſection confine ourſelves, in conformity to the author's method, to the conſideration of Faith merely as a Chriſtian duty. The objects of that Faith, with the nature of it, we ſhall diſcuſs more particularly hereafter.

"Faith," ſays he, ‘cannot be altogether void of moral merit, (as ſome would repreſent it) becauſe it is in a degree voluntary; for daily experience ſhews us, that men not only pretend to, but actually do believe, and diſbelieve almoſt any [76] propoſitions, which beſt ſuits their intereſts, or inclinations, and unfeignedly change their ſincere opinions with their ſituations and circumſtances. For we have power over the mind's eye, as well as over the body's, to ſhut it againſt the ſtrongeſt rays of truth and religion, whenever they become painful to us, and to open it again to the faint glimmerings of ſcepticiſm and infidelity’ when we ‘love darkneſs rather than light, becauſe our deeds are evil.’ And this, I think, ſufficiently ‘refutes all objections to the moral nature of faith, drawn from the ſuppoſition or its being quite involuntary and neceſſarily dependent on the degree of evidence, which is offered to our underſtandings.’

We cannot pretend to call in queſtion the ductility of our author's believing [77] organs, or the power he has over them to enable him to believe what he pleaſes. But, we muſt own, with regard to ourſelves, we ſhould be happy to be poſſeſſed of ſuch power of credulity; ſo as to be able to believe every thing to be true which beſt ſuits our intereſts, inclinations, and circumſtances; even though we ſhould thence be ſubject to be ſometimes diſagreeably undeceived. We ſhould get rid of many irkſome reflections and enjoy many a happy hour, at the hazard only of being diſturbed from our pleaſing reveries, and exclaiming with the interrupted viſionary; ‘Pol, me occidiſtis, amici, Non ſervaſtis ait; cui ſic extorta voluptas, Et demtus per vim mentis gratiſſimus error.’

As it is, we do not perceive ourſelves, eſpecially juſt at preſent, a whit more diſpoſed to believe, than to doubt [78] the reality of what we wiſh to be true. We do not think the obſervation holds good, at leaſt ſo generally, or in the degree here ſuppoſed. The bold and ſanguine, indeed, are apt to anticipate their wiſhes; but the timid and ſaturnine are as apt to procraſtinate even their juſt expectations. It is as natural for the one to be confident as for the other to be dubious; nay, perſons of the ſame conſtitution are not always in the ſame diſpoſition or mood either of doubt or credulity.

That there is ſome truth, however, in the rule, with reſpect to its general application, is probable; as faith or facility of Belief is frequently and ſtrongly recommended in the goſpel.

But by the faith or eaſineſs of belief, inculcated in the goſpel, can ſurely be meant nothing more than the pious aſſent and ſubmiſſive acquieſcence of [79] human reaſon to its myſterious and incomprehenſible doctrines, agreeable to its goſpel ſignification mentioned above *, and not that rational conviction, which ariſes from a clear comprehenſion of a propoſition and the evident demonſtration of its truth. The futility of recommending the latter kind of faith or facility of rational conviction, we think, is obvious.

Indeed we do not ſee the neceſſity of demonſtration to produce ſuch an aſſent, as is here admitted to conſtitute a Chriſtian's Faith. If ſuch Faith be, as our author ſays, an act of the will as much as of the underſtanding, there are many inducements to ſuch an act that fall far ſhort of demonſtration.

[80]If it be, as he obſerves, "well worth every man's while to believe Chriſtianity if he can," and ſuch belief depends ſo much on his will, one would think motives of ſelf-intereſt alone would excite him to ſhew that he could, in this caſe, do as he would.

Is it not a ſufficient incitement, to faith in Chriſtianity, to reſſect that "it is the ſureſt preſervative againſt vicious habits and their attendant evils, the beſt reſource under diſtreſſes and diſappointments, ill health and ill fortune, and the firmeſt baſis on which contemplation can reſt?"—That "it is the only principle, which can retain men in a ſteady and uniform courſe of virtue, piety, and devotion, or can ſupport them in the hour of diſtreſs, of ſickneſs and of death?"—

The word Faith, indeed, our author calls unfortunate: ‘It has, ſays he, [81] been ſo tortured and ſo miſapplied to mean every abſurdity, which artifice could impoſe upon ignorance, that it has loſt all pretenſions to the title of virtue; but if brought back to the ſimplicity of its original ſignification, it well deſerves that name, becauſe it uſually ariſes from the moſt amiable diſpoſitions, and is always a direct contraſt to pride, obſtinacy, and ſelf-conceit. If taken in the extenſive ſenſe of an aſſent to the evidence of things not ſeen, it comprehends the exiſtence of a God, and a future ſtate, and is therefore not only itſelf a moral virtue, but the ſource from whence all others muſt proceed; for on the belief of theſe all religion and morality muſt intirely depend.’

Here again, we muſt remind this writer of his having before admitted [82] that men might be virtuous, honeſt and even religious men and yet not be Chriſtians: whereas now he makes not only all religion, but all morality depend on Chriſtian Faith for its very exiſtence; ſuch faith being here expreſsly declared not only in itſelf a moral virtue, but the ſource from whence all others muſt proceed.

Wits, they ſay, have ſhort memories; but, when they turn logicians, philoſophers and divines, they ſhould endeavour to extend their memory, and keep it on the ſtretch, with the thread of their argument, from one end to the other.

On the whole, with reſpect to Faith, as a moral duty; there appears to us but very little argument neceſſary to enforce it. If men can believe or even half-believe what they will, it is ſo much their intereſt to do it in believing [83] the truths of Chriſtianity; the man muſt be either a very great fool or a very great philoſopher indeed, who would remain one moment an Infidel.

If, as this writer declares; Faith be alſo the ſource from whence all other real virtues muſt proceed, who would not be a Chriſtian in practice as well as theory, without waiting a moment for any rational proof of the internal evidence of Chriſtianity!

SECT. V.

On the fourth or concluſive propoſition. ‘That ſuch a ſyſtem of religion and morality could not poſſibly have been the work of any man or ſet of men: much leſs of thoſe obſcure and illiterate perſons, who actually did diſcover and publiſh it to the world; and that, [84] therefore, it muſt undoubtedly have been effected by the interpoſition of divine power, that is, it muſt derive its origin from God.’—This propoſition ſhewn to contain only corollaries of the preceding propoſitions; and, though true as to fact, and therefore admitted ex gratia, ſtill problematical in argument.

THIS propoſition, or rather two propoſitions united, our author gives, as corollaries to the three preceding; preſuming they are ſo concluſive as to amount to little ſhort of demonſtration. It is, indeed, founded, ſays he, ‘on the very ſame reaſoning by which the material world is proved to be the work of his inviſible hand. We view with admiration the heavens and the earth, and all therein contained; we contemplate with amazement [85] ment the minute bodies of animals too ſmall for preception, and the immenſe planetary orbs too vaſt for imagination: we are certain that theſe cannot be the works of man; and therefore we conclude with reaſon, that they muſt be the productions of an omnipotent Creator.’

‘In the ſame manner we ſee here a ſcheme of religion and morality unlike and ſuperior to all ideas of the human mind, equally impoſſible to have been diſcovered by the knowledge, as invented by the artifice of man; and therefore by the very ſame mode of reaſoning, and with the ſame juſtice, we conclude, that it muſt derive its origin from the ſame omnipotent and omniſcient Being.’

With due deference to this ingenious writer, this, like many other [86] parts of his work, is rather declamatory than argumentative. In contemplating the works of creation, our wonder is excited and our admiration raiſed, in proportion as human genius is enabled to trace the marks of divine wiſdom in the Great Artificer.

The vulgar indeed may gape and ſtare at what they cannot comprehend; but how limited are their ideas, how low are their conceptions of the power and wiſdom of the Deity! Their wonder at the moſt ſtupendous inſtances of both, is like that of a child at the ſqueaking of a trumpet or the tinkling of a rattle.

The admiration of the ignorant indeed is founded on their ignorance, that of the ſcientific on their knowledge. It is not from what we do not comprehend that we deduce the wiſdom and power of the Creator, but [87] from what we do comprehend; which, however comparatively little, is the real foundation of our faith in his omniſcience and omnipotence.

On the other hand it is, according to this writer, from the incomprehenſibility of the ſcriptures, as well as of the works of nature, that their divine origin is to be deduced.

The manner of reaſoning therefore, is not, as this writer aſſerts, the ſame in both caſes, but totally different. In reaſoning from our view of the material world, we prudently reaſon from what we know, and how ſhall we reaſon otherwiſe. "What can we reaſon but from what we know?" And yet, in logiciſing according to our author's mode from a view both of the material world and of revelation we fooliſhly attempt to reaſon from what we do not know.

Thus, he ſays, of the former.‘It [88] is not in the leaſt ſurprizing, that we are not able to underſtand the ſpiritual diſpenſations of the Almighty, when his material works are to us no leſs incomprehenſible, our reaſon can afford us no inſight into thoſe great properties of matter, gravitation, attraction, elaſticity, and electricity, nor even into the eſſence of matter itſelf: Can reaſon teach us how the ſun's luminous orb can fill a circle, whoſe diameter contains many millions of miles, with a conſtant inundation of ſucceſſive rays during thouſands of years, without any perceivable diminution of that body, from whence they are continually poured, or any augmentation of thoſe bodies on which they fall, and by which they are conſtantly abſorbed? Can reaſon tell us how thoſe rays, darted with a velocity [89] city greater than that of a canon ball, can ſtrike the tendereſt organs of the human frame without inflicting any degree of pain, or by what means this percuſſion only can convey the forms of diſtant objects to an immaterial mind? or how any union can be formed between material and immaterial eſſences, or how the wounds of the body can give pain to the ſoul, or the anxiety of the ſoul can emaciate and deſtroy the body? That all theſe things are ſo, we have viſible and indiſputable demonſtration; but how they can be ſo, is to us as incomprehenſible, as the moſt abſtruſe myſteries of Revelation can poſſibly be.’

But, ſo far are we from having any viſible and indiſputable demonſtration of the union, or even exiſtence of two eſſentially different and diſtinct ſubſtances [90] in body and ſoul, that our ableſt philoſophers deny the poſſibility of ſuch demonſtration.*

And, indeed, if our author did not himſelf confeſs it, we ſhould hardly be made to believe that he is himſelf ſo bad a philoſopher, as to take the evidence of ſenſe (than which nothing is niore fallible) for demonſtration.

It is with propriety indeed he aſks if reaſon can explain the popular ſyſtem of the ſolar rays in exhibiting the emanation of light: becauſe that popular ſyſtem is unphiloſophical, unreaſonable, and merely imaginary. Were he acquainted with the real mechaniſm productive of thoſe phenomena, he might be ſtruck with the amazing diſplay of wiſdom and power in the divine mechaniſm, but he would find no greater myſtery [91] tery in it than in the complicated operation of the moſt ſimple mechanic powers.

We do readily agree with this ingenious inveſtigator, that we ſee but a ſmall part of the great Whole; that we know but little of the relation, which the preſent life bears to pre-exiſtent and future ſtates; that we can conceive little of the nature of God and his attributes or mode of exiſtence; that we can comprehend little of the material and ſtill leſt of the moral plan on which the univerſe is conſtituted, or on what principle it proceeds.

But we cannot admit ourſelves to be quite ſo ignorant of the mechaniſm of the material univerſe or the true principles of natural philoſophy, as our author appears to be.

And though with regard to the theological [92] plan of the univerſe, we ſhould confeſs our greater ignorance and incapacity of comprehenſion, we ſhould not preſume, as our author in fact does, to deduce the internal evidence of its divine origin from that very incapacity. —On the contrary, we think even the beſt experience and hiſtorical information reſpecting both the works of nature and the doctrines of revelation equally inſufficient to form ſuch a concluſion. *

[93]Another argument, adduced by this author, reſpects the propagation of this religion, which, he ſays, is not leſs extraordinary than the religion itſelf, or leſs above the reach of all human power, than the diſcovery of it was above that of all human underſtanding.

‘It is well known, ſays he, that in the courſe of a very few years, it was ſpread over all the principal parts of Aſia and of Europe, and this by the minlſtry only of an inconſiderable number of the moſt inconſiderable perſons; that at this time paganiſm was in the higheſt repute, believed univerſally by the vulgar and patronized by the great; that the wiſeſt men of the wiſeſt nations aſſiſted at its ſacrifices and conſulted its oracles on the moſt important occaſions: Whether theſe were the tricks of the prieſts or of the devil, is of no conſequence [94] as they were both equally u [...] likely to be converted or overcome; the fact is certain, that on the preach ing of a few fiſhermen, their altars were deſerted, and their deities were dumb.’

Out of veneration for the ſubject, we ſhall not place this argument in that ridiculous light, into which it might be thrown. At the ſame time, having intimated in what a ſuſpicious light we hold hiſtorical evidence in general, we ſhall not enter into any diſpute about matters of fact. *

We might otherwiſe controvert the reputable ſtate of paganiſm at the commencement of the Chriſtian aera; the immediate dumb-founding of its oracles [95] by the preaching of the fiſhermen, and the conſequent eſtabliſhment of Chriſtianity in the principal parts of Europe and Aſia.

The belief of the vulgar in any age [96] reflects but little credit on their religion; and as to the wiſeſt men of the wiſeſt nations of paganiſm conſulting the oracle on important occaſions; we can no more infer their really intereſting themſelves in behalf of paganiſm, than we can infer a ſimilar concluſion in favour of Chriſtianity from the ſimilar farce which the wiſeſt men of the wiſeſt nations in Europe play now.

Even in this proteſtant country, do not our patricians, ſenators, and magiſtrates, goin proceſſion to church, and pay their formal devoirs on certain red letter days, though they laugh at the inſtitution, and even execrate the occaſion? —In poliſhed popiſh countries, their religious ceremonies are ſtill as much more pompous and ſolemn, as the occaſion or deſign is ſtill more held in contempt and deriſion, even by the [97] very perſons aſſiſting in their celebration. *

The fact is, paganiſm was juſt in the ſame reputable ſtate in Greece and Rome at that time, as Chriſtianity is in Paris and Rome at this day: ſo that if political circumſtances did not interfere, and Chriſtianity had no better ſupport than the patronage of the Great and the piety of the populace, it might without a miracle be preached out of both cities by a methodiſt or a mountebank, in much leſs time than paganiſm, was formerly preached out of Rome and Athens, by a few fiſhermen. Our author allows that ‘neither [98] learning nor ſagacity is now able preciſely to aſcertain circumſtances, equally intereſting, of ſtill later times;’ we wonder, therefore, he ſhould reſt on this circumſtance alone the divine authority of the fiſhermen's commiſſion. It is equally ſurpriſing, that having ſo many arguments, and all of them according to him ſeparately irrefragable, he ſhould think it neceſſary to accumulate others merely plauſible.

Of this kind is that paradoxical inſinuation that the improbabilities on the other ſide of the queſtion are ſo much greater that an infidel muſt be an unbeliever from mere credulity. *

Of the ſame kind is that trite, inſinuating, beggarly plea (as Lord Shaftsbury calls it) of ‘what harm could [99] enſue, if Chriſtianity ſhould after all prove a fable?’

There may be in ſome caſes great virtue in that if; but to us, it appears very extraordinary that ever ſuch a ſuppoſition ſhould come from a writer, who has laboured ſo hard, and adduced ſo many arguments to prove its impoſſibility.—Suppoſe! quotha!—

Surely, after all, he does not think there is ſtill ‘left a loop to hang a doubt on,’ that he is ſo very anxious to perſuade thoſe he may not convince! that he dwells ſo earneſtly on the ſaving pleas of their being nothing to be loſt and ſo much to be got by believing in Chriſtianity!* Be this as it may, the whole argumentative part of the author's propoſitions and inference may be reduced to this: ‘The Chriſtian [100] ſyſtem would never have entered into the heads of any perſons whatever. It is inconceivable therefore how ſuch men as did, could propagate it. —Ergo, It muſt have been conceived and propagated by the immediate and miraculous interpoſition of the Deity’.—

Such is, in ſum and ſubſtance, the whole of this mighty argument! in the expoſition of which, we have poſſibly beſtowed already much more time and pains than the diſcerning reader will think neceſſary.

But, having proceeded ſo far with our author's view, we ſhall now proceed till we have ſhewn the vaniſhing point of his perſpective.

SECT. VI.

[101]

On the writer's general concluſions and his notions concerning the eſſential objects of the Chriſtian faith.—Till theſe objects are preciſely determined, the determination of the queſtion reſpecting their divine origin of little importance.

ADMITTING even this writer's propoſitions to have been demonſtrated and the internal evidence of the divine origin of the Chriſtian religion fully proved; we yet ſtill recur to the queſtion, ‘What is the Chriſtian religion, or what are its doctrines?’

We have already obſerved that even the actual profeſſors of Chriſtianity are, by no means agreed on this head.* Our author himſelf, indeed, complains, [102] plains, that ‘ſome there are, who, by perverting the eſtabliſhed ſignification of words, (which they call explaining) have ventured to expunge all the principal doctrines out of the ſcriptures, for no other reaſon than that they are not able to comprehend them; and argue thus:—The ſcriptures are the word of God; in his word no propoſitions contradictory to reaſon can have a place; theſe propoſitions are contradictory to reaſon, and therefore they are not there: But if theſe bold aſſertors would claim any regard, they ſhould reverſe their argument, and ſay—Theſe doctrines make a part, and a material part of the ſcriptures, they are contradictory to reaſon; no propoſitions contradictory to reaſon can be a part of the word of God, and therefore neither the ſcriptures, nor the pretended revelation contained in them, can be derived from him: [103] this would be an argument worthy of rational and candid deiſts, and demand a reſpectful attention; but when men pretend to diſprove facts by reaſoning, they have no right to expect an anſwer.’

Our author will, therefore, hardly think it worth his while to anſwer the queſtions, put to him, on this head, by certain Reviewers; who demand to know where, or by what paſſages the New Teſtament inculcates the doctrines he ſpecifies: doctrines, which the rational advocates of Chriſtianity, they pretend, are afraid to adopt. ‘Theſe advocates,’ ſay they, ‘cannot adopt notions and ſentiments, which are founded on ambiguous, ſigurative, or ſacrificial expreſſions; and ſuſpect a miſinterpretation of ſcripture, where the doctrine they embrace is [104] far removed from every tract of the human imagination.’

This is exactly what our author upbraids them for, their wanting to reduce the extent of divine wiſdom to the line of the human underſtanding.

At the ſame time, before we can admit our author to have deduced any concluſive argument reſpecting the internal evidence of the Chriſtian religion, it is requiſite he ſhould certify what its doctrines are. The critics laſtmentioned ſuſpect a miſinterpretation of ſcripture, where the doctrine they inculcate is far removed from every tract of the human imagination.—The Monthly Reviewers ſay alſo, ‘it has not occurred to them that doctrines, allowed to be contradictory to reaſon, are not on this account the leſs credible.’

On the other hand, our author [105] makes their inconſiſtency with reaſon, and their being above the flight of human imagination, the very criterion of their divine origin and, of courſe, their credibility. The ſcriptures, according to him, ‘contain ideas totally unheard of, and quite diſſimilar from any which had ever been thought on previous to their publication. No other, ſays he, ever drew ſo juſt a portrait of the worthleſsneſs of this world; and all its purſuits, nor exhibited ſuch diſtinct, lively and exquiſite pictures of the joys of another; of the reſurrection of the dead, the laſt judgment, and the triumphs of the righteous in that tremendous day, when this corruptible ſhall put on incorruption, and this mortal ſhall put on immortality. No other has ever repreſented the ſupreme Being in the character of [106] three perſons united in one God. No other has attempted to reconcile thoſe ſeeming contradictory but both true propoſitions, the contingency of future events, and the foreknowledge of God, or the free will of the creature with the over-ruling grace of the Creator. No other has ſo fully declared the neceſſity of wickedneſs and puniſhment, yet ſo effectually inſtructed individuals to reſiſt the one, and to eſcape the other: no other has ever pretended to give any account of the depravity of man, or to point out any remedy for it: no other has ventured to declare the unpardonable nature of ſin without the influence of a mediatorial interpoſition, and a vicarious atonement from the ſufferings of a ſuperior Being.’

[107]Such are the objects of the Chriſtian, Religion according to this author; but it is well known that the moſt eſſential of theſe doctrines are either totally diſbelieved or explained away by a very conſiderable part of the profeſſors of Chriſtianity.

The very Reviewers, above mentioned, in particular, cannot allow with this writer ‘that the province of reaſon is only to examine into the authority of Revelation; and when that is proved that reaſon has nothing more to do than to acquieſce.’

And ſo far we agree with them that Reaſon is juſt as well qualified to judge of the interpretation of particular texts and paſſages of ſcripture, as to judge of the authenticity of the whole.

But we deny, on the authority of that very ſcripture, that unenlightened [108] reaſon is qualified to judge of either, Our author "readily, as unneceſſarily, acknowledges, as before obſerved, that the ſcriptures are not revelations from God, but the hiſtory of ſuch Revelations;" of whoſe imperfections and fallibility, therefore, we ſay, nothing leſs than the influence of that divine grace, which inſpired the revelation itſelf, can qualify any man to judge.

Hence the moral arguments, and hiſtorical evidence, which our author adduces, to prove the divine origin of revelation, appear nugatory.

To deny the probable facts, he ſays, related in the New Teſtament, would be as abſurd as to deny the probable facts in any other hiſtory.—This is true, and yet the joint evidence of all the probable facts, related in any hiſtory ſacred or profane, amounts to no more [109] than that moral evidence, which will juſtify the belief of probable (not improbable) facts.

The ſame may be ſaid of the doctrines of the Scriptures; if their divine authority is to depend on mere hiſtorical evidence, they ſhould appear to be as rational as the evidence, on which that authority is ſupported, is probable: and not the credibility of both facts and doctrines left prepoſterouſly to be ſupported, according to our author's ſcheme, by the improbability of the one, and incomprehenſibility of the other *.

[110] ‘To aſcertain the true ſyſtem and genuine doctrines of this religion after the undecided controverſies of above ſeventeen centuries, and to remove all the rubbiſh, which artifice and ignorance have been heaping upon it during all that time, would indeed be an arduous talk, which our author will by no means undertake;’ nor is it, indeed, neceſſary when he can reduce all the eſſentials as he ſuppoſes, into ſo ſmall a compaſs.

[111]But it is neceſſary that theſe eſſentials ſhould be agreed on and rendered indiſputable, before the proof of their divine origin can be of any uſe.

With reſpect, for inſtance, to one of the moſt eſſential:—‘That Chriſt ſuffered and died as an atonement for the ſins of mankind, is a doctrine,’ ſays the writer, ‘ſo conſtantly and ſo ſtrongly enforced through every part of the New Teſtament, that whoever will ſeriouſly peruſe thoſe writings, and deny that it is there, may, with as much reaſon and truth, after reading the works of Thucydides and Livy, aſſert, that in them no mention is made of any facts relative to the hiſtories of Greece and Rome.’

We are perfectly of his opinion in this reſpect, and yet it is with aſtoniſhing confidence the contrary is [112] maintained by many late writers of pretended candour and undoubted abilities. So that while the doctrines of Chriſtianity are thus in diſpute (that is) till it be determined what the eſſential doctrines of Revelation are, we conceive, as we ſaid before, the determination of the queſtion reſpecting its divine origin to be of very little importance; even if it were determinable by our author's mode of argument. But, again we ſay, we can by no means agree with him that men would believe divine revelation in proportion as its tenets were incomprehenſible to the underſtanding.

On the contrary, the inference we ſhould naturally draw from the imperfect ſtate of human ſcience and the inſufficiency of unaſſiſted reaſon to attain any portion of divine knowledge, would be, that nothing but the immediate influence of Grace, the inſpiration [113] of the Almighty which giveth underſtanding, could induce the ſceptic to believe either the divine origin of the ſcriptures or the doctrines, they contain.

SECT. VII.

On the objections, that have been made to the divinity and veracity of the Chriſtian religion: and particularly to objection the First, viz, ‘That divine Revelation is incredible becauſe unneceſſary, becauſe the reaſon, which God has beſtowed on mankind is ſufficiently able to diſcover all the religious and moral duties, which he requires of them; if they will but attend to her precepts and be guided by her friendly admonitions.’—This objection ſhewn to be neither properly ſtated nor ſatisfactorily removed.

[114]"IF," ſays our author, ‘I have demonſtrated the divine origin of the Chriſtian religion by an argument which cannot be confuted; no others, however plauſible or numerous, founded on probabilities, doubts and conjectures, can ever diſprove it, becauſe if it is once ſhewn to be true, it cannot be falſe *.’

There is no parrying theſe ifs; but if this writer's argument be not ſuch as cannot be confuted, there may beſomething in the arguments founded on probabilities, doubts and conjectures, that make againſt it.—It is on that ſuppoſition, we imagine, he attempts to refute ſuch objections: as it is on that conviction, viz. that his argument itſelf is invalid, that we ſhall proceed to conſider how far he has been ſucceſsful in removing them.

[115]In anſwer to the firſt objection *, ‘That Revelation is incredible becauſe unneceſſary, on the plea of the ſufficiency of human reaſon to diſcover all the religious and moral duties God requires of them.’ He obſerves, that ‘Reaſon alone is ſo far from being ſufficient to offer to mankind a perfect religion, that it has never yet been able to lead them to any degree of culture or civiliſation whatever;’ deducing a demonſtration (as it ſeems to him.) from Hiſtory, that ‘although human reaſon is capable of progreſſion in ſcience, yet the firſt foundation muſt be laid by ſupernatural inſtructions.

Now, ſays he, ‘As Reaſon in her natural ſtate is incapable of making [116] any progreſs * in knowledge, ſo when furniſhed with materials by ſupernatural aid, if left to the guidance of her own wild imaginations, ſhe falls into more numerous, and more groſs errors, than her own native ignorance could ever have ſuggeſted.’

Only think, reader, of the wild imaginations of Reaſon!—And yet the reaſonable ſuggeſtions, which our author enumerates, it muſt be owned, are wild and extravagant enough.

"SHE," ſays he (that is Reaſon) ‘has perſuaded ſome, that there is [117] no God; others that there can be no future ſtate: ſhe has taught ſome, that there is no difference between vice and virtue, and that to cut a man's throat and to relieve his neceſſities are actions equally meritorious: ſhe has convinced many, that they have no free-will in oppoſition to their own experience: ſome that there can be no ſuch thing as ſoul, or ſpirit, contrary to their own perceptions; and others, no ſuch thing as matter or body, in contradiction to their ſenſes. By analyſing all things ſhe can ſhew, that there is nothing in any thing; by perpetual ſhifting ſhe can reduce all exiſtence to the inviſible duſt of ſcepticiſm; and by recurring to firſt principles, prove to the ſatisfaction of her followers, that there are no principles at all.’

[118]After this curious piece of ſophiſtical declamation, he adds, ‘How far ſuch a guide is to be depended on in the important concerns of religion, and morals, I leave to the judgment of every conſiderate man to determine.’

That is, after declaring Reaſon to be a fallacious guide and an incompetent judge, he will leave it to the direction of that very guide and the determination of that very judge, how far ſuch direction and determination are to be depended on!—For what elſe can he mean by leaving it to the judgment of any conſiderate man? Is not this leaving it to Reaſon, or ſetting up Reaſon in judgment on herſelf?

To do juſtice to the nobleſt faculty of the human mind, we will venture to declare that Reaſon never [119] ſuggeſted any of the above extravagancies to any man.

Reaſon never could perſuade any man that "there is no God." Indeed the office of Reaſon is not perſuaſion but conviction, and no man, capable of conviction, ever yet was even perſuaded that ſecond cauſes do not proceed from a firſt. *

Reaſon never taught any man there is no difference between virtue and vice: His neceſſary uſe of the very terms is a proof of it; as well as the [120] natural ſenſe of juſtice, implanted in the breaſt of every humanbeing. ‘Do unto others as you would have them do unto you,’ is not merely New Teſtament doctrine. It is as old as the multiplication of mankind; it is an univerſal principle, a law of which (to uſe the expreſſion of a celebrated, though inconſiſtent, moraliſt) ‘every man may find the expoſition in his own breaſt *.

Reaſon never taught any man, there can be no future ſtate. The utmoſt, that reaſon ever taught, is that we are indebted to revelation for the certain knowledge of ſuch ſtate or muſt depend chiefly on ſcriptural proof for the evidence of it. Not but that there are even rational arguments in its favour, as [121] well of the phyſical and moral * as of the religious kind.

[122] Reaſon never perſuaded any man that he hath no free-will, in oppoſition to his own experience.—If ſhe ſuggeſted a doubt of his capacity to [123] will or act without a motive, it is a ſuggeſtion founded on all experience; as his conviction of not being a mere mechanical machine, actuated by no motives at all, is founded on the ſame experience.

Reaſon never ſuggeſted the non-exiſtence of ſoul or body, of matter or ſpirit, in contradiction to our ſenſes and perceptions.—Neither matter nor ſpirit are ideas of ſenſation, but of reflection. Reaſon teaches us, indeed, the fallibility of ſenſation and perception, and the means of correcting their errors; and well for us it is, that ſhe does ſo: we ſhould elſe be totally deſtitute of ſcience; and, for want of the inſtincts of other animals, ſhould be in a worſe ſituation than the brutes that periſh.

From the above ſpecification, indeed, of the ſuppoſed abſurdities of human reaſon, it appears to us that, our author [124] hath neither phyſics nor metaphyſics enough to enter on a philoſophical diſcuſſion of the points in queſtion.— We might, therefore, in like manner, leave to the judgment of our conſiderate readers to determine, whether the Reaſon, or rather the Imagination, of any man, in his ſenſes, ever fell into groſſer errors than has here that of our author; in which caſe, they would likewiſe determine how far ſuch a guide is to be depended on in the important concerns of religion and morals.

We might, indeed, cenſure here the ſuperficial and illogical manner; in which this writer has ſtated this objection; viz. his ſpeaking of mankind, as if the human mind was ſomething diſtinct from, and poſſeſſed of, the power of controuling its eſſential faculties.

But that excellent logician, Mr Harris, in his Dialogue on Happineſs, [125] hath illuſtrated, in the moſt perſpicuous manner, the reciprocal influence of reaſon and paſſion in the conduct and compoſition of the human mind. To ſuch writers, therefore, we refer our author, for the attainment of more preciſe ideas on this ſubject than he ſeems at preſent to poſſeſs, or will ever obtain from the looſe and rambling reaſonings of thoſe who ſtile themſelves Chriſtian philoſophers or rational divines.

SECT. VIII.

On his reply to a ſecond objection, ‘That the Old and New Teſtament cannot be a revelation from God, becauſe in them are to be found errors and inconſiſtencies, fabulous ſtories, falſe facts and falſe philoſophy; which can never be derived from the Fountain of all Truth.’—This objection ſhewn to [126] be rather enforced by the author's conceſſions, than removed by his concluſions.

HERE our author very readily (and, as we before obſerved, in our opinion, for his argument unneceſſarily) acknowledges that the ſcriptures are not revelations from God, but only the hiſtory of them. ‘The revelation itſelf,’ ſays he, ‘is derived from God; but the hiſtory of it is the production of men, and therefore the truth of it is not in the leaſt affected by their fallibility.’

He admits, of courſe, that the inſpired writers were not always under the influence of inſpiration; for, if they had, ſays he, St Paul, who was ſhipwrecked, and left his cloak and parchments at Troas, would not have put to ſea before a ſtorm, nor have [127] forgot himſelf ſo much as to leave his cloak behind him.

"But," continues he, ‘if in theſe books a religion ſuperior to all human imagination actually exiſts, it is of no conſequence to the proof of its divine origin, by what means it was there introduced, or with what human errors and imperfections it is blended. A diamond, though found in a bed of mud, is ſtill a diamond, nor can the dirt, which ſurrounds it, depreciate its value or deſtroy its luſtre.’

This alluſion may be well calculated to catch the ſimple apprehenſion of the ſuperficial reader; but, one of the leaſt diſcrimination cannot fail to diſcover how totally inapplicable it is to the ſubject in queſtion.

A fine lady, indeed, may careleſsly drop a manufactured brilliant into the [128] kennel, to be accidentally picked up by a gold-finder; but rough diamonds are not originally found there; they have not their native bed in the ſtreets, or on the dunghill; but are dug from mines, prepared by Nature's proceſs for their production: in which ſtate, alſo, they do not ſhine with a luſtre ſo greatly ſuperior to the ſurrounding materials.

We by no means agree with our author, therefore, that his proof of the internal evidence of the divine origin of revelation, does not ſuffer, by admitting that ‘the prophecies are all fortunate gueſſes or artful applications, and the miracles there recorded no better than legendary tales.’ *

On the contrary we conceive that ſuch an heterogeneous mixture of truth and falſehood, as he hypothetically [129] admits in the hiſtory, as he calls it, of revelation, would, if it really exiſted there, very reaſonably bring the truths it contains into doubt.—Nay, we will go ſo far as to admit that there really do appear ſo many errors and inconſiſtencies, in that hiſtory, that unenlightened reaſon cannot reconcile them: the inſpiration of grace being as neceſſary to point out theſe truths and induce a firm belief of them, as it was to direct and enable the inſpired writers to record them.

SECT. IX.

On his reply to a third objection. ‘That a wiſe and benevolent Creator ſhould have conſtituted a world upon one plan and a religion for it on another.’ Under the term religion in this objection, the author [130] is ſhewn to include morals alſo; but the purity of the Chriſtian morals is ſhewn not to be calculated for the conſtitution of this world, and therefore not required of Chriſtians in their preſent ſtate of probation.

‘TO ſome ſpeculative and refined obſervers it has appeared incredible’, ſays our author, ‘that a wiſe and benevolent Creator ſhould have conſtituted a world upon one plan, and a religion for it on another; that is, that he ſhould have revealed a religion to mankind, which not only contradicts the principal paſſions and inclinations which he has implanted in their natures, but is incompatible with the whole oeconomy of that world which he has created, and in which he has thought proper to place them. This, ſay they, with [131] regard to the Chriſtian, is apparently the caſe: the love of power, riches, honour, and fame, are the great incitements to generous and magnanimous actions; yet by this inſtitution are all theſe depreciated and diſcouraged. Government is eſſential to the nature of man, and cannot be managed without certain degrees of violence, corruption, and impoſition; yet are all theſe ſtrictly forbid. Nations cannot ſubſiſt without wars, nor war be carried on without rapine, deſolation, and murder: yet are theſe prohibited under the ſevereſt threats. The non-reſiſtance of evil muſt ſubject individuals to continual oppreſſions, and leave nations a defenceleſs prey to their enemies; yet is this recommended. Perpetual patience under inſults and injuries muſt every day provoke new inſults [132] and new injuries, yet is this injoined. A neglect of all we eat and drink and wear, muſt put an end to all commerce, manufactures, and induſtry; yet is this required. In ſhort, were theſe precepts univerſally obeyed, the diſpoſition of all human affairs muſt.be entirely changed, and the buſineſs of the world, conſtituted as it now is, could not go on.’

The Monthly Reviewers very juſtly obſerve, on this paſſage, that no ſerious advocate for Chriſtianity can admit all theſe contradictions: for, indeed, they militate not leſs againſt the practical principles of Chriſtianity than againſt: thoſe of Common-ſenſe. Our author, nevertheleſs boldly affirms that ‘Such is the Chriſtian revelation, tho' ſome of its advocates may perhaps be unwilling to own it, and ſuch it is conſtantly declared to be by him [133] who gave it, as well as by thoſe who publiſhed it under his immediate direction:’ To theſe he ſays, ‘If ye were of the world, the world would love his own; but becauſe ye are not of the world, but I have choſen you out, of the world, therefore the world hateth you’ *. To the Jews he declares, ‘Ye are of this world; I am not of this world’ . St Paul writes to the Romans, ‘Be not conformed to this world ; and to the Corinthians, "We ſpeak not the wiſdom of this world §." St James ſays, ‘Know ye not, that the friendſhip of the world is enmity with God? whoſoever therefore will be a friend of the world is the enemy of God . This irreconcileable ‘diſagreement between Chriſtianity and the world is announced in numberleſs [134] berleſs other places in the New Teſtament, and indeed by the whole tenour of thoſe writings. Theſe are plain declarations, which, in ſpite of all the evaſions of thoſe good managers, who chooſe to take a little of this world in their way to heaven, ſtand fixed and immoveable againſt all their arguments drawn from public benefit and pretended neceſſity, and muſt ever forbid any reconciliation between the purſuits of this world and the Chriſtian inſtitution.’

We have as much contempt as our author can have for thoſe good managers, who chooſe to take as much of this world as they can with them in their journey to the next. We are alſo as well ſatisfied as he can be, that Chriſtian morality in its purity is not calculated for the practice of man in [135] his preſent ſtate; but inculcated to inſpire a proper diſpoſition preparatory to another. But, for the ſame reaſons, we think the obſervance of it no farther required of us than it is practicable.

‘If it be poſſible, as much as lieth in you, live peaceably with all men *,’ ſays St. Paul to the Romans. The Chriſtian religion enjoins not impoſſibilities; it impoſes not hard and impracticable duties; requiring no more of any man than lieth in him. The Scripture expreſsly declares; ‘Its yoke is eaſy and its burthen is light.’

[136]The ſeveral texts, therefore, above adduced by our author, are evidently miſapplied.

That a conformity to the vices and follies of the world is prohibited to Chriſtians, is moſt certain; but where are they forbid to conform to the eſtabliſhed cuſtoms and neceſſary duties of ſociety? Are they not, on the other hand, expreſsly enjoined, to ſubmit to every ordinance of man for the Lord's ſake?To pay the moſt implicit obedience to magiſtrates and all that are in power; for that the powers, that be, are of God?

Where is it, we aſk again, that Chriſtians are required by the Scriptures ſo to act as to put an end to all commerce, manufactures, and induſtry; to change the diſpoſition of all human [137] affairs, and put a ſtop to the buſineſs of the world?—

Are theſe extravagances deduced from our Saviour's ſermon on the Mount and the inſtructions he gave his immediate diſciples?—Men poſſeſſed of the power of working miracles for their ſupport or defence, might ſafely indeed leave to-morrow to take care for itſelf, careleſs of what they might eat, drink or wear. But ſetting aſide the conſideration that many things may be enjoined as particular and perſonal duties, adapted to time and place, which are by no means required univerſally; ſetting aſide alſo the conſideration that our Saviour was exhibiting to his diſciples a theory of morality, adapted rather to man in a ſtate of perfection than to man in his preſent imperfect ſtate of probation; it is plain that he had in view the holding [138] up a contraſt to the boaſted morality of thoſe vain-glorious hypocrites the Scribes and Phariſees; in order to check that overweening pride, with which they exulted in their good-works over the ſincere and humble penitence of the publican and ſinner.

Our Saviour did not preach the ſame ſtrictneſs of morals to all, as he did to his immediate followers. ‘Behold one came and ſaid unto him, good maſter, what good thing ſhall I do to inherit eternal life? —And he ſaid unto him, Why calleſt thou me good? there is none good but one, that is God: but if thou wilt enter into life keep the Commandments.—He ſaith unto him, which? Jeſus ſaid, Thou ſhalt do no murder, Thou ſhalt not commit adultery, Thou ſhalt not ſteal, Thou ſhalt not bear falſe witneſs; [139] Honour thy father and thy mother: and thou ſhalt love thy neighbour as thyſelf.’

Every one of theſe commandments, we ſee, reſpects the diſcharge of the ſocial duties incumbent on man in the preſent ſtate of ſociety. Not one is mentioned of a nature purely religious; even the firſt commandment reſpecting the very acknowledgment of God is omitted: and yet Jeſus ſays, keep theſe commandments and thou wilt enter into life.

The unattainable nature of moral goodneſs in this mortal ſtate is alſo here ſtrongly inculcated, "There is none good but God *. "—And yet ſo good [140] was the preſuming Queriſt, that he anſwered, he had kept all theſe commandments from his youth up; pertly adding, "what lack I yet?"— Jeſus ſaid unto him, "if thou wilt be perfect, go, ſell that thou haſt, give it to the poor and follow me."

[141]This ſacrifice of the things of this world, we ſee, was required of him, not as the conditions of his ſalvation, but as a proof of that moral perfection to which he pretended, and as a qualification neceſſary for him to become an immediate follower and diſciple of Jeſus Chriſt.

In like manner, we will venture to ſay, that Chriſtianity, at this day, requires no purer morals in its profeſſors, than as much as in them lies, to live peaceably with all men, to keep thoſe commandments which are eſſential to the good of ſociety and the peace and happineſs of mankind.

Let the ſincere Chriſtian do this and we believe he will enter into eternal life, even though he ſhould be ſomewhat nice in regard to what he eats, drinks and wears; though he ſhould promote commerce, manufactures and [142] induſtry, yea, though he ſhould, conſiſtently with the laws of his country, reſent inſults, puniſh injuries, enter into the civil or even military ſervice of government, draw his ſword againſt the enemies of the ſtate, and even fatally embrue it in blood, to chaſtiſe the inſolence of unnatural rebellion!

SECT. X.

On his reply to a fourth objection, ‘That if this revelation had really been from God, his infinite power and goodneſs could never have ſuffered it to have been ſo ſoon perverted from its original purity, to have continued in a ſtate of corruption through the courſe of ſo many ages; and at laſt to have proved ſo ineffectual to the reformation of mankind.’—The manner, in [143] which this objection is attempted to be removed, ſhewn to reflect the higheſt indignity on the divine Author of the Chriſtian religion, as well as on that religion itſelf.

IN anſwer to this fourth objection, our author very candidly and very ſimply replies, that on examination all this will be found inevitable.—We believe it; things could not poſſibly be otherwiſe, becauſe ſuch was the general deſign of Providence, and ſuch the Chriſtian diſpenſation, which was a part of it.

In reply to this objection, indeed, our author admits the whole force of it; which he endeavours to elude by a very ſimple expedient: much ſuch another as that, by which he accounts elſewhere for the origin of evil, Neceſſity! hard neceſſity; which even the omnipotence of the Deity could not [144] prevent! What is this but making the God of the Chriſtians a mere heathen Jupiter, ſubject to the controul of ſuperior Fate?

He admits, that after Chriſtianity had had made its way, by means of the preaching of the poor and mean, in holes and caverns, under the iron rod of perſecution, till it ſo far prevailed as to obtain the countenance and protection of princes; when kings became its patrons, and queens its nurſing mothers; he admits, we ſay, that it could no longer withſtand the irreſiſtible effects of the natural imperfection of man and the political evils of civil ſociety. ‘At length the meek and humble profeſſors of the goſpel inſlaved theſe princes, and conquered theſe conquerors their patrons, and erected for themſelves ſuch a ſtupendous fabric of wealth and power, as the world [145] had never ſeen: they then propagated their religion by the ſame methods by which it had been perſecuted; nations were converted by fire and ſword, and the vanquiſhed were baptiſed with daggers at their throats.*

Horrid abominations! exclaims our author at the enormities of the poor pagans. But what more horrid abominations could they be guilty of than theſe? Were any of thoſe, which, our author ſays, were practiſed in the pagan world, and vaniſhed at the approach of Chriſtianity, more horrid or more abominable? And yet they were permitted it ſeems, becauſe they could not be prevented. They proceeded, we are told, from a chain of cauſes and conſequences, which could not have been broken without changing the eſtabliſhed courſe of things by a conſtant ſeries of [146] miracles, or a total alteration of human nature.*

What a pity that a buſineſs which had ſo promiſing a beginning, ſhould be ſo ſoon interrupted by ſuch ſiniſter and unforeſeen accidents! For ſurely they muſt have been unforeſeen, when the courſe of things was about to be eſtabliſhed and human nature firſt conſtituted!

To be ſerious, this is a bungling excuſe for a ſuppoſed blunder in the firſt outſet of things, unleſs we ſeriouſly adopt the reaſon, our author deduces from revelation, viz. that it could not be otherwiſe, ‘becauſe that all men ſhould be exempted from ſin and puniſhment is utterly repugnant to the univerſal ſyſtem, and that conſtitution of things, which infinite wiſdom has thought proper to adopt.

[147]This may be, but we revere the eternal councils of the great author and diſpoſer of all things too much, to ſuppoſe he was ever under the predicament of adopting any meaſure or ſyſtem of action, that reſulted originally from any thing but his own will.

SECT. XI.

On his reply to the fifth objection, ‘The incredibility of ſome of its doctrines, particularly thoſe concerning the Trinity, and atonement for ſin by the ſufferings and death of Chriſt; the one contradicting all the principles of human reaſon, and the other all our ideas of natural juſtice.’—This objection ſhewn to be rather evaded than ſolved; the author not having fairly and fully ſtated the difficulties it really contains.

[148]TO theſe objections, ſays our author, ‘I ſhall only ſay, that no arguments founded on principles, which we cannot comprehend, can poſſibly diſprove a propoſition already proved on principles which we do underſtand; and therefore that on this ſubject they ought not to be attended to.’ But this is rather evading the difficulty than ſolving it. Indeed, with regard to the doctrines of the Trinity and vicarious atonement he beſtows on them ſome little attention. In reſpect to the former, he obſerves, ‘That three beings ſhould be one being, is a propoſition which certainly contradicts reaſon; that is, our reaſon: but it does not thence follow, that it cannot be true; for there are many propoſitions which contradict our reaſon, and yet are demonſtrably true.’

[149]That this is a propoſition contradictory to reaſon, we admit; but we deny, that it is either true or capable of demonſtration. There may be propoſitions contradictory to reaſon, and yet not demonſtrably falſe; nay, they may be ſuch as, however contradictory to reaſon, we cannot help believing to be true; but to be demonſtrably ſo, they muſt be perfectly and evidently conſonant to reaſon; for demonſtration is nothing but the reſult of a compleat proceſs of rational argument.

That propoſitions apparently falſe are demon ſtrably true, is almoſt too notorious to merit illuſtration. Inſtances occur every moment in which the inference of our ill-informed and immediate apprehenſion is directly contradictory to that of a better-informed and deliberate reflection.

[150]There are propoſitions, alſo, that require not only much deliberation, but much inſtruction, before our reaſon is qualified to paſs any judgment concerning them. This our author elſewhere admits, * though, under the preſent head, he proceeds to ſupport his aſſertion by example; offering an inſtance of the propoſitions, which, he ſays, are contradictory to reaſon, and yet demonſtrably true. ‘One, ſays he, is the very firſt principle of all religion, the being of a God; for that any thing ſhould exiſt without a cauſe, or that any thing ſhould be the cauſe of its own exiſtence, are propoſitions equally contradictory to our reaſon; yet one of them muſt be true, or nothing could ever have exiſted.

The Monthly Reviewers very juſtly inſinuate, that here is a confuſion of [151] terms: indeed our author here ſadly expoſes his want of logical preciſion. —Not to cavil at his calling God a thing, his oppoſing the term being, or exiſtence (inſtead of effect) to the term cauſe, is illogical in the higheſt degree.

All created beings, or things, are confeſſedly the EFFECTS of one firſt CAUSE; but we conceive this is the firſt time, ſo expert a logician ever made ſuch a blunder as to put the firſt cauſe on a footing with ſecond cauſes; and aſſert (as our author, in fact, does) that no cauſe could ever have exiſted that was not the effect of ſome prior cauſe. If he is not betrayed here into a ſlat denial of the exiſtence of a God, or firſt cauſe, we know not what is ſuch.

Our author palpably miſtakes the permanent predicament of exiſtence and duration, for the tranſitory one of production and ſucceſſion In the former the [152] terms being and thing are uſed with propriety: in the latter thoſe of cauſe and effect with equal propriety: but it is a ſoleciſm in ratiocination to confound one with the other. For, though, in the order of nature the exiſtence of one thing becomes the productive cauſe of another, the God of Nature, the primary, and efficient cauſe of all, ſuperier to the work of his hands, * is exempted [153] from the laws of ſubordination; which he has preſcribed as the tegular ſucceſſion of ſecond cauſes and effects. It is, indeed, in our conception, a kind of metaphyſical blaſphemy to repreſent God as an effect which could not have exiſted without a cauſe, even though it be ſheltered uhder the metaphyſical abſurdity of ſuppoſing that effect the cauſe of itſelf.

And yet our author proceeds with his examples; ‘In like manner, the over-ruling grace of the Creator, and [154] the free-will of his creatures, his certain foreknowledge of future events, and the uncertain contingency of thoſe events, are to our apprehenſions abſolute contradictions to each other; and yet the truth of every one of theſe is demonſtrable from Scripture, reaſon and experience.’

Here again our author confounds the abſolute and eternal attributes of the Creator with the relative and temporary properties of his creatures. That theſe ſhould be apparently contradictory is no wonder: but that they are not, as our author affirms, abſolute contradictions, is known to every man of ſenſe and ſcicnce, that hath beſtowed ſufficient attention on the ſubject; to whom theſe ſeeming contradictions muſt be eaſily reconcileable. The over-ruling grace of the Creator is irreſiſtible and poſitive; the free-will of [155] his creatures reſiſtible and comparative. The agency of man, compared with that of the Deity, is limited, confined, and ſervile. On the other hand, if compared with the agency of inferior animals, plants, &c. it is liberal and free.—The foreknowledge of the Deity is abſolute and indiſputable, as the ſucceſſion of future events is with reſpect to him, fixed and unalterable; with reſpect to man, indeed, their contingency is as uncertain as is his want of foreknowledge, or ignorance, of their neceſſary ſucceſſion.

All Nature is but Art, unknown to thee;
All chance, direction, which thou canſt not ſee.

But to recur to the author's remarks on the doctrine of the Trinity. It is with propriety he obſerves, that ‘the difficulties with reſpect to our belief in this doctrine ariſe from our imagining, that the mode of exiſtence [156] of all beings muſt be ſimilar to our own; that is, that they muſt all exiſt in ſpace and time. Hence, ſays he very juſtly, proceeds our embarraſſment on this ſubject. We know that no two beings, with whoſe mode of exiſtence we are acquainted, can exiſt in the ſame point of time, in the ſame point of ſpace, and that therefore they cannot be one: but how far beings, whoſe mode of exiſtence bears no relation to time and ſpace, may be united, we cannot comprehend: and, therefore, the poſſibility of ſuch an union we cannot poſitively deny.’

This is philoſophical and juſt, but there is a wide difference between poſitively denying a doctrine, and abſolutely believing it.—Moſt certain, however, it is, that the doctrine of the Trinity, as it is taught by ſome of the [157] Athanaſians, cannot poſſibly be believed by any human being. *

Our author reduces this formidable abſurdity (for ſuch it is, as ſome trinitarians repreſent it) to a mere ſimple propoſition, as eaſy to be believed as that three equal angles or ſides conſtitute one equilateral triangle. But this is not the caſe. In the exuberant and rattling eloquence of the famous Dr. Jeremy Taylor, the myſtery of the Godhead is thus enigmatically diſplayed. —‘See what was to be taught, a [158] trinity in the unity of the Godhead, [...]; that is, the Chriſtian arithmetic, Three are one and one are three. So Lucian in his Philopatris, or ſome other, decides the Chriſtian doctrines; ſee their philoſophy, Ex nihilo nihil fit.—No: Ex nihilo omnia, all things are made of nothing; and a man-God and a God-man, the ſame perſon finite and infinite, born in time and yet from all eternity, the ſon of God, but yet born of a woman, and ſhe a maid, but yet a mother; reſurrection of the dead, re-union of ſoul and body; this was part of the Chriſtian phyſics or their natural philoſophy.’ *

With due deference to the authority of this eminent divine, as well as to [159] his late editor, Biſhop Hurd, all this is merely declamatory. It is alſo ſo far ſophiſtical, in that it is the Chriſtian theology and not either arithmetic or phyſics.—The mathematics and natural philoſophy of the Chriſtian and the Heathen are the ſame: nor is it any impeachment to the divinity of revelation, that it has no place in the cyclopaedia, or circle of human arts and ſciences.

The caſe is, theſe writers do not make a proper diſtinction between a palpable contradiction in terms and an apparent contrariety in fact. There is alſo a neceſſary diſtinction to be made between the belief of the truth of a propoſition (or the believing a propoſition to be true) and the belief of the propoſition itſelf: the former being conſiſtent with an imperfect apprehenſion of its meaning; and the other conſiſtent only with a clear and preciſe [160] comprehenſion as well of the predicate as of the ſubject.

From theſe diſtinctions ariſes a third, equally juſt and neceſſary, between the faith of the Chriſtian and the belief of the philoſopher. But of theſe diſtinctions more fully hereafter. *

SECT. XII.

On his reply to the ſixth objection. ‘That, however true theſe doctrines may be, yet it muſt be inconſiſtent with the juſtice and goodneſs of the Creator, to require from his creatures the belief of propoſitions, which contradict, or are above the reach of that reaſon, which he has thought proper to beſtow on them.’ This objection [161] anſwered by denying that genuine Chriſtianity requires any ſuch belief.— The nature of the Chriſtian faith inveſtigated and its latitude defined: Chriſtianity, as it requires nothing impracticable to be performed, ſo it requires nothing impoſſible to be believed.

TO this ſixth objection, our author anſwers, "Genuine Chriſtianity requires no ſuch belief."

‘It has diſcovered to us many important truths, with which we were before entirely unacquainted, and amongſt them are theſe, that three Beings are ſome way united in the divine eſſence, and that God will accept of the ſufferings of Chriſt as an atonement for the ſins of mankind. Theſe, conſidered as declarations of facts only, neither contradict, or are above the reach of [162] human reaſon: The firſt is a propoſition as plain, as that three equilaral lines compoſe one triangle *, the other is as intelligible, as that one man ſhould diſcharge the debts of another. In what manner this union is formed, or why God accepts theſe vicarious puniſhments, or to what purpoſes they may be ſubſervient, it informs us not, becauſe no information could enable us to comprehend theſe myſteries, and therefore it does not require that we ſhould know or believe any thing about them.’

How! not any thing about them! Surely this is looſely and badly expreſſed! As a declaration of fact merely, it has been already obſerved that the [163] orthodox doctrine of the Trinity is not ſo ſimple and rational as here laid down; but much more complex and paradoxical.

As to the quomodo of the triunion, and the reaſon why God accepts of a vicarious atonement for the ſins of mankind; theſe are certainly beyond rational inveſtigation, but Chriſtians are doubtleſs required to believe ſo much about them, as that the facts are as poſſible as their declaration is true.

Again, if no information can enable us to comprehend theſe myſteries, it is not with very great propriety ſuch important truths are ſaid to be diſcovered by Revelation. The doctrines as mere declarations, indeed, may be ſaid to be diſcovered, as they were not divulged before; but if thoſe doctrines themſelves ſtill remain myſterious, they [164] would with more propriety be ſaid to be ſimply declared or promulgated, than their truth to be diſcovered.

"The truth of theſe doctrines," our author owns, ‘muſt reſt intirely on the authority of thoſe who taught them; but then, ſays he, we ſhould reflect that thoſe were the ſame perſons who taught us a ſyſtem of religion more ſublime, and of ethics more perfect, than any which our faculties were ever able to diſcover; but which, when diſcovered, are exactly conſonant to our reaſon; and that therefore we ſhould not haſtily reject thoſe informations which they have vouchſafed to give us, of which our reaſon is not a competent judge.’

By the truth of theſe doctrines, he evidently means the credibility of them; but what he means by the exact conſonance of thoſe which are diſcovered [165] to our reaſon, we do not underſtand. It is from the want of ſuch conſonance, neceſſarily ariſing from the myſterious nature of ſuch doctrines, that we deduce the incompetency of reaſon to judge of their truth.

But men, as our author juſtly obſerves, may very reaſonably believe propoſitions to be true, of whoſe truth, nevertheleſs, they are no competent judges. "If an able mathematician," ſays he, ‘proves to us the truth of ſeveral propoſitions by demonſtrations, which we underſtand, we heſitate not on his authority to aſſent to others, the proceſs of whoſe proofs we are not able to follow: why therefore ſhould we refuſe that credit to Chriſt and his apoſtles, which we think reaſonable to give to one another.’

[166]Why? indeed! It is very unreaſonable: they doubtleſs deſerve our credit.—But ſtill we recur again to the authenticity of the hiſtory of the goſpel and the interpretation of its doctrines. Admitting, therefore, the propriety of placing the utmoſt confidence in the veracity of Chriſt and his apoſtles, and that what they really meant to inculcate is worthy of all acceptation, ſtill, we ſay, the cautious and candid Chriſtian may, without the immediate direction of divine grace, remain at a loſs what to believe.

As to what genuine Chriſtianity requires us to believe; here again we plead for the ſame neceſſary latitude in matters of faith, as we have before done in morals *. Indeed, our author [167] is, in this reſpect, and very juſtly, a latitudinarian too: for though he hath reduced the Chriſtian's creed, as before obſerved, to a very ſmall compaſs, he hath, by ſo doing, opened a wide field for ſcepticiſm. And yet ſo far are the dictates of genuine Chriſtianity, even in our opinion, conſonant with reaſon, that, as it requires nothing which is impracticable to be performed, ſo it requires nothing, which is impoſſible to be believed.

‘But how ſhall ſuch a ſhort-ſighted Being as man know what is, or is not impoſſible?’—True; he may be conſcious of what is impracticable, as [168] that regards himſelf, but he Cannot preſcribe impoſſibilities to God; of whoſe omnipotence he is no judge. To infinite power every thing is poſſible, except, indeed, inconſiſtency or ſelf-contradiction. Every propoſition, therefore, reſpecting the deity, that doth not involve a contradiction in terms, however improbable or apparently impoſſible, may yet be really poſſible, and therefore believed on proper evidence, powerful perſuaſion, or the influence of divine grace: whereas no kind or degree of evidence, no power of perſuaſion, no influence human or divine can poſſibly make any man believe a contradiction in terms.

This is one of thoſe impracticabilities which reſpects himſelf. Of the incompatibility of facts he may not be a competent judge; but of the incongruity of his own deas, he cannot but be ſenſible. To a direct contradiction-in-terms, [169] therefore, he cannot give his unfeigned aſſent, though to the moſt egregious falſehood or palpable contrariety-in-fact, he may.

This diſtinction between a contrariety-in-fact and a contradiction-in-terms, we conceive, has not ſufficiently been attended to. The one is popular, and phyſical; conſiſting of natural inconſiſtency and moral improbabilities; the other philoſophical and logical, conſiſting of artificial inconſiſtencies and verbal incongruities. Hence, however incompetent human reaſon may be, to determine of poſſibilities in nature and probabilities in providence, it is competent to judge of the agreement and diſagreement of its own ideas. Words, therefore, being the artificial ſigns of our ideas, a contradiction-in-terms becomes obviouſly and [170] certainly diſcaverable, whilſt a contrariety-in-facts is not.

The greateſt falſehoods in fact, hence frequently paſs for inconteſtible and demonſtrable truths, on thoſe who would immediately detect a direct contradiction in terms.—To illuſtrate this diſtinction by a familiar elucidation. A man as totally ignorant of the Copernican ſyſtem as even the learned formerly were, might be told that the ſun is much bigger than the earth and does not move round it every twentyfour hours, as it appears to do; the earth only moving imperceptibly rounds its own axis and carrying round with it every thing adhering to its ſurface with great rapidity.

An aſtronomer, we ſay, might tell an ignorant man this, who might either believe it, confiding in the aſtronomer's veracity, although it ſeemed [171] contrary to the evidence of his ſenſes; or he might diſbelieve and even deny it, confiding more in that evidence, he might ſay, ‘I cannot be perſuaded out of my ſenſes; I can ſee the ſize of the ſun, and ſee it goes round the earth, which I alſo perceive ſtands all the while ſtockſtill. It is impoſſible that I and every body about me ſhould be whiſked round with ſuch velocity without our perceiving it.’—If therefore, he ſhould believe the aſtronomer's aſſertion, however true it be in reality, he would believe, what we call, a contrariety-in-fact, viz. that things really are, as he perceives they are not. The ſame illuſtration holds good reſpecting the exiſtence of ſoul and body, matter and ſpirit, of which, it is popularly ſuppoſed, we have poſitive prooſ or indubitable demonſtration; [172] whereas we have nothing more than the imperfect evidence of our ſenſations and perceptions; which are ſo far from directly affording us demonſtration of any thing, that they are conſtantly and egregiouſly deceiving us in almoſt every thing.

It will follow from the eſtabliſhment of this diſtinction that, however juſtifiable men of diſcernment may be in their diſbelief or denial of inconſiſtent or ſelf-contradictory propoſitions, the very limited extent of their knowledge in the works of nature and the ways of providence, diſqualifies them from taking upon them abſolutely to deny improbable and even apparently impoſſible facts.

Another diſtinction, which here offers itſelf to our conſideration, is that, between believing the truth of a doctrine (or the believing that a doctrine [173] is true) and the belief of that doctrine itſelf.

For a man may very properly be ſaid to believe the truth of a propoſition (in other words, that ſuch propoſition is true) although the doctrine or declaration, it contains, appears doubtful, nay although the terms of ſuch propoſition be totally unintelligible: in which latter caſe he certainly cannot with any propriety be ſaid to believe the propoſition or doctrine itſelf.

The learned and ingenious author of a late plea for the divinity of Chriſt *, lays down in form, indeed, the following propoſition: ‘The belief of a propoſition does not neceſſarily imply a clear idea of the object of which the propoſition affirms any thing.’ So that in this caſe a man may be ſaid to [174] believe a propoſition he does not underſtand. But to this we cannot ſubſcribe: a clear idea is certainly required as well of the ſubject as the predicate, though not a full or adequate idea. The idea entertained of God by a philoſopher and that attached to the ſame term by an ignorant clown, are widely different: the one, magnificent and extenſive as human ſcience can teach or imagination conceive; the other mean and confined as ignorance and dulneſs can dictate. We will yet venture to ſay they are both equally clear; nay, we conceive the confined idea of the clown may be the cleareſt, as being more definite, in coming nearer the preciſion of our ideas of material objects. This very preciſion, indeed, is more deſtroyed by the effulgence of too much light than by the obſcurity attending the want of it; even as the face of the [175] moon is ſeen clearer than that of the ſun.

No doctrine or propoſition, therefore, can, in our opinion, be actually believed, unleſs it be clearly underſtood; and yet propoſitions which are not clearly underſtood, nay not underſtood at all, may comprehend a truth, or may be true; and "that they do "ſo," is a propoſition that may be believed.

A man may believe, as already obſerved, a contrariety in fact, a great falſehood, ſupported by competent evidence or credible affirmation; ſo may he with equal propriety and on the ſame grounds believe the truth of a myſterious or even unintelligible propoſition; or that ſuch a propoſition is true.

But then this is not the propoſition he believes; this is quite a new one, [176] viz, ‘That the ſaid myſterious or unintelligible propoſition is true,’ which new propoſition is neither myſterious nor unintelligible, and therefore may be believed .

Thus a magiſtrate or officer who adminiſters affidavits ex officio and knows not the contents, may, on the credit and veracity of the deponent, believe the truth of his depoſition, or that the contents of ſuch depoſition are true; but he cannot with any propriety [177] priety be ſaid to believe ſuch affidavit itſelf or the contents of ſuch depoſition, becauſe he knows not what thoſe contents are and therefore can believe nothing about them.

Theſe diſtinctions lead us naturally to a third, which, we flatter ourſelves, may tend to conciliate the minds of polemical diſputants; or, at leaſt, to abate their rancour, which too often prevails between the orthodox and heterodox in religious diſputes: and this is the diſtinction, before hinted at, between the faith of the Chriſtian and the belief of the Philoſopher.

The former does not require a rational conviction of the propoſition believed; whereas the belief of a philoſopher not only requires rational conviction, founded on poſitive evidence, but it requires alſo a clear and preciſe comprehenſion of all the terms of the [178] propoſition laid down, On the contrary the unfeigned aſſent, or voluntary ſubmiſſion of reaſon, to the truth of a propoſition, whoſe terms are not even perfectly underſtood, is ſufficient to entitle a Chriſtian to rank among the number of the faithful *. But a philoſopher, who makes every thing ſubmit to reaſon, cannot believe either that which he does not clearly conceive, or that of which he is not as clearly convinced.

Should he, as a man, be induced, by any means or motives, to give up the authority of his reaſon in matters where human reaſon is incompetent, he would do this, not as a Philoſopher, but as a Chriſtian, and of eourſe be entitled to all the privileges and immunities attached to that character.

[179]Of theſe our author has given an encouraging enumeration.—Unhappily for unbelievers, they require a proof of the truth of even thoſe advantages, or, what would anſwer the ſame end, a belief or perſuaſion of their reality. There can be no doubt but this would be ſufficient to make them immediately adopt an expedient, ſo admirably calculated to promote their eaſe and happineſs. But whence is ſuch belief or perſuaſion to be derived? From reaſon? Surely not; unleſs the truth of the Chriſtian religion could be much more rationally proved than by, what this writer calls, demonſtration.

But what, we aſk again, is demonſtration? And what is its influence? Intuition is not demonſtration; inſtinct is not demonſtration; perception [180] is not demonſtration, nor is conceit demonſtration; and yet intuitive or inſtinctive impulſe, the force of imagination or firm perſuaſion, may have equal influence on the mind, with that of the cleareſt demonſtration.

This influence, however, is of another kind; and, though it be not rational, it has often a greater effect over even rational creatures than the moſt clear and preciſe of rational deductions. We experience this, even in the common concerns of life: in the more uncommon, the force of inclination and the power of imagination, are ſo notoriouſly known to overpower the ſtrongeſt of our reaſoning faculties, that it were abſurd to ſupport the credit of demonſtration in caſes, where even demonſtration itſelf muſt give way to prejudice and prepoſſeſſion.—And if to prejudice and prepoſſeſſion, ſurely [181] to the operation of Grace, and the influence of divine inſpiration!

That ſomething more than the mere exerciſe of reaſon, or even a good-will, or inclination to believe, appears neneceſſary from our author's own confeſſion.

"There are people," ſays he, ‘who from particular motives have determined with themſelves, that a pretended revelation founded on ſo ſtrange and improbable a ſtory, ſo contradictory to reaſon, ſo adverſe to the world and all its occupations, ſo incredible in its doctrines, and in its precepts ſo impracticable, can be nothing more than the impoſition of prieſtcraft upon ignorant and illiterate ages, and artfully continued as an engine well-adapted to awe and govern the ſuperſtitious vulgar. To talk to ſuch about the [182] Chriſtian religion, is to converſe with the deaf concerning muſic, or with the blind on the beauties of painting: They want all ideas relative to the ſubject, and therefore can never be made to comprehend it; to enable them to do this, their minds muſt be formed for theſe conceptions by contemplation, retirement, and abſtraction from buſineſs and diſſipation, by ill-health, diſappointment, and diſtreſſes; and poſſibly by divine interpoſition, or by enthuſiaſm, which is uſually miſtaken for it. Without ſome of theſe preparatory aids, together with a competent degree of learning and application, it is impoſſible that they can think or know, underſtand or believe, any thing about it. If they profeſs to believe, they deceive others; if they fancy that they believe [183] they deceive themſelves. I am ready to acknowledge, that theſe gentlemen, as far as their information reaches, are perfectly in the right; and if they are endued with good underſtandings, which have been entirely devoted to the buſineſs or amuſements of the world, they can paſs no other judgment, and muſt revolt from the hiſtory and doctrines of this religion. 'The preaching Chriſt crucified was to the Jews a ſtumbling block, and to the Greeks fooliſhneſs;' * and ſo it muſt appear to all, who, like them, judge from eſtabliſhed prejudices, falſe learning, and ſuperficial knowledge; for thoſe who are quite unable to follow the chain of its prophecy, to ſee the beauty and juſtneſs of its moral precepts, and to enter into the [184] wonders of its diſpenſations, can form no other idea of this revelation but that of a confuſed rhapſody of fictions and abſurdities.’

This is ſaying a great deal in diſcredit of a revelation, whoſe divine origin is ſo obvious, and whoſe doctrines are ſo reaſonable as our author pretends. Surely there are no men, of good under ſtandings, ſo entirely devoted to the buſineſs or amuſements of the world, as to be quite unable to form any other idea of revelation than that it is a confuſed rhapſody of fictions and abſurdities.

Granting, indeed, it be ſo, and that the purſuits of this world are ſo totally incompatible with the things of the next; it ſurely affords a ſtrong argument that reaſon is an incompetent judge in every thing relative to the ſyſtem, and that nothing but divine inſpiration [185] can effectually inculcate the dictates of divine revelation!

The admitting, that poſſibly divine interpoſition may be neceſſary to prepare ſome perſons for believing the truths of the Chriſtian religion, is, in fact, admitting that to be true in a degree, and in particular caſes, which we contend for altogether and univerſally.

We are ſorry, however, to find ſuch divine interpoſition put on a footing with ill-health, diſappointment, diſtreſs and even enthuſiaſm.

Not that we conceive the mode of that interpoſition to be confined to unaccountable impulſe or miraculous converſion. Natural means may in this caſe be made the forerunners of ſupernatural effects; nay we will not deny that even enthuſiaſm, or a falſe inſpiration itſelf, may be made the harbinger of the true.

[186]Through even the fooliſhneſs of preaching were unbelievers formerly converted. Learning and ſtudy, alſo, may be made the concomitant means of grace; but we do not conceive they are eſſentially neceſſary to give efficacy to other means or to divine interpoſition itſelf. If they were, it would not appear that God had choſen the fooliſhneſs of this world to confound the wiſe. It would rather be the ſubjecting of divine wiſdom to human ſagacity, and the excluding from Chriſtianity all but learned divines and profound philoſophers.

"And yet," ſays our author, ‘if it be aſked, was Chriſtianity intended only for theſe? I anſwer, No: It was at firſt preached by the illiterate, and received by the ignorant; and to ſuch are the practical, which are the moſt neceſſary parts of it, ſufficiently [187] intelligible: but the proofs of its authority undoubtedly are not, becauſe theſe muſt be chiefly drawn from other parts, of a ſpeculative nature, opening to our inquiries inexhauſtible diſcoveries concerning the nature, attributes, and diſpenſations of God, which cannot be underſtood without ſome learning and much attention. From theſe the generality of mankind muſt neceſſarily be excluded, and muſt therefore truſt to others for the grounds of their belief, if they believe at all.’

"And hence," continues he, ‘perhaps it is, that faith, or eaſineſs of belief, is ſo frequently and ſo ſtrongly recommended in the goſpel; becauſe if men require proofs, of which they themſelves are incapable, and thoſe who have no knowledge on this important ſubject will not [188] place ſome confidence in thoſe who have; the illiterate and unattentive muſt ever continue in a ſtate of unbelief.’

Our author here ſeems to have run away from his argument; the faith recommended in the goſpel and therefore required of Chriſtians by God, may be widely different from that required by men either of themſelves or of others; and, of courſe, the requiſite proofs of the doctrines believed, may be different alſo.

We cannot admit, therefore, this neceſſity of any man's pinning his faith on his neighbour's ſleeve. The moſt ignorant and illiterate man is no farther removed from God, or incapable of receiving the illuminations of grace, than the greateſt philoſopher or the moſt learned divine. So that if men are content with believing only [189] What God requires of them, as neceſſary to ſalvation, they may ſafely rely on him and the ordinary means of providence for inſtruction.

The caſe is different with thoſe, who, to gratify even a laudable curioſity, are inquiſitive about circumſtances and doctrines uneſſential to ſalvation. The object of that curioſity is a worldly object, and, if attained, muſt be attained by worldly means. They who poſſeſs not the means of original purſuit, therefore, muſt be content, as a certain author expreſſes it, ‘to receive the object of it at ſecond hand: but the faith neceſſary to ſalvation is no ſuch ſtale bargain, it is the immediate gift of God.’

Our author would have the inattentive and illiterate receive this gift at the hands of man; and, becauſe uninformed reaſon is not to be depended on in [190] matters of faith, he adviſes them to reſt their dependence on the information of thoſe, who profeſſedly deduce what they know from the exerciſe of their reaſon. "They," ſays he, ‘that is the inattentive and illiterate, ſhould all remember, [what perhaps they never knew] that in all ſciences, even in mathematics themſelves [itſelf] there are many propoſitions, which on a curſory view appear to the moſt acute underſtandings, uninſtructed in that ſcience, to be impoſſible to be true, which yet on a cloſer examination are found to be truths capable of the ſtricteſt demonſtration; and that therefore in diſquiſitions on which we cannot determine without much learned inveſtigation, reaſon uninformed is by no means to be depended on; and from hence they ought ſurely to conclude, That it [191] may be at leaſt as poſſible for them to be miſtaken in diſbelieving this revelation, who know nothing of the matter, as for thoſe great maſters of reaſon and erudition, Grotius, Bacon, Newton, Boyle, Locke, Addiſon, and Lyttleton, to be deceived in their belief: a belief, to which they firmly adhered after the moſt: diligent and learned reſearches into the authenticity of its records, the completion of the prophecies, the ſublimity of its doctrines, the purity of its precepts, and the arguments of its adverſaries; a belief, which they have teſtified to the world by their writings, without any other motive, than their regard for truth and the benefit of mankind.’

In a matter of ſo great importance, we pay no authority even to great names. Without uncharitably queſtioning, [192] however, either the ſincerity or the motives of the ſeveral avowed defenders of Chriſtianity, certain it is that ſome of them have been ſecretly contemners of its doctrines and privately diſbelievers of its divine original.

It is, indeed, juſtly to be ſuſpected that the number of theſe, is much greater than is generally imagined; for, however widely religious infidelity may have ſpread itſelf, moral hypocriſy hath, in the preſent age, kept pace with it.

Religious maſquerading hath, in fact, become ſo general and unbelievers ſo numerous that, they keep one another in countenance, while, with unparallelled effrontery they take off the maſk and openly belie the characters they aſſume. Thus our modiſh Chriſtians wear the plain face of downright heathens, [193] while they retain the domino, or outward garb of Chriſtianity.

This they do, by explaining away, as our author obſerves, the plain and obvious meaning of ſcripture and modelling the articles of faith agreeable to their own imagination. And yet theſe very underminers of genuine Chriſtianity, who are daily ſapping its foundation and preying on its vitals, keep flouriſhing away with their miſrepreſentations of its proſperous and flouriſhing ſtate.

"If Chriſtianity," ſay certain bold Reviewers, in their critique on the pamphlet before us, ‘had been an impoſture, it could never have maintained its credit for almoſt eighteen hundred years, or ſtood the teſt of the moſt acute and accurate examinations of friends and enemies, of wits and infidels, critics and philoſophers [194] of all denominations; ſome fundamental defect, ſome irreconcileable contradiction, or ſome groſs abſurdity muſt have been diſcovered. But this is ſo far from being the caſe, that the more it is conſidered the more it convinces; every new enquiry produces new light, new evidence, and from every freſh attack it gains an additional triumph.’

What an impudent abuſe of the good faith of the Chriſtian reader! what an inſolent attempt to impoſe on his credulity!

Do not theſe very critics themſelves pretend to have diſcovered fundamental defects, irreconcileable contradictions, and groſs abſurdities in the primitive and orthodox tenets of Chriſtianity? Do they not ridicule the doctrine of the Trinity? Do they not deny the [195] Divinity of our Saviour? Do not they reject the tenets of vicarious atonement, juſtification by faith, and almoſt every eſſential article in the Chriſtian creed? And do they ſtill pretend that the mutilation of its very being, is gaining additional triumphs to its cauſe? Shame on ſuch bareſaced irony*!

[196]The real ſtate of the caſe is quite otherwiſe: genuine Chriſtianity, notwithſtanding the vapouring of theſe nominal Chriſtians, being never at ſo low an ebb as it is among our modern rationaliſts; ſurviving chieſly among thoſe who are ridiculed as contemned viſionaries, enthuſiaſts and fanatics. The truth is that, ſo far has pure Chriſtianity been from profiting by the freedom of enquiry, with which its doctrines have of late years been treated, that it has really loſt ground among all the advocates for ſuch enquiry.

[197]It is an idle boaſt that a mere belief in the myſteries of religion will ſtand the teſt of ridicule and defy the powers of rational inveſtigation. Thoſe myſteries themſelves will undoubtedly do it, becauſe they depend not on the credulity or credibility of men, but on the unchangeable promiſes of God. But we ſee daily the moſt plauſible profeſſional characters laughed out of their religion, and even the warmeſt zealots argued out of their zeal *. So that if we were to calculate, to how ſmall a number of people genuine Chriſtianity is at preſent confined, we ſhall have no reaſon to boaſt, with this author, the extent of its propagation and influence; and ſtill much leſs to advance it as a proof of its divine original .

[198]Happily for Chriſtianity it hath a much firmer ſupport in the promiſes of its divine author, than in any rational arguments that can be produced from ſuch circumſtances: and happily for real Chriſtians their faith hath a more unfailing reſource in the operations of divine grace, than in the moſt fertile expedients of human reaſon.

SECT. XIII.

[199]

On his reply to the ſeventh objection. ‘That the whole ſcheme of Revelation is partial, falſe, fluctuating, unjuſt, and unworthy of an omniſcient and omnipotent Author.’

THIS objection is conveyed in ſuch diffuſe and deſultory terms that it amounts to little more than what has before been urged, viz. that the whole is incredible and bears no internal evidence of its divine original.

And, indeed, if we ſuppoſe human reaſon to be a competent judge of the divinity of Revelation, and alſo of what is worthy or unworthy an omniſcient and omnipotent Being, the objection ſtands in its full force.

[200]But we deny this competence, as indeed does our author, who obſerves that though ‘Reaſon is undoubtedly our ſureſt guide in matters which lie within the narrow circle of her intelligence,’ ſhe is greatly deficient when ſhe proceeds farther.

‘God, ſays this ſelf-ſufficient teacher [reaſon] is perfectly wiſe, juſt and good; and what is the inference? That all his diſpenſations muſt be conformable to our notions of perfect wiſdom, juſtice and goodneſs: but it ſhould be firſt proved that man is as perfect, and as wiſe as his Creator, or this conſequence will by no means follow’ *:

But, ſays our author on the ſubject of revelation, her province is only to examine into its authority, and when that is once proved, ſhe has no more to do but to acquieſce in its doctrines?—

[201]We have before hinted that we think reaſon has at leaſt as much to do in the one caſe as in the other; we ſhall now, therefore; only obſerve, on this head, that the Monthly Reviewers conceive it to be a very unguarded and dangerous poſition. "It precludes," ſay they, "and diſcourages all rational inquiry *.

Doubtleſs it does and properly, all rational inquiry on a ſubject that does not admit of rational inquiry.

But, ſay they, ‘if it were purſued it would juſtify the wildeſt enthuſiaſm or ſuperſtition.’—How! will an acquieſcence, or the putting an implicit faith, in the doctrines of the ſcripture, lead to the wildeſt enthuſiaſm and ſuperſtition? Is the human mind, when directed by divine revelation, [202] more apt to err, than when under the ſimple influence of reaſon? *

We have already obſerved that, in our opinion, it is the duty of Chriſtians to ſubmit the dictates of reaſon, as well with reſpect to the authority of the ſcriptures, as the truth of its doctrines, to the influence of divine grace; and it would be but modeſt, in our rival Reviewers, to leave to the author of the foundation of our faith the care of its ſuperſtructure.

They may reſt aſſured that, whatever extravagancies of enthuſiaſm or ſuperſtition men have fallen into, it has not ariſen from their putting an implicit [203] faith in the doctrines of ſcriptures (in other words, from their ſubmitting their reaſon to revelation) but to their indulging, in the pride of their hearts, the wantonneſs of their imagination and trying their reaſonable practices on ſuch doctrines.

SECT. XIV.

General Reflections on the whole argument, and concluſion in favour of univerſal candour, in judging of the faith and morals of others, or the exertion of Chriſtian charity toward all mankind.

HAVING thus aſſigned our reaſons for thinking the human underſtanding a very incompetent judge either of the myſteries of our holy religion, or of the proof of its divine origin; we [204] ſhall add only a few curſory reflections reſpecting the ſtate of the argument in general:

And firſt let us obſerve that were we diſpoſed to take away even the ſlighteſt prop, on which the popular belief of revelation reſts, we might expoſe to the greateſt ridicule thoſe vain boaſtings of vaunting caſuiſts, who, declaring the truths of chriſtianity to be ſit objects of rational inveſtigation, invite the attacks of argument, wit, and ridicule, and boldly bid them defiance. Among theſe we may particularize, as of late the moſt eminent and conſpicuous, that ingenious and juſtly celebrated philoſopher, Dr. Joſeph Prieſtly and his very able coadjutors in the theological repoſitory.

It was with a very bad grace, alſo, the celebrated author of the Divine [205] Legation made a ſimilar boaſt and threw out the ſame defiance againſt the freethinkers; while the civil power was actually up in arms to cruſh one of, the dulleſt, and inoffenſive inſects of the whole tribe; poor old Peter Annet! It was certainly a glorious triumph over infidelity and a fine proof of the clerical faith in the impregnability of the Chriſtian church, the getting a decrepid dotard of eighty, ſentenced to be impriſoned in Newgate, pilloried in the public ſtreets, and condemned to beat hemp in Bridewell for a twelvemonth; and all merely for puſhing a few pitiful pellets, out of the pop-gun of his wretched gooſe-quill, againſt the credibility, of the Moſaic hiſtory of the plagues of Egypt!

Why was not the artillery of the eccleſiaſtical fortreſs levelled at ſome more formidable foe? in their oppoſition [206] to whom thoſe doughty engineers might have reaped ſome credit for their valour (if not for their conduct) and have at leaſt eſcaped the odium, which ever falls on cowards for their cruelty!

They may reſt, however, ſecure: the aſhes of poor Peter will remain quiet in his grave. We dare ſay there was not ſo much ſpirit buried with them, as to cauſe any future diſturbance either to him or them! *

The digniſied eccleſiaſtic abovementioned has been bold enough to ſay, in ſome of his prefaces, that the freethinkers (as they are falſely ſtiled) [207] have had fair-play in the argument? that they have been left at liberty to handle the weapons of offence and defence at pleaſure, and yet have been foiled.

But this is not true. The freethinkers never had fair-play given them, nor in fact do they deſerve it, if it were prudent, in the civil magiſtrate, to indulge them. They are, in general, as little actuated by candour and the love of truth, as their antagoniſts are by the deteſtation of falſhood; and it muſt be owned of the latter, they do, for the moſt part, love a little deception DEARLY!

The writer of this critique can as truly aver his ſincerity as the author of the pamphlet, which is the ſubject of it. He can truly ſay that, with the moſt ardent deſire of reconciling revelation to reaſon, he long and laboriouſly [208] attached himſelf to the ſtudy of the ſcriptures and the reading of the commentators: that, with the moſt earneſt with to find the doctrines of chriſtianity true, and its divine origin morally evident, he attended with the utmoſt candour, to the authorities of ancient hiſtorians and the arguments of modern reaſoners.

And yet, though early inſtructed to pay the moſt profound reverence and put the moſt implicit faith in the orthodox doctrines of Chriſtianity, the more cloſely he applied the criterion of reaſon the more clearly did that criterion appear to be inapplicable. The farther advances he made in human ſcience the leſs compatible he found it with divine knowledge.

He felt, by no means, the force of argument reſpecting the divine miſſion of our Saviour, either from the [209] completion of prophecies or the effect of miracles. The hiſtory of the former ſeemed too problematical and legendary, while the latter appeared to have had much leſs effect, than they might reaſonably be ſuppoſed to have, on the very perſons who were eye-witneſſes of them.

It appeared to him that the credit of Chriſtianity was ſo little eſtabliſhed, and even the name of its divine inſtitutor ſo little known, in its very birthplace and infancy, that the magiſtrates themſelves ſpeak of one Jeſus *, as of [210] an obſcure and unheard-of ſtranger; and of his ſacrifice on the croſs, as a doubtful event.

It appeared to him that if there were any thing ſupernatural in the propagation of Chriſtianity, it lay in its ſubſequent progreſs in oppoſition to the incredulity of the times, and the inefficacy of the miracles of Chriſt and his apoſtles to diffuſe a more general and earlier belief. Next to this he conceived the ſtrongeſt proof that [211] could be brought of the divine origin, and of a ſupernatural interpoſition in the eſtabliſhment of Chriſtianity, is that the enormous wickedneſs of its later profeſſors, the flagitious, the inhuman methods of propagating it, together with the apparent abſurdities, contained in its myſterious tenets, have not been able to bring it altogether into diſcredit even in the moſt ſcientific ages and with the moſt rational and humane nations of the world.

Here is, indeed, the appearance of ſomething ſupernatural; the fulfilling of the divine founder's promiſe to the Chriſtian church that the gates of hell ſhall not prevail againſt it. It is to an over-ruling providence and the irreſiſtible power of grace in the completion of this promiſe, as before obſerved, more than to the ſtrongeſt rational [212] arguments, that Chriſtianity owes its permanence and protection.

Depended its ſacred myſteries on the force of reaſon, what can be more rationally advanced in defence of the incarnation of Jeſus, than of the incarnanations of Viſtnou? Depended they on rational arguments in favour of their truth? What could reaſonably be ſaid in favour of a God, the author of life, becoming ſubject to mortality? To his being born, of a woman, though not begot by a man? To his dying the death of a ſinner to atone for the ſins of the ſaints, to his deſcending into hell, and his aſcending again to heaven, to reaſſume, after all, the priſtine glory of the Deity!

If there be any thing, in any religion, more revolting to human reaſon than this, we are unacquainted with [213] the greateſt apparent abſurdities in the known world.

If we are aſked then, whether as mere rational beings, we can believe ſuch propoſitions? we frankly anſwer, no.—And yet, experimentally convinced how ſhort is the line of the human underſtanding, how inadequate the ſtrongeſt powers of ſenſe and genius to penetrate the veil of nature and of providence, we can readily ſubmit our reaſon to revelation, and give our unfeigned aſſent, as Chriſtians, to the truth of propoſitions, which, as men. and philoſophers, we can neither fully underſtand nor clearly conceive.—Believing though not on any rational conviction, that faith, or as our author properly deſcribes it, an aſſent to the eſſential doctrines of Chriſtianity, is a religious duty enjoined every man, who lives under the diſpenſation of the [214] goſpel, we believe, even as men, ſo much of them as we comprehend; perſuaded that even what we do not comprehend, would command our belief, if we did, in the ſame proportion.

We can unfeignedly do this, even while the truth, as it is called, of ſuch myſterious propoſitions appears doubtful, nay while even the terms of ſuch propoſitions appear in part or altogether unintelligible.

It is a favorite maxim with our modern rationaliſts (or as ſome call them divines) that ‘where myſtery begins religion ends.’ This maxim is, in our opinion, ſo far from being applicable to the Chriſtian religion, that we think the faith of the Chriſtian applicable chieſly to its myſteries, with which it begins and ends.

[215]There would, indeed, be ſomething myſterious in the promulgation even of the morals of Chriſtianity, if we could be brought to believe the practice of them in their declared purity to be in our preſent ſtate required of us; a practice ſo diametrically oppoſite to the gratification of the appetites and paſſions of human nature, and even to the laws of juſtice and equity admitted in natural religion.

‘To ſubmit to every inſult, to return good for evil, to love thoſe that hate us, and wiſh well to them that deſpitefully uſe us,’ are tenets ſo contrary as well to our natural impatience of injuries as to our ideas of natural juſtice, that, however the meekſpirited and grace-endowed individual may adopt them in private practice, no community of Chriſtians ever yet [216] dared to admit them into their ſyſtem of civil policy.

As to the Faith of the Chriſtian if it be not exerciſed on the myſteries of his religion, we ſee neither uſe nor merit in his belief. If he believe nothing but what appears rational and probable, nothing but what is evinced by a cloud of witneſſes, and carries with it the cleareſt conviction, in what is it more meritorious than the creed of the ſkeptic or infidel? for even they have their creed.

"Becauſe thou haſt ſeen me (faith our Saviour to Didymus) thou haſt believed bleſſed are they that have not ſeen, and yet have believed."

We think this text perfectly applicable to ſuch as, like our author, are anxious to prove the divine authority of the Scriptures by rational argument: in doing which, we think [217] them juſt as ill employed as, this writer ſays, they would be in pretending to accommodate the ſcriptural doctrines to our natural ideas of rectitude and truth.

The well-diſpoſed reader, therefore, ſubmitting his Reaſon to Revelation, and his belief of its divine origin, as well as of its eſſential doctrines, to a ſuperior mode of conviction, the influence of Grace, would do well patiently to wait the effect of its operation in God's own place and time, and not be importunately anxious for the elucidation of obſcurities, which nothing but divine illumination can illuſtrate.

For, after all, what men generally mean by the truth of the doctrines of revelation, is their conſonance or congruity with the deductions of commonſenſe and mere unenlightened reaſon.

[218]The truly-devout need be under no apprehenſion of being guilty of a neglect of religious duty, in thus patiently-waiting for that inſpiration from above, which only can, make them wiſe unto ſalvation.

In the mean time, they ſhould not be ſurprized nor alarmed at finding their notions of divine truths not exactly to coincide with thoſe of other men, of whoſe talents, gifts or graces, they may entertain a higher opinion than they do of their own.

As there are few, if any, perſons in the world, that either hear, ſee or feel external objects exactly alike (our nervous ſyſtems being as diverſified as our features) ſo there are as few that conceive exactly alike the meaning of any one moral or religious propoſition; even divine inſpiration itſelf accommodating [219] its influence to the different faculties of the individual.

This reflection, above all others, ſhould excite us to the exerciſe of that Chriſtian charity, which, covering a multitude of ſins, we ſhould throw, as a veil of univerſal candour, over the miſtakes and errours of the reſt of mankind; juſtly ſuſpecting that, with regard to others more enlightened than ourſelves, we may ſtand in need of the ſame indulgence.

THE END.

REASON AND GRACE, THEOLOGICAL [...]LOGUE.*

[]
DO Chriſtian Heathens ſtill complain,
That infidels our creed profane;
Yet harbour doubts ſo dark and nice
They were in infidels a vice?
Religion, do they ſtill pretend,
Where myſtery begins, muſt end;
And yet affect in revelation
To trace the means of man's ſalvation?—
O'er errour let the truth prevail,
The truth, though treated as a tale.
High on th' imperial throne of grace,
Where angels view their Maker's face,
(As, fondly in imagination
Men give him local habitation,
Tho' nature's univerſal mind
By time and place is unconfin'd)
[222]Through clouds, that canopy his throne,
Seen by the eye of faith alone,
Conceal'd the Chriſtian Deity
Sat veil'd in awful myſtery!
With anxious heart and liſtening ear,
Alternate ſlave to hope and fear,
Devotion blind, a pagan bred,
To viſionary notions led,
With ſpirits of fantaſtic birth
Had peſter'd heav'n and peopled earth.
In ev'ry ſtream, thro ev'ry grove,
Did nayad ſwim or dryad rove;
On ev'ry whirlwind terrour rode,
And ſpoke the preſence of a god;
His breaſt with human paſſions fraught,
As folly dreamt or errour taught;
Till cautious reaſon ſcarce could tell
The gods of heav'n from thoſe of hell.
'Twas now the one true God, ſupreme,
Diſperſing darkneſs like a dream,
From heav'n directed revelation,
Beneath the Chriſtian diſpenſation,
Thoſe truths to teach; which, left alone
To reaſon, MAN had never known:
For 'tis by different means we trace
[223]The works of nature and of grace;
Degen'rate minds in contradiction
Full oft from rational conviction!
Yet Reaſon, piqu'd with envious pride,
At ſight of this tranſcendent guide,
Affected much to ſcorn her aid
And ſcoff'd at the celeſtial maid;
As if, by ſimple nature given
The ſpecial privilege of heaven;
Whence they, who goſpel-truths believe,
The ſame implicitly receive;
By grace intuitively taught,
Without the aid of puzzling thought,
Without the uſe of ſtudied rules,
Without the logic of the ſchools;
Without the means, that art ſupplies,
Or ſcience, making blockheads wiſe!
For human wiſdom here at fault,
Its ſolemn forms are ſet at nought;
While thro the wide world's narrow bounds,
Mere fooliſhneſs the wiſe confounds.
In heaven's own manner, time and place,
Hence Chriſtians wait the call of grace;
Whoſe operation, from on high,
Nor wit, nor learning can ſupply.
[224]
The ſkeptic yet, devoutly vain
Becauſe he bows at nature's fane,
Tho' ne'er the unregen'rate mind,
May nature's GOD behold enſhrin'd,
Perſiſts, with ſcrutinizing eye,
By logic goſpel-truth to try;
To make the ſapience of the ſage
The ſtandard of the ſacred page;
And take, for heaven, in worldly pride,
A carnal, for a ſpiritual, guide.
Hence each, by reaſoning led aſtray,
Perverſely takes a different way;
T [...]o' the ſame chart, they all pretend,
Directs them to their journey's end.
Ceaſe, ye diſcordant ſkeptics ceaſe?
The goſpel is the word of peace:
Its myſt'ries taught the human race
Alone by heav'n-inſpiring grace.
The ſophiſt, poring in the dark,
Still ſyllogizes wide the mark;
The Chriſtian takes the book in hand,
And where he may not underſtand,
Nor heſitates, nor blindly pores;
But reads, believe, admires, adores!
The diff'rence then, with me, admit;
[225]Betwixt divine and human wit:
This but for this world's purpoſe given,
That to direct the way to heaven.
To Caeſar pay great Caeſar's due,
And take his coin for ſterling true;
But dig not Caeſar's richeſt mine,
To mix its ore with gold divine:
Leſt worſe deſigning Chriſtian-Jews
The dangerous precedent abuſe,
Adulterate with new allay,
And clip and ſweat it all away.*

Appendix A ERRATA.

[]
  • Page 6. Note, line 2. for France, having, read France. Having.
  • P. 20. Note, line 6. for expence, read experience.
  • P. 78. line 10. for dubious, read diffident.
  • P. 83. line 1. for the man read that the man.
  • P. 97. Note, line 5. for farce read function.
  • P. 124. line 17. for mankind, read man. lines 19. and 20. tranſpoſe the Comma from of to controuling.
  • P. 175. line ult. for this read that.
  • P. 213. line 1. for greateſt read the greateſt.

Appendix B THE REMARKS, ON MR. JENYNS'S ENQUIRY INTO THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF EVIL,

[]

Advertiſed to be annexed to the foregoing Obſervations, will be inſerted in the next number of the London Review.

Notes
*
This intimation of our author's, puts us in mind of old Greſſet, one of the beauxeſprits, eſprits, and, as he long affected to be thought the eſprits-forts of France, having outlived his paſſions, and almoſt his vanity, (which is ſaying a great deal of a Frenchman) he retired in diſguſt to a monaſtery, and turned enthuſiaſt; alledging, as the ſtrongeſt proof of the propriety of his new creed, the impropriety of his former infidelity.—
Should not a ſtamp upon a thing be rather called an external than internal mark?
*
Think not, Lorenzo, Nature ſtrays
Whene'er the world is in amaze:
For, ſay that miracles there be,
May'nt they be only ſuch to thee?
So many links conceal'd remain,
Which form the complicated chain,
True cauſes and effects between,
In Nature's providential ſcene!
EP. TO LORENZO.
We ſhall take the liberty, in the courſe of this critique, to refer the reader more than once to the Epiſtles to Lorenzo; not to indulge the vanity of an author in quoting from himſelf, but to ſhew that the critick is no new convert; being much of the ſame opinion reſpecting theſe matters, after upwards of twenty years expence and reflection, as he was of, ſo long ago, and at a very early period of life.
*
But if undeniable, why all this trouble to ſtate and explain them?
*
See Page 7.
*
Now, I readily acknowledge, ſays our author, that the Scriptures are not revelations from God; but the hiſtory of them. See View, page 123.
*
The late Dr. Watts.
*
And yet this appears to be all the ſuperiority ſuggeſted, ‘Both the object and the doctrines,’ ſays the author, ‘are not only infinitely ſuperior to, but totally unlike every thing, which had ever before entered into the mind of man’. And again, ‘the doctrines of this religion contain ideas &c. quite diſſimilar from any which had ever been thought on, previous to its publication.’—Thus it appears to be in the thought and not in the deed of the myſtery of ſalvation, that, according to this writer, the ſuperiority, contended for, conſiſts.
*
If we believe modern hiſtory, (for which we have certainly as good authority as for the ancient) there have been found ſavage nations (if ſo we may call them) whoſe ſimplicity and purity both of religion and morals have been remarkable.
The plain Peruvian, pure in heart,
Strange to the guile and guilt of art,
Unaw'd by tenet, text or tale,
Erects his temple in the vale,
Sacred to th' univerſal mind,
The guardian-God of human-kind!
No firſtlings here affront the ſkies,
No clouds of ſmoaking incenſe riſe;
No hypocrite with doubtful face,
No convert, tortur'd into grace,
No ſolid ſkull, in wiſdom's cowl,
No hooded hawk, nor ſolemn owl,
Nor blind nor ominous invade
This ſpotleſs conſecrated ſhade:
But, like the native of the ſpray,
Man hails his Maker, with the day;
By nature taught, Heav'n aſks no more,
In ſpirit and in truth adore!
EP. TO LOR.
*
Rouſſeau ſomewhere obſerves that the univerſal philanthropy of thoſe coſmopolites who have neither love for their relations, friendſhip for their neighbours nor partiality for their country, is juſtly to be ſuſpected; even as he who has no love for himſelf can hardly be ſuppoſed to love all mankind. And yet Rouſſeau was a warm advocate for the purity of the Chriſtian morality.
They are insfact equally conſtitutional, as above hinted; and, it is preſumed are not badly illuſtrated by the following poetical alluſion.
The Fountain is thy favorite theme,
That trickles forth, a ſhallow ſtream,
In murmurs ſoft, a purling rill!—
What wilt thou do, to work thy mill?
How wilt thou make to ride, at large,
Thy timber or thy loaded barge?—
As much as purling rills admired
The navigable ſtream's required;
The ſtream, whoſe turbulence abides
The roaring of the ſwelling tides;
Alike whoſe raging boſom ſwells,
And back the threatening tide repels.—
Hence, to the Valiant and the Brave
Giv'n half the world, the reſt to ſave!
EP. TO LOR.
*
Surely this is inconſiſtent! Ay and No too can never be good divinity.’
*
Meaning an humble, tractable, and candid diſpoſition, a truſt in God, and confidence in his promiſes. See page 71.
*
See Dr Prieſtley's Introduction to Hartley's Eſſays on Man.
*
Whether from Nature's general law.
The outlines of our creed we draw,
Or think the truth be only given
In revelation pure from Heaven,
It matters not, unleſs we find
Some active index in the mind,
Some ray of grace, a purer light,
To point or here or there aright.
EP. TO LOR.
*
The clergy are much obliged to the writer for putting their power on a par, and of courſe, making them, what they ought to be, a match for the devil.
Atleaſt, if its doctrine obtained a hearing, and for a while a very partial reception, they were ſoon obſcured and obliterated; while religion and philoſophy were conſigned to oblivion together. ‘When Minerva could no longer protect her city. it was forſaken by good fortune, and would have lingered in decay, but the barbarians interpoſed, and ſuddenly completed its downfal. Athens itſelf was pillaged by Goths, and. its libraries conſumed. Devaſtation reigned within and ſolitude without its walls’. A ſituation in which, according to Dr Chandler, it remains to this day, notwithſtanding the ſucceſſive efforts of Chriſtian emperors, and pontiffs, by croiſades and holy wars, to effect its eſtabliſhment.
*
That ſenſible and diſcerning traveller, Mrs Miller, remarked in particular the arch ſneer of the Roman pontiff, while he performed the ceremony of ſerving at table, and waſhing the feet, of the poor prieſts, in the ſarce of the holy week.
*
See View, page 107.
*
See View, page III.
*
See page 74.
*
See page II. Indeed the ſuggeſtion that any thing ſhould be credible in proportion to its being incomprehenſible, is, in itſelf, a proof how far the human genius can ſoar into the myſterious and ſublime. Why, therefore, ſuppoſe it ſo incapable of inventing myſterious and ſublime religious ſyſtems?
Genius, Lorenzo, yours or mine,
Faint image of a power divine;
Endow'd with ev'n creative power
To form the Beings of an hour,
To people worlds, to light the ſkies,
To bid a new creation riſe;
O'er all to wield the thunderer's rod,
And act the momentary God!
Ep. To Lor.
*
See View, page to.
*
See View, page. 115.
See View, p. 118.
*
Does our author make a diſtinction between progreſs in knowledge and progreſſion in Science, that human reaſon is admitted to be incapable of one and not of the other? Or does he mean by progreſſion in Science, of which reaſon is incapable, the ſtarting ab initio, which he confines to ſupernatural communication? In either caſe there is an apparent contradiction.
*
No Atheiſt e'er was known on earth,
Till fiery zealots gave him birth,
For controverſy's ſake their trade;
Damning the heretic they made.
Of the firſt cauſe, or fools or wiſe
The pure exiſtence none denies;
Tho' in its eſſence few agree:
For who defines INFINITY!
EP. TO LOR.
*
The Rambler, No. 8.
*
Setting aſide the moral and religious pleas uſually adduced in proof of a future ſtate; the ſtrong probability of it is plauſibly urged, in the eighth epiſtle to Lorenzo, on the ſimpleſt plea.
To animals of every kind
Are their peculiar powers aſſign'd;
To actuate, ſtrengthen, or reſtrain;
Nor ſenſe nor inſtinct giv'n in vain?
Man, a mere animal confeſs'd,
Is yet diſtinguiſh'd from the reſt;
His pow'rs, his views, his labours here,
Preſumptive of a brighter ſphere!
Say, why is knowledge giv'n, to raiſe
Our wonder to our Maker's praiſe?
Why are we taught our God t' adore,
If ſeen in death his face no more?—
It cannot be.—Of heav'nly birth,
Science, deſcending to the earth,
To man hath Jacob's ladder given;
Reaching, an angel's flight, to heaven!
Is it, becauſe we know not why,
So ſad a thing for once to die?
Is it ſo hazardous, my friend,
On God, our maker, to depend?
That God, to whom we being owe,
Our friend and guardian here below;
Who all along the vale of life,
In ev'ry ſcene of care and ſtrife,
Affords his providential arm,
To raiſe beneath, or ſhield from, harm?
Is it for him ſo hard to ſave
That conſcious Being from the grave?—
Secure, Lorenzo, in the power,
That wak'd me at my natal hour,
To me and mine, in life ſo juſt,
On him in death I mean to truſt;
Safe in the hollow of his hand,
Fearleſs to fall by whom I ſtand,
Of whom I kiſs the chaſtening rod,
And bleſs the father in the GOD.
EP. TO LOR:
See View, page 123.
*
See View, page 131.
*
John xv. 19.
John viii. 23.
Rom. xii. 2.
§
Cor. ii. 6.
Jam. iv. 4.
*
Rom. xii. 18.
But are ſelf-mortification, penance, the loving one's enemies, the renouncing one's property and even one's life; are theſe eaſy or light?—We believe that, however they may have been required of particular perſons on particular occaſions, the general impoſition of ſuch unneceſſary commands have only ſerved to diſguſt the well-diſpoſed and ſincere Chriſtian, and to fill the world with hypocrites.
*
This paſſage has been urged in proof of our Saviour's giving up all pretenſions to perſonal divinity. But the contrary is plain, on the ſlighteſt reflection. This Queriſt, who ſeems to have poſſeſſed all the ſpirit of the Phariſees, came, forſooth, with his "good maſter," in oppoſition to thoſe humble believers, who ſaluted Jeſus by the title of Lord; to which they had no need to add the epithet of good.—Our Saviour, who read the hearts of men, and never wanted ſhrewdneſs of reply, queſtioned him therefore, why, on the preſumption he was addreſſing a mere man, he called him good, an epithet applicable only to God. So far, therefore, is this paſſage from making againſt our Saviour's aſſerting his own divinity, it proves that he did ſo, in an inſtance, where, without any impeachment of his title, he might have neglected it.
*
See View, page 149.
*
See View, page 149.
View, page 159.
*
See Section XII.
*
Some writers, indeed, and thoſe of celebrity, have imagined a ſcale of beings, riſing up from the meaneſt of God's creatures to the Creator himſelf; but we always regarded this as groundleſs and viſionary.
Thy pride, Lorenzo diſbelieve;
Let Locke nor Addiſon deceive.
For tho creation's varied plan
Aſſigns degrees reſpecting man;
Yet humbly know, and learn to fear
GOD is beyond this mortal ſphere!
Created beings, tho his care,
Doth he with them cteation ſhare?
Oh! no: the ſyſtem all his own,
God, the creator, ſtands alone:
At equal diſtance all his plan,
The mite, the ſeraph, and the man!
EP. TO LOR.
*
By nonſenſe nor deceit miſled
The honeſt heart and ſober head;
Some meaning, poſitive and plain,
A creed believ'd muſt needs contain:
A parrot elſe, if none deceive her,
A ſound and orthodox believer;
As much convine'd as e'er was yet,
Your Athanaſian paroquet!
EP. TO LOR.
*
See a Moral Demonſtration of the Truth of the Chriſtian Religion, firſt printed in the year 1660, lately reprinted for Cadell, Page 53.
*
See the following Section.
*
That any three lines might do, properly diſpoſed, though not equal: indeed this alluſion is by no means adequate, and but little pertinent.
*
We call it a neceſſary latitude; becauſe, to whatever purity of faith or morals hypocriſy may pretend, men always deceive themſelves or others, when they affect to have a command, over their reaſon and paſſions, which they can derive from no reſource either of Nature or Grace; the only ſprings of human reflection and action
*
Mr Robinſon:
It has been frivolouſly objected that ‘a mathematician, who demonſtrates the truth of any propoſition, does not believe it to be true; he knows it to be ſo.’ True, he does not only believe it to be true, he does more, he alſo knows it to be ſo; he believes not only the truth of the propoſition, but the propoſition itſelf. Knowledge includes belief, though belief does not include knowledge.
*
Agreeable to our author's deſcription of the nature of faith, See page 79.
*
1 Cor. i. 26.
*
We ſhould not think it worth while to notice here even this groſs miſrepreſentation of things, by ſuch anonymous critics; as they are at preſent ſunk deſervedly ſo low in the general eſteem of the public: but, as they have heretofore ſtood in much higher eſtimation, and perſons, ignorant of their degeneracy, might put the ſame confidence in them as formerly, we think a land-mark ſhould be placed on the accumulating ſhoal, leſt the unwary mariner ſhould ſuppoſe himſelf in a deep when he is barely floating on a ſhallow. If any of their old friends are deſirous to remain undeceived, we leave them to make their own diſcovery; in which caſe they will find themſelves much in the ſituation of Sancho Pancha, when, his aſs being ſtolen from under him, while he was aſleep, he waked and found himſelf mounted merely on a pack-ſaddle.
*
Ridicule, though not the teſt of truth, is thus often the teſt of our adherence to it.
It muſt be owned, indeed, that our author does not much boaſt of its preſent ſtate. Comparing it with the ancient, he ſays, ‘If it is aſked, why ſhould not the belief of the ſame religion now produce the ſame effect? the anſwer is ſhort, becauſe it is not believed:’ VIEW page 156. The writer's meaning is plain, though not accurately expreſſed, unleſs an indirect anſwer only was intended to the queſtion.
*
See View, p. 175.
*
Monthly Review, for June 1776. p. 472.
*
Theſe learned and ingenious gentlemen (if indeed any gentleman, ingenious or learned, ſtill continues to write in the Mouthly Review) ſeems to think that Reaſon has ſtill wilder imaginations than thoſe imputed to it by our author.
*
We are aſſured that a late Archbiſhop of Canterbury thought the puniſhment of this poor man ſo much greater than his crime, that he allowed him a ſtipend for life, after he had ſubmitted to, and undergone, the ſentence of the law.
*
Acts, xxv. 19. It is true that this depreciating mode of expreſſion is uſed by Feſtus, a new governor juſt come into office; but it does not appear that King Agrippa himſelf, whom Paul compliments with being expert in all cuſtoms and queſtions then among the Jews, knew any thing more of this Jeſus than the governour, Paul, indeed, would fain have perſuaded him that he knew much more of the matter than he did, or at leaſt would ſeem to do: he could not perſuade him, however, to acknowledge himſelf a Chriſtian, when he was not. For that ſeems to be the true meaning of the paſſage, as it ſeems the boldneſs and artfulneſs of the inſinuation, cauſed Agrippa to get up and walk away.
*
The reader, who has not been offended at the few verſes, quoted in the foregoing pages, will not be diſpleaſed at the inſertion of this apologue, firſt prefixed to the fourth edition of the epiſtles to Lorenzo before-mentioned.
*
It has been objected that this apprehenſion is groundleſs, if the ſcriptural promiſes reſpecting the ſtability of the Chriſtian church, are to be depended on. But this objection is founded on miſapprehenſion. A particular people may forfeit, thro' infidelity, their title to that church, without affecting its general ſtability or proſperity, as experience hath evinced. There cannot, alſo, be a more fatal prognoſtic of Chriſtianity's forſaking any country than its being reduced to a mere name among its pretended profeſſors; for ſuch, we preſume, is the paganized Chriſtianity, as Biſhop W. calls it; prevailing in the preſent day.
Distributed by the University of Oxford under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License

Citation Suggestion for this Object
TextGrid Repository (2020). TEI. 4659 Observations on Soame Jenyns s View of the internal evidence of the Christian religion addressed to its almost Christian author By W Kenrick LL D. University of Oxford Text Archive. . https://hdl.handle.net/21.T11991/0000-001A-613A-6