SKETCHES OF THE HISTORY OF MAN.
VOLUME III.
SKETCHES OF THE HISTORY OF MAN.
IN FOUR VOLUMES.
By HENRY HOME, Lord KAIMS, Author of Elements of Criticiſm, &c.
VOLUME III.
DUBLIN: Printed for JAMES WILLIAMS, No. 5, SKINNER-ROW. M,DCC,LXXIV.
SKETCHES OF THE HISTORY OF MAN.
BOOK II.
Progreſs of MEN in SOCIETY.
[]SKETCH IX.
MILITARY Branch of GOVERNMENT.
DURING the infancy of a nation, every member depends on his own in⯑duſtry for procuring the neceſſaries of life: he is his own maſon, his own taylor, his own phyſician; and on himſelf he chiefly relies for offence as well as defence. Every ſavage can ſay, what few beggars among us can ſay, Omnia mea mecum porto; and hence the apti⯑tude of a ſavage for war, which makes little alte⯑ration in his manner of living. In early times accordingly, the men were all warriors, and every known art was exerciſed by women; which is [2] the caſe at preſent of American ſavages. And even after arts were ſo much improved as to be exerciſed by men, none who could bear arms were exempted from war. In feudal governments, the military ſpirit was carried to a great height: all gentlemen were ſoldiers by profeſſion; and every other art was deſpiſed, as low, if not con⯑temptible.
Even in this untoward ſtate, arts made ſome progreſs, not excepting thoſe for amuſement; and many conveniencies, formerly unknown, became neceſſary to comfortable living. A man cannot bear to be deprived of the conveniencies and amuſements to which he is accuſtomed: he hates war, and clings to the ſweets of peace. Hence the neceſſity of a military eſtabliſhment, hard⯑ening men by ſtrict diſcipline to endure the fa⯑tigues of war. By ſtanding armies, war is carried on more regularly and ſcientifically than in feudal governments; and as it is carried on with infinite⯑ly greater expence; nations are more reſerved in declaring war than formerly. Long experience has at the ſame time made it evident, that a nation ſeldom gains by war; and that agriculture, ma⯑nufactures, and commerce, are the only ſolid foundations of power and grandeur. Theſe arts accordingly have become the chief objects of European governments, and the only rational cau⯑ſes of war. Among the warlike nations of Greece and Italy, how would it have ſounded, that their effeminate deſcendants would employ ſoldiers by profeſſion to fight their battles? And yet this is neceſſary, in every country where arts and manu⯑factures flouriſh; which, requiring little exerciſe, tend to enervate the body, and of courſe the mind. Gain, at the ſame time, being the ſole object of induſtry, advances ſelfiſhneſs to be the ruling paſſion, and brings on a timid anxiety about [3] property and ſelf-preſervation. Cyrus, tho' flaming with reſentment againſt the Lydians for revolting, liſtened to the following ſagacious ad⯑vice, offered by Croeſus, their former King. ‘"O Cyrus, deſtroy not Sardis, an ancient city, famous for arts and arms; but, pardoning what is paſt, demand all their arms, encourage lux⯑ury, and exhort them to inſtruct their children in every art of gainful commerce. You will ſoon ſee, O King, that inſtead of men, they will be women."’ The Arabians, a brave and generous people, conquered Spain, and drove into the inacceſſible mountains of Biſcay and Auſtria, the few natives who ſtood out. When no longer an enemy appeared, they turned their ſwords into plough-ſhares, and became a rich and flouriſhing nation. The inhabitants of the mountains, hard⯑ened by poverty and ſituation, ventured, after a long interval, to peep out from their ſtrong-holds, and to lie in wait for ſtraggling parties. Finding themſelves now a match for a people, whom opu⯑lence had betrayed to luxury, and the arts of peace to cowardice; they took courage to diſplay their banners in the open field; and after many military atchievements, ſucceeded in reconquering Spain. The Scots, inhabiting the mountainous parts of Caledonia, were an overmatch for the Picts, who occupied the fertile plains, and at laſt ſubdued them*.
[4] Where arts, manufactures, and commerce, have arrived at perfection, a pacific ſpirit pre⯑vails univerſally: not a ſpark is left of military ardor, nor will any man be a ſoldier. Hence in ſuch a ſtate, the neceſſity of mercenary troops, hired among nations leſs effeminate, who fight for pay, not for the ſtate they ſerve. Benjamin de Tudele, a Spaniſh Jew, who wrote in the twelfth century, reports, that the Greeks, by luxury and effeminacy, had contracted a degree of ſoftneſs, that made them reſemble women more than men; and that the Greek Emperor was reduced to the neceſſity of employing mercenary troops, to de⯑fend his country againſt the Turks. And accord⯑ingly when, in the year 1453, the city of Con⯑ſtantinople, defended by a garriſon not exceeding 6000 men, was beſieged by the Turks, and re⯑duced to extremity, not a ſingle inhabitant had courage to take up arms, all waiting with torpid deſpondence the hour of utter extirpation. Venice, Genoa, and other ſmall Italian ſtates, became ſo effeminate by long and ſucceſsful commerce, that not a citizen ever thought of ſerving in the army; which obliged them to employ mercenaries, offi⯑cers as well as private men. Theſe mercenaries at firſt fought conſcientiouſly for their pay; but re⯑flecting, that the victors were not better paid than [5] the vanquiſhed, they learned to play booty. In a battle particularly between the Piſans and Flo⯑rentines, which laſted from ſun-riſing to ſun⯑ſetting, there was but a ſingle man loſt, who, having accidentally fallen from his horſe, was trode under foot. Charles VIII. of France, when he invaded Italy anno 1498, underſtood nothing of ſuch mock battles; and his men were held to be devils incarnate, who ſeemed to take delight in ſhedding human blood. The Dutch, who for many years have been reduced to mercenary troops, are more indebted to the mutual jea⯑louſy of their neighbours for their indepen⯑dence, than to their own army. In the year 1672, Lewis of France invaded Holland, and in forty days took forty walled towns. That country was ſaved, not by his army, but by being laid un⯑der water. Froſt, which is uſual at that ſeaſon, would have put an end to the ſeven United Pro⯑vinces.
The ſmall principality of Palmyra is the only inſtance known in hiſtory, where the military ſpirit was not enervated by opulence. Pliny de⯑ſcribes that country as extremely pleaſant, and bleſſed with plenty of ſprings, tho' ſurrounded with dry and ſandy deſerts. The commerce of the Indies was at that time carried on by land; and the city of Palmyra was the centre of that commerce between the Eaſt and the Weſt. Its territory being very ſmall, little more than ſuffi⯑cient for villas and pleaſure-grounds, the inhabi⯑tants, like thoſe of Hamburgh, had no way to employ their richeſs for profit but in trade. At the ſame time, being ſituated between the two mighty empires of Rome and Parthia, it required great addreſs, and the moſt aſſiduous military diſ⯑cipline, to preſerve the inhabitants from being ſwallowed up by the one or the other. This [6] tickliſh ſituation preſerved them from luxury and effeminacy, the uſual concomitants of riches. They made a better figure with their ſuperfluous wealth: they laid it out on magnificent buildings, and adorning their country-ſeats. The fine arts in general, were among them carried to a high degree of perfection. The famous Zenobia, their Queen, led captive to Rome after being de⯑prived of her dominions, was admired and cele⯑brated for ſpirit, for learning, and for an exqui⯑ſite taſte in the fine arts.
Thus, by accumulating wealth, a manufactur⯑ing and commercial people become a tempting object for conqueſt; and by effeminacy become an eaſy conqueſt. The military ſpirit ſeems to be much decayed in Britain; and ere it be gone, will no phantom appear, even in a dream, to diſturb our downy reſt? Formerly, the culture of corn in the temperate regions of Europe and Aſia, proved a tempting bait to northern ſavages who wanted bread: have we no cauſe to dread a ſimi⯑lar fate from ſome warlike neighbour, impelled by hunger, or by ambition, to extend his domi⯑nions? The difficulty of providing for defence, without hurting induſtry, has produced a general opinion among political writers, that a nation, if it will preſerve its military ſpirit, muſt exclude induſtry; and, if it will preſerve its induſtry, muſt give up all hopes of retaining its military ſpirit. In the former caſe, we are ſecure againſt any invader: in the latter, we indeed make a conſiderable figure, but lie open to every invader. Happy would Britain be, could the ſpirit of war and of commerce be made compatible by ſome mi⯑litary plan, that would protect us againſt enemies, without hurting our induſtry and manufactures. That ſuch a plan is not abſolutely impracticable, will, I hope, appear from what follows; tho' [7] I am far from hoping that it will meet with uni⯑verſal approbation. To prepare the reader, I ſhall premiſe an account of the different military eſtabliſhments that exiſt, and have exiſted, in Europe, with the advantages and diſadvantages of each. In examining theſe, who knows whether ſome hint may not occur of a plan more perfect than any of them.
The moſt illuſtrious military eſtabliſhment of antiquity is that of the Romans, by which they ſubdued almoſt all the known world. The Roman citizens were many of them huſbandmen, and all of them ſoldiers. The inhabitants of Rome, in particular, lived upon their pay when in the field; but if they happened not to be ſuc⯑ceſsful in plundering, they had no means of li⯑ving at home. An annual diſtribution of corn among them became neceſſary, which in effect correſponded to the halfpay of our officers. It is believed, that ſuch a conſtitution would not be adopted by any modern ſtate. It was a forc'd conſtitution; contrary to nature, which gives different diſpoſitions to men, in order to ſupply hands for every neceſſary art. It was, at the ſame time, extremely precarious, there being in it no medium between univerſal conqueſt and the moſt wretched ſlavery. Had the Gauls, who conqured Rome, entertained any view but of plunder, Rome would never have been more heard of. It was on the brink of ruin in the war with Hannibal. What would have happened had Hannibal been victorious? It is eaſy to judge, by comparing it with Carthage. Carthage was a commercial ſtate, the people all employ'd in arts, manufactures, and navigation. The Carthaginians were ſubdued; but they could not be reduced to extremity, while they had acceſs to the ſea. In fact, they pro⯑ſpered ſo much by commerce, even after they [8] were ſubdued, as to raiſe jealouſy in their maſters, who thought themſelves not ſecure while a houſe remained ſtanding in Carthage. On the other hand, what reſource for the inhabitants of Rome, had they been ſubdued? They muſt have periſh⯑ed by hunger; for they could not work. In a word, ancient Rome reſembles a gameſter who ventures all upon one deciſive throw: if he loſe, he is undone.
I take it for granted, that our feudal ſyſtem will not have a ſingle vote. It was a ſyſtem that led to confuſion and anarchy, as little fitted for war as for peace. And as for mercenary troops, it is unneceſſary to bring them again into the field, after what is ſaid of them above.
The only remaining forms that merit attention, are a ſtanding army, and a militia; which I ſhall examine in their order, with the objections that lie againſt each. The firſt ſtanding army in modern times was eſtabliſhed by Charles VII. of France, on a very imperfect plan. By an edict anno 1448, he appointed each pariſh to furniſh an archer: theſe were termed franc-archers, becauſe they were exempted from all taxes. This little army was intended for reſtoring peace and order at home, not for diſturbing neighbouring ſtates. This good prince had been forced into many peri⯑lous wars, ſome of them for reſtraining the tur⯑bulent ſpirit of his vaſſals, and moſt of them for defending his crown againſt a powerful adverſary, Henry V. of England. As theſe wars were car⯑ried on in the feudal manner, the ſoldiers, who had no pay, could not be reſtrained from plunder⯑ing; and inveterate practice rendered them equal⯑ly licentious in peace and in war. Charles, to leave no pretext for free quarters, laid upon his [9] ſubjects a ſmall tax, ſufficient for regular pay to his little army*.
Firſt attempts are commonly crude and defec⯑tive. The franc-archers, diſperſed one by one in different villages, and never collected but in time of action, could not eaſily be brought under re⯑gular diſcipline. They were idle when not in the field; and in the field, they diſplayed nothing but vicious habits, a ſpirit of lazineſs, of diſorder, and of pilfering. Neither in peace were they of any uſe: their character of ſoldier made them deſpiſe agriculture, without being qualified for war: in the army they were no better than peaſ⯑ants: at the plough, no better than idle ſoldiers. But in the hands of a monarch, a ſtanding army is an inſtrument of power, too valuable ever to be abandoned: if one ſovereign entertain ſuch an army, others in ſelf-defence muſt follow the ex⯑ample. Standing armies are now eſtabliſhed in every European ſtate, and are brought to a com⯑petent degree of perfection.
This new inſtrument of government, has pro⯑duced a wonderful change in manners. We now [10] rely on a ſtanding army, for defence as well as offence: none but thoſe who are trained to war, ever think of handling arms, or even of defending themſelves againſt an enemy: our people in ge⯑neral have become altogether effeminate, terrifi⯑ed at the very ſight of a hoſtile weapon. It is true, they are not the leſs qualified for the arts of peace; and if manufacturers be protected from being obliged to ſerve in the army, I diſcover not any incompatibility between a ſtanding army and the higheſt induſtry. Huſbandmen at the ſame time make the beſt ſoldiers: a military ſpirit in the lower claſſes ariſes from bodily ſtrength, and from affection to their natal ſoil: both are emi⯑nent in the huſbandman: conſtant exerciſe in the open air renders him hardy and robuſt; and fond⯑neſs for the place where he finds comfort and plenty, attaches him to his country in general*. An artiſt or manufacturer, on the contrary, is [11] attached to no country but where he finds the beſt bread; and a ſedentary life, enervating his body, renders him puſillanimous. For theſe reaſons, among many, agriculture ought to be honoured and cheriſhed above all other arts. It is not only a fine preparation for war, by breeding men who love their country, and whom labour and ſobriety fit for being ſoldiers; but is alſo the beſt founda⯑tion for commerce, by furniſhing both food and materials to the induſtrious.
But ſeveral objections of the moſt intereſting nature occur againſt a ſtanding army, that call aloud for a better model than has hitherto been e⯑ſtabliſhed, at leaſt in Britain. The ſubject is of importance, and I hope for attention from every man who loves his country. During the vigour of the feudal ſyſtem, which made every land-proprietor a ſoldier, every inch of ground was te⯑naciouſly diſputed with an invader: and while a ſovereign retained any part of his dominions, he never loſt hopes of recovering the whole. At preſent, we rely entirely on a ſtanding army, for defence as well as offence, which has reduced e⯑very nation of Europe to a very precarious con⯑dition. If the army of a ſtate happen to be de⯑feated, [12] even at the moſt diſtant frontier, there is little reſource againſt a total conqueſt. Compare the hiſtory of Charles VII. with that of Lewis XIV. Kings of France. The former, tho' dri⯑ven into a corner by Henry V. of England, and deprived of the bulk of his provinces, was howe⯑ver far from yielding: on the contrary, relying on the military ſpirit of his people, and indefati⯑gably intent on ſtratagem and ſurpriſe, he reco⯑vered all he had loſt. When Lewis XIV. ſuc⯑ceeded to the crown, the military ſpirit of the people, was contracted within the narrow ſpan of a ſtanding army. Behold the conſequence. That ambitious monarch, having provoked his neighbours into an alliance againſt him, had no reſource againſt a more-numerous army, but to purchaſe peace by offering to abandon all his con⯑queſts, upon which he had laviſhed much blood and treaſurea. France at that period contain⯑ed ſeveral millions capable of bearing arms; and yet was not in a condition to make head againſt a diſciplined army of 70,000 men. Poland, which continues upon the ancient military eſta⯑bliſhment, wearied out Charles XII. of Sweden, and had done the ſame to ſeveral of his predeceſ⯑ſors. But Saxony, defended only by a ſtanding army, could not hold out a ſingle day againſt the prince now mentioned, at the head of a greater army. Mercenary troops are a defence ſtill more feeble, againſt troops that fight for glory, or for their country. Unhappy was the invention of a ſtanding army; which, without being any ſtrong bulwark againſt enemies, is a grievous burthen on the people; and turns daily more and more ſo. Liſten to a firſt-rate author on that point. ‘"Sitot qu' un etat augmente ce qu' il appelle ſes [13] troupes, les autres augmentent les leurs; de façon qu'on ne gagne rien par̄la que la ruine commune. Chaque monarque tient ſur pied toutes les armées qu'il pourroit avoir ſi ſes peuples étoient en danger d'être exterminées; et on nomme paix cet état d'effort de tous contre tous. Nous ſommes pauvres avec les richeſſes et le commerce de tout l'univers; et bientôt à force d'avoir des ſoldats, nous n'au⯑rons plus que des ſoldats, et nous ſerons com⯑me de Tartares* b."’
But with reſpect to Britain, and every free nation, there is an objection ſtill more formida⯑ble; which is, that a ſtanding army is dangerous to liberty. It avails very little to be ſecure againſt foreign enemies, ſuppoſing a ſtanding army to af⯑ford ſecurity, if we have no ſecurity againſt an enemy at home. If a warlike king, heading his own troops, be ambitious to render himſelf abſo⯑lute, there are no means to invade the impending blow; for what avail the greateſt number of effe⯑minate cowards againſt a diſciplined army, de⯑voted to their prince, and ready implicitly to ex⯑ecute his commands? In a word, by relying en⯑tirely on a ſtanding army, and by truſting the [14] ſword in the hands of men who abhor the re⯑ſtraint of civil laws, a ſolid foundation is laid for military government. Thus a ſtanding army is dangerous to liberty, and yet no ſufficient bul⯑wark againſt powerful neighbours.
Deeply ſenſible of the foregoing objections, Harrington propoſes a plan for a militia, which he holds to be unexceptionable. Every male be⯑tween eighteen and thirty, is to be trained to mi⯑litary exerciſes, by frequent meetings, where the youth are excited by premiums to contend in running, wreſtling, ſhooting at a mark, &c. &c. But Harrington did not advert, that ſuch meet⯑ings, enflaming the military ſpirit, muſt create an averſion in the people to dull and fatiguing la⯑bour. His plan evidently is inconſiſtent with in⯑duſtry and manufactures: it would be ſo at leaſt in Britain. A moſt ſucceſsful, plan it would be, were defence our ſole object; and not the leſs ſucceſsful, by rendering Britain ſo poor as ſcarce to be a tempting conqueſt. Our late war with France is a conſpicuous inſtance of the power that can be exerted by a commercial ſtate, entire in its credit; a power that amaz'd all the world, and ourſelves no leſs than others. Politicians be⯑gin to conſider Britain, and not France, to be the formidable power that threatens univerſal monar⯑chy. Had Harrington's plan been adopted, Bri⯑tain, like Sweden or Denmark, muſt have been contented with an inferior ſtation, having no am⯑bition but to draw ſubſidies from its more potent neighbours.
In Switzerland, it is true, boys are, from the age of twelve, exerciſed in running, wreſtling, and ſhooting. Every male who can bear arms is regimented, and ſubjected to military diſcipline. Here is a militia in perfection upon Harrington's plan, a militia neither forced nor mercenary; in⯑vincible [15] when fighting for their country: and as the Swiſs are by no means an idle people, we learn from this inſtance, that the martial ſpirit is not an invincible obſtruction to induſtry. But the original barrenneſs of Switzerland, compel⯑led the inhabitants to be ſober and induſtrious: and induſtry hath among them become a ſecond nature, there ſcarcely being a child above ſix years of age but who is employed, not excepting children of opulent families. England differs widely in the nature of its ſoil, and of its peo⯑ple. At the ſame time, there is little occaſion to inſiſt upon that difference; as Switzerland af⯑fords no clear evidence, that a militia gives no obſtruction to a ſpirit of induſtry: the Swiſs, it is true, may be termed induſtrious; but their in⯑duſtry is confined to neceſſaries and convenien⯑cies: they are leſs ambitious of wealth than of military glory; and they have few arts or ma⯑nufactures, either to ſupport foreign commerce, or to excite luxury.
Fletcher of Salton's plan of a militia, differs little from that of Harrington. Three camps are to be conſtantly kept up in England, and a fourth in Scotland; into one or other of which, every man muſt enter upon compleating his one and twentieth year. In theſe camps the art of war is to be acquired and practiſed: thoſe who can maintain themſelves muſt continue there two years, others but a ſingle year. Secondly, thoſe who have been thus educated, ſhall for ever after have fifty yearly meetings, and ſhall exerciſe four hours every meeting. It is not ſaid, by what means young men are compelled to reſort to the camp; nor is any exception mentioned of perſons deſtined for the church, for liberal ſci⯑ences, or for the fine arts. The weak and the ſickly muſt be exempted; and yet no regulation [16] is propoſed againſt thoſe who abſent themſelves on a falſe pretext. But waving theſe, the capi⯑tal objection againſt Harrington's plan ſtrikes equally againſt Fletcher's, That by rouſing a mi⯑litary ſpirit, it would alienate the minds of the people from arts and manufactures, and from any conſtant and uniform occupation. The author himſelf remarks, that the uſe and exerciſe of arms, would make the youth place their honour upon that art, and would enflame them with love of military glory; not adverting, that love of military glory, diffuſed through the whole maſs of the people, would unqualify Britain for being a manufacturing and commercial country, rendering it of little weight or conſideration in Europe.
The military branch is eſſential to every ſpe⯑cies of government: the Quakers are the only people who ever doubted of it. Is it not then mor⯑tifying, that a capital branch of government, ſhould to this day remain in a ſtate ſo imperfect? One would ſuſpect ſome inherent vice in the na⯑ture of government, that counteracts every effort of genius to produce a more perfect mode. I am not diſpoſed to admit any defect of Providence, eſpecially in an article eſſential to the well-being of ſociety; and rather than yield to the charge, I venture to propoſe the following plan, even at the hazard of being thought an idle projector. And what animates me greatly to make the at⯑tempt is, a firm conviction, that a military and an induſtrious ſpirit are of equal importance to Britain; and that if either of them be loſt, we are undone. To reconcile theſe ſeeming anta⯑goniſts, is my chief view in the following plan; to which I ſhall proceed, after paving the way by ſome preliminary conſiderations.
[17] The firſt is, that as military force is eſſential to every ſtate, no man is exempted from bearing arms for his country: all are bound; becauſe none can be bound, if every one be not bound. Were any difference to be made, perſons of fi⯑gure and fortune ought firſt to be called to that ſervice, as being the moſt intereſted in the wel⯑fare of their country. Liſten to a good ſoldier delivering his opinion on that ſubject. ‘"Les levées qui ſe font par ſupercherie font tout auſſi odieuſes; on met de l'argent dans la po⯑chette d'un homme, et on lui dit qu'il eſt ſol⯑dat. Celles qui ſe font par force, le font en⯑core plus; c'eſt une deſolation publique, dont le bourgeois et l'habitant ne ſe ſauvent qu'a force d'argent, et dont le fond eſt toujours un moyen odieux. Ne voudroit-il pas mieux établer, par une loi, que tout homme, de quelque condition qu'il fût, ſeroit obligé de ſervir ſon prince et ſa patrie pendant cinq ans? Cette loi ne ſçauroit être deſapprovée, parce qu'il eſt naturel et juſte que les citoyens s'em⯑ploient pour la défenſe de l'état. Cette me⯑thode de lever des troupes ſeroit un fond in⯑épuiſable de belles et bonnes recrues, qui ne ſeroient pas ſujetes a déſerter. L'on ſe feroit même, par la ſuite, un honneur et un devoir de ſerver ſa tâche. Mais, pour y parvenir, il faudroit n'en excepter aucune condition, être ſévére ſur ce point, et s'attacher a faire exé⯑cuter cette loi de préférence aux nobles et aux riches. Perſonne n'en murmureroit. Alors ceux qui auroient ſervi leur temps, verroient avec mépris ceux qui repugneroient à cette loi, et inſenſiblement on ſe feroit un honneur de ſervir: le pauvre bourgeois ſeroit conſolé par [18] l'exemple du riche; et celui-ci n'oſeroit ſe plaindre, voyant ſervir le noblea *."’
Take another preliminary conſideration. While there remained any portion of our original mar⯑tial ſpirit, the difficulty was not great of recruit⯑ing the army. But that taſk hath of late years become extremely troubleſome; and more diſa⯑greeable [19] ſtill than troubleſome, by the neceſſity of uſing deceitful arts for trepanning the unwary youth. Nor are ſuch arts always ſucceſsful: in our late war with France, we were neceſſitated to give up even the appearance of voluntary ſer⯑vice, and to recruit the army on the ſolid princi⯑ple of obliging every man to fight for his country: the juſtices of peace were empowered by the le⯑giſlature, to force into the ſervice ſuch as could be beſt ſpared from civil occupation. If a ſingle clauſe had been added, limiting the ſervice to five or ſeven years, the meaſure would have been unexceptionable, even in a land of liberty. To relieve officers of the army from practiſing de⯑ceitful arts for recruiting their corps, by ſubſti⯑tuting a fair and conſtitutional mode, was a valua⯑ble improvement. It was of importance with re⯑ſpect to its direct intendment; but of much greater with reſpect to its conſequences. One of the few diſadvantages of a free ſtate, is licenti⯑ouſneſs in the common people, who may wallow in diſorder and profligacy without control, if they be but cautious to refrain from groſs crimes, pu⯑niſhable by law. Now, as it appears to me, there never has been deviſed a method more ef⯑ficacious for reſtoring induſtry and ſobriety, than that under conſideration. Its ſalutary effects were conſpicuous, even during the ſhort time it ſub⯑ſiſted. The dread of being forced into the ſer⯑vice, rendered the populace peaceable and order⯑ly: it did more; it rendered them induſtrious in order to conciliate favour. The moſt beneficial diſcoveries have been accidental: without having any view but for recruiting the army, our legi⯑ſlature ſtumbled upon an excellent method for re⯑claiming the idle and the profligate; a matter, in the preſent depravity of manners, of greater importance than any other that concerns the po⯑lice [20] of Britain. A perpetual law of that kind, by promoting induſtry, would prove a ſovereign remedy againſt mobs and riots, diſeaſes of a free country, full of people and of manufactures*. Why were the foregoing ſtatutes, for there were two of them, limited to a temporary exiſtence? There is not on record another ſtatute better in⯑titled to immortality.
And now to the project, which, after all my efforts, I produce with trepidation; not that I doubt of its ſolidity, but as ill ſuited to the pre⯑ſent manners of this iſland. To hope that it will be put in practice, would indeed be highly ridi⯑culous: this can never happen, till patriotiſm flouriſh more in Britain than it has done for ſome time paſt. Suppoſing now an army of 60,000 men to be ſufficient for Britain, a rational me⯑thod for raiſing ſuch an army, were there no ſtanding forces, would be, that land-proprietors, in proportion to their valued rents, ſhould fur⯑niſh men to ſerve ſeven years, and no longer§. But as it would be no leſs unjuſt than imprudent, to diſband at once our preſent army, the ſoft and natural way is, to begin with moulding gra⯑dually [21] the old army into the new, by filling up vacancies with men bound to ſerve ſeven years and no longer. And for raiſing proper men, a matter of much delicacy, it is propoſed, that in every ſhire a ſpecial commiſſion be given to cer⯑tain landholders of rank and figure, to raiſe re⯑cruits out of the lower claſſes, ſelecting always thoſe who are the leaſt uſeful at home.
Second. Thoſe who claim to be diſmiſſed af⯑ter ſerving the appointed time, ſhall never again be called to the ſervice, except in caſe of an ac⯑tual invaſion. Every one of them ſhall be in⯑titled to a premium of eight or ten pounds, for enabling him to follow a trade or calling, with⯑out being ſubjected to corporation laws. The private men in France are inliſted but for ſix years; and that mode has never been attended with any inconvenience.
Third. With reſpect to the private men, idleneſs muſt be totally and for ever baniſhed. Suppoſing three months yearly to be ſufficient for military diſcipline, the men, during the reſt of the year, ought to be employed upon public works, forming roads, erecting bridges, making rivers navigable, clearing harbours, &c. &c. Why not alſo furniſh men for half pay to private undertakers of uſeful works? And ſuppoſing the daily pay of a ſoldier to be ten pence, it would greatly encourage extenſive improvements, to have at command a number of ſtout fellows, un⯑der ſtrict diſcipline, at the low wages of five pence a-day. An army of 60,000 men thus em⯑ployed, would not be ſo expenſive to the public, as 20,000 men upon the preſent eſtabliſhment: for beſide the money contributed by private un⯑dertakers, public works carried on by ſoldiers, [22] will be miſerably ill contrived, if not cheaply purchaſed with their pay*.
The moſt important branch of the project, is what regards the officers. The neceſſity of re⯑viving in our people of rank ſome portion of mi⯑litary ſpirit, will be acknowledged by every perſon of reflection; and in that view, the following articles are propoſed. Firſt: That there be two claſſes of officers, one ſerving for pay, one with⯑out pay. In filling up every vacant office of cor⯑net or enſign, the latter are to be preferred; but in progreſſive advancement, no diſtinction is to be made between the claſſes. An officer who has ſerved ſeven years without pay, may retire with honour.
Second. No man ſhall be privileged to repre⯑ſent a county in parliament, who has not ſerved ſeven years without pay; and, excepting an ac⯑tual burgeſs, none but thoſe who have perform⯑ed that ſervice, ſhall be privileged to repreſent a borough. The ſame qualification ſhall be ne⯑ceſſary to every one who aſpires to ſerve the public or the King in an office of dignity, ex⯑cepting only churchmen and lawyers, with regard to offices in their reſpective profeſſions. In old Rome, none were admitted candidates for any civil employment, till they had ſerved ten years in the army.
Third. Officers of this claſs are to be exempt⯑ed from the taxes impoſed on land, coaches, win⯑dows, and plate; not for ſaving a trifling ſum, but as a mark of diſtinction.
[23] The military ſpirit muſt in Britain be miſer⯑ably low, if ſuch regulations prove not effectual to decorate the army with officers of figure and fortune. Nor need we to apprehend any bad con⯑ſequence, from a number of raw officers who ſerve without pay: among men of birth, emula⯑tion will have a more commanding influence than pay or profit; and at any rate, there will always be a ſufficiency of old experienced officers re⯑ceiving pay, ready to take the lead in every dif⯑ficult enterprize.
Fourth. To improve this army in military diſcipline, it is propoſed, that when occaſion of⯑fers, 5 or 6000 of them be maintained by Great Britain, as auxiliaries to ſome ally at war. And if that body be changed from time to time, knowledge and practice in war will be diffuſed through the whole army.
Officers who ſerve for pay, will be greatly be⯑nefited by this plan: frequent removes of thoſe who ſerve without pay, make way for them; and from the very nature of the plan, buying and ſelling is abſolutely excluded.
I proceed to the alterations neceſſary for ac⯑commodating this plan to our preſent military eſtabliſhment. As a total revolution at one in⯑ſtant would breed confuſion, the firſt ſtep ought to be a ſpecimen only, ſuch as the levying two or three regiments on the new model; the ex⯑pence of which ought not to be grudged, as the forces preſently in pay, are not ſufficient, even in peace, to anſwer the ordinary demands of go⯑vernment. And as the proſpect of civil employ⯑ments, will excite more men of rank to offer their ſervice than there is room for, the choice muſt be in the crown, not only with reſpect to the new regiments, but with reſpect to the vacant cornet⯑cies and enſigncies in the old army. But as theſe [24] regulations will not inſtantly produce men qualified to be ſecretaries of ſtate or commiſſioners of treaſury, ſo numerous as to afford his majeſty a ſatisfactory choice, that branch of the plan may be ſuſpended, till thoſe who have ſerved ſeven years without pay, amount to one hundred at leaſt. The article that concerns members of par⯑liament muſt be ſtill longer ſuſpended: it may however, after the firſt ſeven years, receive ex⯑ecution in part, by privileging thoſe who have received no pay to repreſent a borough, refuſing that privilege to others, except to actual burgeſ⯑ſes. We may proceed one ſtep farther, That if in a county there be five gentlemen who have the qualification under conſideration, over and above the ordinary legal qualifications, one of the five muſt be choſen, leaving the electors free as to their other repreſentative.
With reſpect to the private men of the old army, a thouſand of ſuch as have ſerved the longeſt may be diſbanded annually, if ſo many be willing to retire; and in their ſtead an equal num⯑ber may be inliſted, to ſerve but ſeven years. Upon ſuch a plan, it will not be difficult to find recruits.
The advantage of this plan, in one particular, is eminent. It will infallibly fill the army with gallant officers: Other advantages concerning the officers themſelves, ſhall be mentioned afterward. An appetite for military glory cannot fail to be rouſed in officers who ſerve without pay, when their ſervice is the only paſſport to employments of truſt and honour. And may we not hope, that officers who ſerve for pay, will, by force of imi⯑tation, be inſpired with the ſame appetite? No⯑thing ought to be more ſedulouſly inculcated into every officer, than to deſpiſe riches, as a mercan⯑tile object, below the dignity of a ſoldier. Often [25] has the courage of victorious troops been blunted by the pillage of an opulent city; and may not rich captures at ſea have the ſame effect? Some ſea-commanders have been ſuſpected, of beſtow⯑ing their fire more willingly upon a merchantman, than upon a ſhip of war. A triumph, an ovation, a civic crown, or ſome ſuch mark of honour, were in old Rome the only rewards for military atchievements*. Money, it is true, was ſometimes diſtributed among the private men, as an addition to their pay, after a fatiguing campaign; but not as a recompence for their good behaviour, be⯑cauſe all ſhared alike. It did not eſcape the pe⯑netrating Romans, that wealth, the parent of lux⯑ury and ſelfiſhneſs, fails not to eradicate the mi⯑litary ſpirit. The ſoldier who to recover his bag⯑gage performed a bold action, gave an inſtructive leſſon to all governments. Being invited by his general to try his fortune a ſecond time; Invite, ſays the ſoldier, one who has loſt his baggage. Many a bold adventurer goes to the Indies, who, returning with a fortune, is afraid of every breeze. Britain, I ſuſpect, is too much infected with the ſpirit of gain. Will it be thought ridiculous in [26] any man of figure, to prefer reputation and re⯑ſpect before riches; provided only he can afford a frugal meal, and a warm garment? Let us compare an old officer, who never deſerted his friend nor his country, and a wealthy merchant, who never indulged a thought but of gain: the wealth is tempting;—and yet does there exiſt a man of ſpirit, who would not be the officer rather than the merchant, even with his millions? Sultan Mechmet granted to the Janiſaries a pri⯑vilege of importing foreign commodities free of duty: was it his intention to metamorphoſe ſol⯑diers into merchants, loving peace, and hating war?
But though I declare againſt large appointments beforehand, which, inſtead of promoting ſervice, are a temptation to luxury and idleneſs; yet to an officer of character, who has ſpent his younger years in ſerving his king and country, a govern⯑ment, or other ſuitable employment that enables him to paſs the remainder of his life in eaſe and affluence, is a proper reward for merit, reflecting equal honour on the prince who beſtows, and on the ſubject who receives; beſide affording an enlivening proſpect to others, who have it at heart to do well.
With reſpect to the private men, the rotation propoſed, aims at improvements far more impor⯑tant, than that of making military ſervice fall light upon individuals. It tends to unite the ſpirit of induſtry with that of war, and to form the ſame man to be an induſtrious labourer, as well as a good ſoldier. The continual exerciſe recom⯑mended, cannot fail to produce a ſpirit of induſ⯑try; which will occaſion a demand for the private men after their ſeven years ſervice, as valuable above all other labourers, not only for regularity, but for activity. And with reſpect to ſervice in [27] war, conſtant exerciſe is the life of an army, in the literal as well as metaphorical ſenſe. Boldneſs is inſpired by ſtrength and agility, to which con⯑ſtant motion mainly contributes. The Roman citizens, trained to arms from their infancy, and never allowed to reſt, were invincible. To men⯑tion no other works, ſpacious and durable roads carried to the very extremities of that vaſt em⯑pire, ſhow clearly how the ſoldiers were employ⯑ed during peace; which hardened them for war, and made them orderly and ſubmiſſivea. So eſſential was labour held by the Romans for training an army, that they never ventured to face an enemy, with troops debilitated in any degree by idleneſs. The Roman army in Spain, having been worſted in ſeveral engagements, and confin⯑ed within their entrenchments, were ſunk in idleneſs and luxury. Scipio Naſica, after demo⯑liſhing Carthage, taking the command of that army, durſt not oppoſe it to the enemy, till he accuſtomed the ſoldiers to temperance and hard labour. He exerciſed them without relaxation in marching and countermarching, in fortifying camps and demoliſhing them, in digging trenches and filling them up, in building high walls and pul⯑ling them down; he himſelf, from morning to night, going about, and directing every operation. Marius, before engaging the Cimbri, exerciſed his army in turning the courſe of a river. Ap⯑pian relates, that Antiochus, during his winter⯑quarters at Calchis, having married a beautiful virgin, with whom he was greatly enamoured, ſpent the whole winter in pleaſure, abandoning his army to vice and idleneſs: and when the time [28] of action returned with the ſpring, he found his ſoldiers unfit for ſervice. The idleneſs of our ſoldiers in time of peace, promoting debauchery and licentiouſneſs, is no leſs deſtructive to health than to diſcipline. Unable for the fatigues of a firſt campaign, our private men die in thouſands, as if ſmote with a peſtilence*. We never read of any mortality in the Roman legions, though frequently engaged in climates very different from their own. Let us liſten to a judicious writer, to whom every one liſtens with delight: ‘"Nous remarquons aujourd'hui, que nos ar⯑mées périſſent beaucoup par le travail immodé⯑ré des ſoldats; et cependant c'étoit par un tra⯑vail immenſe que les Romains ſe conſervoient. La raiſon en eſt, je croix, que leurs fatigues étoient continuelles; au lieu que nos ſoldats paſſent fans ceſſe d'un travail extreme à une extreme oiſivété, ce qui eſt la choſe du monde la plus propre à les faire perir. Il faut que je rapporte ici ce que les auteurs nous diſent de l'education de ſoldats Romains. On les ac⯑coutumoit [29] à aller le pas militaire, c' eſt-a-dire, à fair en cinq heures vingt milles, et quelque⯑fois vingt-quatre. Pendant ces marches, on leur faiſoit porter de poids de ſoixante livres. On les entretenoit dans l'habitude de courir et de ſauter tout armés; ils prenoient dans leurs exercices des epées, de javelots, de ſlêches, d'une péſanteur double des armes ordinaires; et ces exercices étoient continuels. Des hom⯑mes ſi endurcis étoient ordinairement ſains; on ne remarque pas dans les auteurs que les ar⯑mées Romaines, qui faiſoient la guerre en tant de climats, periſſoient beaucoup par les mala⯑dies; au lieu qu'il arrive preſque continuelle⯑ment aujourd'hui, que des armées, ſans avoir combattu, ſe fondent, pour ainſi dire, dans une campagne* a."’ Mareſchal Saxe, a ſoldier, [30] not a phyſician, aſcribes to the uſe of vinegar the healthineſs of the Roman legions: were vinegar ſo potent, it would of all liquors be the moſt in requeſt. Exerciſe without intermiſſion, during peace as well as during war, produced the ſalutary effect; which every prince will find, who is diſ⯑poſed to copy the Roman diſcipline*. The Ma⯑reſchal gueſſes better with reſpect to a horſe. Diſcourſing of cavalry, he obſerves, that a horſe becomes hardy and healthful by conſtant exerciſe, and that a young horſe is unable to bear fatigue; for which reaſon he declares againſt young horſes for the ſervice of an army.
That the military branch of the Britiſh govern⯑ment is ſuſceptible of improvements, all the world [31] will admit. To improve it, I have contributed my mite; which is humbly ſubmitted to the public, a judge from whom there lies no appeal. It is ſubmitted in three views. The firſt is, Whether an army, modelled as above, would not ſecure us againſt the boldeſt invader; the next, Whether ſuch an army be as dangerous to liberty, as an army in its preſent form; and the laſt, Whether it would not be a ſchool of induſtry and moderation to our people.
With reſpect to the firſt, we ſhould, after a few years, have not only an army of ſixty-thou⯑ſand well-diſciplined troops, but the command of another army, equally numerous, and equally well diſciplined. It is true, that troops inured to war have an advantage over troops that have not the ſame experience: but with aſſurance it may be pronounced impracticable, to land at once in Britain an army that can ſtand againſt 100,000 Britiſh ſoldiers well diſciplined, fighting even their firſt battle, for their country, and for their wives and children.
A war with France raiſes a panic on every ſlight threatening of an invaſion. The ſecurity afforded by a propoſed plan, would enable us to act offenſively at ſea, inſtead of being reduced to keep our ſhips at home, for guarding our coaſts. Would Britain any longer be obliged to ſupport her continental connections? No ſooner does an European prince augment his army, or improve military diſcipline, than his neighbours, taking fright, muſt do the ſame. May not one hope, that by the plan propoſed, or ſome ſuch, Britain would be relieved from jealouſy and ſolicitude a⯑bout its neighbours?
With reſpect to the ſecond view, having long enjoyed the ſweets of a free government, under a ſucceſſion of mild princes, we begin to forget, [32] that our liberties ever were in danger. But drou⯑ſy ſecurity is of all conditions the moſt dangerous; becauſe the ſtate may be overwhelmed before we even dream of danger. Suppoſe only, that a Bri⯑tiſh King, accompliſhed in the art of war, and beloved by his ſoldiers, heads his own troops in a war with France; and after more than one ſuc⯑ceſsful campaign, gives peace to his enemy, on terms advantageous to his people: what ſecurity have we for our liberties, when he returns with a victorious army, devoted to his will? I am talk⯑ing of a ſtanding army in its preſent form. Troops modelled as above will not be ſo obſequi⯑ous: a number of the prime nobility and gentry ſerving without pay, who can be under no tempta⯑tion to enſlave themſelves and their country, will prove a firm barrier againſt the ambitious views of ſuch a prince. And even ſuppoſing that army to be totally corrupted, the prince can have little hope of ſucceſs againſt the nation ſupported by a⯑nother army, compoſed of men, who, having completed their military ſervice, may be relied on as champions for their country.
And as to the laſt view mentioned, the plan propoſed cannot fail to promote induſtry and vir⯑tue, not only among the ſoldiers, but among the working people in general. To avoid hard la⯑bour and ſevere diſcipline in the army, men will be ſober and induſtrious at home; and ſuch un⯑tractable ſpirits as cannot be reached by the mild laws of a free government, will be effectually tamed by military law. At the ſame time, as ſo⯑briety and innocence are conſtant attendants upon induſtry, the manners of our people would be much purified; a circumſtance of infinite impor⯑tance to Britain. The ſalutary influence of the plan would reach perſons in a high ſphere. A young gentleman, whipt at ſchool, or falling be⯑hind [33] at college, contracts an averſion to books; and flies to the army, where he is kept in coun⯑tenance by numbers, idle and ignorant like him⯑ſelf. How many young men are thus daily ruin⯑ed, who, but for the temptation of idleneſs and gaiety in the army, would have become uſeful ſubjects! In the plan under conſideration, the officers who ſerve for pay would be ſo few in number, and their proſpect of advancement ſo clear, that it would require much intereſt to be admitted into the army. None would be admit⯑ted but thoſe who had been regularly educated in every branch of military knowledge; and idle boys would be remitted to their ſtudies.
Here is diſplayed an agreeable ſcene with rela⯑tion to induſtry. Suppoſing the whole threeſcore thouſand men to be abſolutely idle; yet, by dou⯑bling the induſtry of thoſe who remain, I affirm, that the ſum of induſtry would be much greater than before. And the ſcene becomes enchanting, when we conſider, that theſe threeſcore thouſand men, would not only be of all the moſt induſtri⯑ous, but be patterns of induſtry to others.
Upon concluſion of a foreign war, we ſuffer grievouſly by diſbanded ſoldiers, who muſt plun⯑der or ſtarve. The preſent plan is an effectual remedy: men accuſtomed to hard labour under ſtrict diſcipline, can never be in want of bread: they will be ſought for every where, even at higher than ordinary wages; and they will prove excellent maſters for training the pleaſants to hard labour.
A man indulges emulation more freely in be⯑half of his friends or his country, than of himſelf: the latter is ſelfiſh; the former proceeds from a ſocial principle. In that view, have we not rea⯑ſon to hope, that the ſeparating military officers into different claſſes, will excite a laudable emu⯑lation, [34] prompting individuals to exert themſelves on every occaſion, for the honour of their corps? Nor will ſuch emulation, a virtuous paſſion, be any obſtruction to private friendſhip between members of different claſſes. On the contrary, may it not be expected, that young officers of birth and fortune, zealous to qualify themſelves, at their own expence, for ſerving their country, will cling for inſtruction to officers of experience, who have no inheritance but perſonal merit? Both find their account in that connection: men of rank become adepts in military affairs, a valua⯑ble branch of education for them; and officers who ſerve for pay, acquire friends at court, who will embrace every opportunity of teſtifying their gratitude.
The advantages mentioned are great and ex⯑tenſive; and yet are not the only advantages. Will it be thought extravagant to hope, that the propoſed plan would form a better ſyſtem of edu⯑cation for young men of fortune, than hitherto has been known in Britain? Before pronouncing ſentence againſt me let the following conſidera⯑tions be duly weighed. Our youth go abroad to ſee the world in the literal ſenſe; for to pierce deeper than eye-ſight, cannot be expected of boys. They reſort to gay courts, where they find nothing for imitation but pomp, luxury, diſſembled virtues, and real vices: ſuch ſcenes make a deep impreſſion on young men of a warm imagination. Our plan would be an antidote to ſuch poiſonous education. Suppoſing eighteen to be the earlieſt time for the army, here is an ob⯑ject held up to our youth of fortune, for rouſing their ambition: they will endeavour to make a figure, and emulation will animate them to excel: ſuppoſing a young man to have no ambition, ſhame alone will puſh him on. To acquire the [35] military art, to diſcipline their men, to direct the execution of public works, and to conduct other military operations, would occupy their whole time, and baniſh idleneſs. A young gentleman, thus guarded againſt the inticing vices and ſaun⯑tering follies of youth, muſt be ſadly deficient in genius, if, during his ſeven years ſervice, reading and reflection have been totally neglected by him. Hoping better things from our youth of fortune, I take for granted, that during their ſervice they have made ſome progreſs, not only in military knowledge, but in morals, and in the fine arts, ſo as at the age of twenty-five to be qualified for profiting, inſtead of being undone, by ſeeing the world*.
Further, young men of birth and fortune, ac⯑quire indeed the ſmoothneſs and ſuppleneſs of a court, with reſpect to their ſuperiors; but the conſtraint of ſuch manners, makes their temper break out againſt inferiors, where there is no conſtraint. Inſolence of rank is not ſo viſible in Britain, as in countries of leſs freedom; but it is ſufficiently viſible to require correction. To that end, no method promiſes more ſucceſs than mili⯑tary ſervice; as command and obedience alter⯑nately, are the beſt diſcipline for acquiring tem⯑per and moderation. Can pride and inſolence be [36] more effectually ſtemmed, than to be command⯑ed by an inferior?
Still upon the important article of education. Where pleaſure is the ruling paſſion in youth, intereſt will be the ruling paſſion in age: the ſelf⯑iſh principle is the foundation of both, the object only is varied. This obſervation is ſadly verified in Britain: our young men of rank, loathing an irkſome and fatiguing courſe of education, aban⯑don themſelves to pleaſure. Trace theſe very men through the more ſedate part of life, and they will be found graſping at power and profit, by means of court-favour, with no regard to their country, and with very little regard to their friends. The education propoſed, holding up a tempting prize to virtuous ambition, is an excel⯑lent fence againſt a life of indolent pleaſure. A youth of fortune, engaged with many rivals in a train of public ſervice, acquires a habit of buſi⯑neſs; and as he is conſtantly employed for the public, patriotiſm becomes his ruling paſſion*.
[37] The advantages of a military education, ſuch as that propoſed, are not yet exhauſted: one of conſiderable importance remains to be unfolded. Under regular government promoting the arts of peace, ſocial intercourſe refines, and fondneſs for company increaſes in proportion. And hence it is, that the capital is crouded with every perſon who can afford to live there. A man of fortune, who has no taſte but for a city life, happens to be forced into the country by buſineſs: finding buſineſs and the country equally inſipid, he be⯑comes impatient, and returns to town, with a diſguſt at every rural amuſement. In-France, the country has been long deſerted: ſuch fond⯑neſs for ſociety prevails there, that ſeldom has the King occaſion to inflict a greater puniſhment on a man of faſhion, than to baniſh him to his coun⯑try-ſeat. In Britain the ſame fondneſs for a town-life is gaining ground daily. A ſtranger conſidering the immenſe ſums expended in En⯑gland upon country-ſeats, would conclude in ap⯑pearance with great certainty, that the Engliſh ſpend moſt of their time in the country. But how would it ſurpriſe him to be told, not only that people of faſhion in England paſs little of their time in the country, but that the immenſe ſums laid out upon gardening and pleaſure⯑grounds, are the effect of vanity more than of taſte! In fact, ſuch embelliſhments are begin⯑ning to wear out of faſhion; appetite for ſociety leaving neither time nor inclination for rural plea⯑ſures. If the progreſs of that diſeaſe can be ſtayed, the only means is military education. In youth laſting impreſſions are made; and men of fortune who take to the army, being confined moſtly to the country in prime of life, contract a liking for country occupations and amuſements; which withdraw them from the capital, and con⯑tribute [38] to the health of the mind, no leſs than of the body.
A military education would contribute equally to moderation in ſocial enjoyments. The pomp, ceremony, and expence, neceſſary to thoſe who adhere to a court, and live always in public, are not a little fatiguing and oppreſſive. Man is na⯑turally moderate in his deſire of enjoyment; and it requires much practice to make him bear exceſs, without ſatiety and diſguſt. The pain of exceſs, prompts men of opulence to paſs ſome part of their time in a ſnug retirement, where they live at eaſe, free from pomp and ceremony. Here is a retirement, which can be reached without any painful circuit; a port of ſafety and of peace, to which we are piloted by military education, avoiding every dangerous rock, and every fati⯑guing agitation.
Reflecting on the advantages of military educa⯑tion above diſplayed, is it fooliſh to think, that our plan might produce a total alteration of man⯑ners in our youth of birth and fortune? The idlers, the gameſters, the profligate, compared with our military men, would make a deſpicable figure: ſhame, not to talk of pride, would compel them to reform.
How conducive to good government might the propoſed plan be, in the hands of a virtuous king, ſupported by a public-ſpirited miniſtry! In the preſent courſe of advancement, a youth of qua⯑lity who aſpires to ſerve his country in a civil em⯑ployment, has nothing to rely on but parliamenta⯑ry intereſt. The military education propoſed, would afford him opportunity to improve his ta⯑lents, and to convince the world of his merit. Honour and applauſe thus acquired, would intitle him to demand preferment; and he ought to be employed, not only as deſerving, but as an en⯑neglecting [39] couragement to others. Frequent inſtances of neglecting men who are patronized by the public, might perhaps prove dangerous to a Britiſh mini⯑ſter.
If I have not all this while been dreaming, here are diſplayed illuſtrious advantages of the military education propoſed. Fondneſs for the ſubject excites me to prolong the entertainment; and I add the following reflection, on the education of ſuch men as are diſpoſed to ſerve in a public ſta⯑tion. The ſciences are mutually connected; and a man cannot be perfect in any one, without be⯑ing in ſome degree acquainted with every one. The ſcience of politics, in particular, being not a little intricate, cannot be acquired in perfection by any one whoſe ſtudies have been confined to a ſingle branch, whether relative to peace or to war. The Duke of Marlborough made an eminent figure in the cabinet, as well as in the field; and ſuch was equally the illuſtrious Sully, who may ſerve as a model to all miniſters. The great aim in modern politics is, to ſplit government into the greateſt number poſſible of departments, truſting nothing to genius. China is a complete model of ſuch a government. National affairs are there ſo ſimplified by diviſion, as to require ſcarce any capacity in the mandarines. Theſe officers, having little occaſion for activity, either of mind or of body, ſink down into ſloth and ſenſuality: motives of ambition or of fame make no impreſſion: they have not even ſo much delicacy as to bluſh when they err: and as they regard no puniſhment but what touches the perſon or the purſe, it is not un⯑uſual to ſee a mandarine beaten with many ſtripes, ſometimes for a very ſlight tranſgreſſion. Let arts be ſubdivided into many parts; the more ſub⯑diviſions the better: but I venture to pronounce, that no man ever did, nor ever will, make a capi⯑tal [40] figure in the government of a ſtate, whether as a judge, a general, or a miniſter, whoſe edu⯑cation is rigidly confined to one ſcience*.
Senſible am I that the foregoing plan is in ſeve⯑ral reſpects imperfect; but if it be ſound at bot⯑tom, poliſh and improvement are eaſy operations. My capital aim has been, to obviate the objections that preſs hard againſt every military plan, hither⯑to embraced or propoſed. A ſtanding army in its preſent form, is dangerous to liberty; and but a feeble bulwark againſt ſuperior force. On the other hand, a nation in which every ſubject is a ſoldier, muſt not indulge any hopes of becoming powerful by manufactures and commerce: it is indeed vigorouſly defended, but is ſcarce worthy of being defended. The golden mean of rotati⯑on and conſtant labour in a ſtanding army, would diſcipline multitudes for peace as well as for war. And a nation ſo defended would be invin⯑cible.
SKETCH X.
PUBLIC POLICE with reſpect to the POOR.
[41]AMONG thoſe nations of Europe where government is a ſcience, that part of public police which concerns the poor, makes now a con⯑ſiderable branch of ſtatute-law. The poor-laws are ſo multiplied, and ſo anxiouſly framed, as to move one to think, that there cannot remain a ſingle perſon wanting bread. It is however a ſad truth, that the diſeaſe of poverty, inſtead of be⯑ing eradicated, has become more and more inve⯑terate. England in particular overflows with beg⯑gars, tho' in no other country are the indigent ſo amply provided for. Some radical defect there muſt be in theſe laws, when, after endleſs attempts to perfect them, they all prove abortive. Every writer, diſſatisfied with former plans, fails not to produce one of his own; which, in its turn, meets with as little approbation as any of the foregoing.
The firſt regulation of the ſtates of Holland concerning the poor, was in the year 1614, pro⯑hibiting all begging. The next was in the year 1649. ‘"It is enacted, That every town, vil⯑lage, [42] or pariſh, ſhall maintain its poor out of the income of its charitable foundations and collections; and in caſe theſe means fall ſhort, the magiſtrates ſhall maintain them at the ge⯑neral expence of the inhabitants, as can moſt conveniently be done: Provided always, that the poor be obliged to work either for mer⯑chants, farmers, or others, for reaſonable wages, in order that they may, as far as poſ⯑ſible, be ſupported that way; provided alſo, that they be indulged in no idleneſs nor inſo⯑lence."’ The advice or inſtruction here given to magiſtrates, is ſenſible; but falls ſhort greatly of what may be termed a law, the execution of which can be inforced in a court of ju⯑ſtice.
In France, the precarious charity of monaſte⯑ries proving ineffectual, a hoſpital was erected in the city of Paris anno 1656, having different apartments; one for the innocent poor, one for putting vagabonds to hard labour, one for found⯑lings, and one for the ſick and maimed; with certain funds for defraying the expence of each, which produce annually much about the ſame ſum. In imitation of Paris, hoſpitals of the ſame kind were erected in every great town of the king⯑dom.
The Engliſh began more early to think of their poor; and in a country without induſtry, the ne⯑ceſſity probably aroſe more early. The firſt Engliſh ſtatute bears date in the year 1496, di⯑recting, ‘"That every beggar unable to work, ſhall reſort to the hundred where he laſt dwelt or was born; and there ſhall remain, upon pain of being ſet in the ſtocks three days and nights, with only bread and water, and then ſhall be put out of town."’ This was a law againſt vagrants, for the ſake of order. There [43] was little occaſion, at that period, to provide for the innocent poor; their maintenance being a burden upon monaſteries. But monaſteries being put down by Henry VIII. there was a ſtatute, 22d year of his reign, cap. 12. impowering the juſti⯑ces of every county, to grant licences to poor aged and impotent perſons, to beg within a certain diſtrict; thoſe who beg without it, to be whipt, or ſet in the ſtocks. In the firſt year of Edward VI. cap. 3. a ſtatute was made in favour of im⯑potent, maimed, and aged perſons, that they ſhall have convenient houſes provided for them, in the cities or towns where they were born, or where they reſided for three years, to be relieved by the willing and charitable diſpoſition of the pariſhioners. By 2d and 3d Philip and Mary, cap. 5. the former ſtatutes of Henry VIII. and Edward VI. were confirmed, of gathering weekly relief for the poor by charitable collections. ‘"A man licenced to beg, ſhall wear a badge on his breaſt and back openly."’
The firſt compulſory ſtatute was 5o Eliſab. cap. 3. empowering juſtices of peace to raiſe a weekly ſum for the poor, by taxing ſuch per⯑ſons as obſtinately refuſe to contribute, after re⯑peated admonitions from the pulpit. In the next ſtatute, 14o Eliſab. cap. 5. a bolder ſtep was made, impowering juſtices to tax the inha⯑bitants of every pariſh, in a weekly ſum for their poor. And taxations for the poor being now in ſome degree familiar, the remarkable ſtatutes, 39o Eliſab. cap. 3. and 43o Eliſab. cap. 2. were enacted, which make the ground-work of all the ſubſequent ſtatutes concerning the poor. By theſe ſtatutes, certain houſe-holders, named by the juſtices, are, in conjunction with the church-wardens, appointed overſeers for the poor; and theſe overſeers, with conſent of two juſtices, [44] are empowered to tax the pariſh in what ſums they think proper, for maintaining the poor.
Among a people ſo tenacious of liberty as the Engliſh are, and ſo impatient of oppreſſion, is it not ſurpriſing, to find a law, that, without cere⯑mony, ſubjects individuals to the arbitrary will of men, who ſeldom either by birth or education de⯑ſerve that important truſt; and without even pro⯑viding any effectual check againſt embezzlement? At preſent, a Britiſh parliament would reject with ſcorn ſuch an abſurd plan; and yet, being familiarized to it, they never ſeriouſly have at⯑tempted a repeal. We have been always on the watch to prevent the ſovereign's encroachments, eſpecially with regard to taxes: but as pariſh-officers are low perſons who inſpire no dread, we ſubmit to have our pockets picked by them, almoſt without repining. There is provided, it is true, an appeal to the general ſeſſions for re⯑dreſſing inequalities in taxing the pariſhioners: but it is no effectual remedy; artful overſeers will not over-rate any man ſo groſsly as to make it his intereſt to complain, conſidering that theſe overſeers have the poor's money to defend them⯑ſelves with. Nor will the general ſeſſions readily liſten to a complaint, that cannot be verified but with much time and trouble. If the appeal have any effect, it will make a ſtill greater inequality, by relieving men of figure at the expence of their inferiors; who muſt ſubmit, having little intereſt to obtain redreſs.
The Engliſh plan, beſide being oppreſſive, is groſsly unjuſt. If it ſhould be reported of ſome diſtant nation, that the burden of maintaining the idle and profligate, is laid upon the frugal and in⯑duſtrious, who work hard for a maintenance to themſelves; what would one think of ſuch a na⯑tion? Yet this is literally the caſe of England. [45] I ſay more: the plan is not only oppreſſive and unjuſt, but miſerably defective in the checking of mal-adminiſtration. In fact, great ſums are levied beyond what the poor receive: it requires brigu⯑ing to be named a church-warden: the nominati⯑on, in London eſpecially, gives him credit at once; and however meagre at the commencement of his office, he is round and plump before it ends. To wax fat and rich by robbing the poor! Let us turn our eyes from a ſcene ſo hor⯑rid*.
Inequality in taxing, and embezzlement of the money levied, which are notorious, poiſon the minds of the people; and impreſs them with a notion, that all taxes raiſed by public authority are ill managed.
Theſe evils are great, and yet are but ſlight compared with what follow. As the number of poor in England, as well as the expence of main⯑tenance, are increaſing daily, proprietors of land, in order to be relieved of a burden ſo grievous, drive the poor out of the pariſh, and prevent all perſons from ſettling in it who are likely to be⯑come a burden: cottages are demoliſhed, and marriage obſtructed. Influenced by the preſent [46] evil, they look not forward to depopulation, nor to the downfall of huſbandary and manufactures by ſcarcity of hands. Every pariſh is in a ſtate of war with every other pariſh, concerning pauper ſettlements and removals.
The price of labour is generally the ſame in the different ſhires of Scotland, and in the different pariſhes. A few exceptions are occaſioned by the neighbourhood of a great town, or by ſome ex⯑tenſive manufacture that requires many hands. In Scotland, the price of labour reſembles water, which alway levels itſelf: if high in any one corner, an influx of hands brings it down. The price of labour varies in every pariſh of England. A labourer who has gained a ſettlement in a pariſh, on which he depends for bread when he inclines to be idle, dares not remove to another pariſh where wages are higher, fearing to be cut out of a ſettlement altogether. England is in the ſame condition with reſpect to labour, that France lately was with reſpect to corn; which, however plentiful in one province, could not be exported to ſupply the wants of another. The pernicious effects of the latter with reſpect to food, are not more obvious, than of the former with reſpect to manufactures.
Engliſh manufactures labour under a ſtill greater hardſhip than inequality of wages. In a country where there is no fund for the poor but what nature provides, the labourer muſt be ſatisfied with ſuch wages as are cuſtomary: he has no re⯑ſource; for pity is not moved by idleneſs. In England, the labourers command the market: if not ſatisfied with cuſtomary wages, they have an excellent reſource; which is, to abandon work altogether, and to put themſelves on the pariſh. Labour is much cheaper in France than in Eng⯑land: I have heard ſeveral plauſible reaſons; but [47] in my opinion, the difference ariſes from the poor⯑laws. In England, every man is entitled to be idle; and every idler is entitled to a maintenance. In France, the funds appropriated to the poor, yield the ſame ſum annually: that ſum is always pre-occupied; and France, with reſpect to all but thoſe on the liſt, approaches to the ſtate of a nation that has no fund provided by law for the poor.
Depopulation, inequality in the price of labour, and extravagant wages, are deplorable evils. But the Engliſh poor-laws are productive of evils ſtill more deplorable: they are ſubverſive both of morality and induſtry. This is a heavy charge, but no leſs true than heavy. Fear of want is the only effectual motive to induſtry with the labour⯑ing poor: remove that fear, and they ceaſe to be induſtrious. The ruling paſſion of thoſe who live by bodily labour, is to ſave a pittance for their children, and for ſupporting themſelves in old age: ſtimulated by deſire of accompliſhing theſe ends, they are frugal and induſtrious; and the proſpect of ſucceſs is to them a continual feaſt. Now what worſe can malice invent againſt ſuch a man, under colour of friendſhip, than to ſecure bread to him and his children whenever he takes a diſlike to work; which effectually deadens his ſole ambition, and with it his honeſt induſtry? Relying on the certainty of a proviſion againſt want, he relaxes gradually till he ſink into idle⯑neſs: idleneſs leads to profligacy: profligacy be⯑gets diſeaſes: and the wretch becomes an object of public charity before he has run half his courſe. Such are the genuine effects of the Engliſh tax for the poor, under a miſtaken notion of charity. There never was known in any country, a ſcheme for the poor more contradictory to ſound policy. Might it not have been foreſeen, that to a grovel⯑ing [48] creature, who has no ſenſe of honour, and ſcarce any of ſhame, the certainty of mainte⯑nance would prove an irreſiſtible temptation to idleneſs and debauchery? The poor-houſe at Lyons contained originally but forty beds, of which twenty only were occupied. The eight hundred beds it contains at preſent, are not ſuffi⯑cient for the poor who demand admittance. A premium is not more ſucceſsful in any caſe, than where it is given to promote idleneſs. A houſe for the poor was erected in a French village, the revenue of which, by oeconomy, became con⯑ſiderable. Upon a repreſentation by the curate of the pariſh, that more beds were neceſſary, the proprietor undertook the management. He ſold the houſe, with the furniture; and to every proper object of charity, he ordered a moderate proportion of bread and beef. The poor and ſick were more comfortably lodged at home, than formerly in the poor-houſe. And by that plan of management, the pariſh-poor decreaſed, inſtead of increaſing, as at Lyons. How few Engliſh manufacturers labour the whole week, if the work of four or five days afford them mainte⯑nance? Is not this a demonſtration, that the malady of idleneſs is widely ſpread? In Briſtol, the pariſh-poor twenty years ago did not exceed four thouſand: at preſent, they amount to more than ten thouſand. But as a malady, when left to itſelf, commonly effectuates its own cure; ſo it will happen in this caſe: when, by prevailing idleneſs, every one without ſhame claims pariſh-charity, the burden will become intolerable, and the poor will be left to their ſhifts.
The immoral effects of public charity are not confined to thoſe who depend on it, but extend to their children. The conſtant anxiety of a labour⯑ing man to provide for his children, endears them [49] to him. Being relieved of that anxiety by the tax for the poor, his affection cools gradually, and he turns at laſt perfectly indifferent about them. Their independence, on the other hand, weans them from their duty to him. And thus, affection between parent and child, which is the corner-ſtone of ſociety, is in a great meaſure ob⯑literated among the labouring poor. In a plan publiſhed by the Earl of Hillſborough, there is an article, obliging parents to maintain their indigent children, and children to maintain their indigent parents. Natural affection muſt indeed be at a low ebb, where ſuch a regulation is neceſſary: but it is neceſſary, at leaſt in London, where it is common to ſee men in good buſineſs neglect⯑ing their aged and diſeaſed parents, for no better reaſon, than that the pariſh is bound to find them bread: Proh tempora, proh mores!
The immoral effects of public charity ſpread ſtill wider. It fails not to extinguiſh the virtue of charity among the rich; who never think of giving charity, when the public undertakes for all. In a ſcheme publiſhed by Mr. Hay, one ar⯑ticle is, to raiſe a ſtock for the poor by voluntary contributions, and to make up the deficiency by a pariſh-tax. Will individuals ever contribute, when it is not to relieve the poor, but to relieve the pariſh? Every hoſpital has a poor-box, which ſeldom produces any thing*. The great comfort of ſociety is aſſiſtance in time of need; [50] and its firmeſt cement is, the beſtowing and re⯑ceiving kindly offices, eſpecially in diſtreſs. Now to unhinge or ſuſpend the exerciſe of chari⯑ty, by rendering it unneceſſary, relaxes every ſo⯑cial virtue, by ſupplanting the chief of them. The conſequence is diſmal: exerciſe of benevo⯑lence to the diſtreſſed is our ſureſt guard againſt the encroachments of ſelfiſhneſs: if that guard be withdrawn, ſelfiſhneſs will prevail, and become the ruling paſſion. In fact, the tax for the poor has contributed greatly to the growth of that gro⯑veling paſſion, ſo conſpicuous at preſent in En⯑gland.
Engliſh authors who turn their thoughts to the poor, make heavy complaints of decaying chari⯑ty, and increaſing poverty: never once drea⯑ming, that theſe are the genuine effects of a legal proviſion for the poor; which on the one hand eradicates the virtue of charity, and on the other is a violent temptation to idleneſs. Wonderfully ill contrived muſt the Engliſh charity-laws be, when their conſequences are to ſap the foundati⯑on of voluntary charity; to deprive the labour⯑ing poor of their chief comfort, that of providing for themſelves and children; to relax mutual af⯑fection between parent and child; and to reward, inſtead of puniſhing, idleneſs and vice. Conſider whether a legal proviſion for the poor, be ſuffici⯑ent to atone for ſo many evils.
No man had better opportunity than Fielding to be acquainted with the ſtate of the poor: let us liſten to him. ‘"That the poor are a very great burden, and even a nuiſance to the kingdom; that the laws for relieving their diſtreſſes, and reſtraining their vices, have not anſwered; and that they are at preſent very ill provided for, and much worſe governed, are truths which every one will acknowledge. Every [51] perſon who hath property, muſt feel the weight of the tax that is levied for the poor; and every perſon of underſtanding, muſt ſee how abſurdly it is applied. So uſeleſs indeed is this heavy tax, and ſo wretched its diſpoſi⯑tion, that it is a queſtion, whether the poor or rich are actually more diſſatisfied, ſince the plunder of the one ſerves ſo little to the real advantage of the other: for while a million yearly is raiſed among the rich, many of the poor are ſtarved; many more languiſh in want and miſery; of the reſt, numbers are found begging or pilfering in the ſtreets to⯑day, and to-morrow are locked up in goals and Bridewells. If we were to make a pro⯑greſs through the outſkirts of the metropolis, and look into the habitations of the poor, we ſhould there behold ſuch pictures of human miſery, as muſt move the compaſſion of every heart that deſerves the name of human. What indeed muſt be his compoſition, who could ſee whole families in want of every ne⯑ceſſary of life, oppreſſed with hunger, cold, nakedneſs, and filth; and with diſeaſes, the certain conſequence of all theſe! The ſuffe⯑rings indeed of the poor are leſs known than their miſdeeds; and therefore we are leſs apt to pity them. They ſtarve, and freeze, and rot, among themſelves; but they beg, and ſteal, and rob, among their betters. There is not a pariſh in the liberty of Weſtminſter, which doth not raiſe thouſands annually for the poor; and there is not a ſtreet in that liberty, which doth not ſwarm all day with beggars, and all night with thieves."’
There is not a ſingle beggar to be ſeen in Pen⯑ſylvania. Luxury and idleneſs have got no footing [52] in that happy country; and thoſe who ſuffer by misfortune, have their maintenance out of the public treaſury. But luxury and idleneſs cannot for ever be excluded; and when they take place, this regulation will be as pernicious in Penſylva⯑nia, as the poor-rates are in Britain.
Of the many propoſals that have been pub⯑liſhed for reforming the poor-laws, not one has pierced to the root of the evil. None of the au⯑thors entertain the ſlighteſt doubt, of a legal pro⯑viſion being neceſſary, tho' all our diſtreſſes ariſe evidently from that very cauſe. Travellers com⯑plain, of being infeſted with an endleſs number of beggars in every Engliſh town; a very different ſcene from what they meet with in Holland or Switzerland. How would it ſurpriſe them to be told, that this proceeds from an overflow of cha⯑rity in the good people of England!
Few inſtitutions are more tickliſh than thoſe of charity. In London, common proſtitutes are treated with ſingular humanity: a hoſpital for them when pregnant, diſburdens them of their load, and nurſes them till they be again fit for buſineſs: another hoſpital cures them of the ve⯑nereal diſeaſe: and a third receives them with open arms, when, inſtead of deſire, they become objects of averſion. Would not one imagine, that theſe hoſpitals have been erected for encouraging proſtitution? They undoubtedly have that effect, tho' far from being intended. Mr Stirling, ſuper⯑intendant of the Edinburgh poor-houſe, deſerves to be kept in perpetual remembrance, for a ſcheme he contrived to reform common proſti⯑tutes. A number of them were confined in a houſe of correction, on a daily allowance of three pence; and even part of that ſmall pittance was embezzled by the ſervants of the houſe. Pin⯑ching hunger did not reform their manners; for [53] being ſo abſolutely idle, they encouraged each o⯑ther in vice, waiting impatiently for the hour of deliverance. Mr Stirling, with conſent of the magiſtrates, removed them to a clean houſe; and inſtead of money, which is apt to be ſquandered, appointed for each a pound of oat meal daily, with ſalt, water, and fire for cooking. Relieved now from diſtreſs, they long for comfort: what would they not give for milk or ale? Work, ſays he, will procure you plenty. To ſome who of⯑fered to ſpin, he gave flax and wheels, engaging to pay them half the price of their yarn, retain⯑ing the other half for the materials furniſhed: The ſpinners earned about nine pence weekly, a comfortable addition to what they had before. The reſt undertook to ſpin, one after another; and before the end of the firſt quarter, they were all of them intent upon work. It was a branch of his plan, to ſet free ſuch as merited that fa⯑vour; and ſome of them appeared ſo thoroughly reformed, as to be in no danger of a relapſe.
The ingenious author of The Police of France, who wrote in the year 1753, obſerves, that not⯑withſtanding the plentiful proviſion for the poor in that kingdom, mentioned above, there was a general complaint, of the increaſe of beggars and vagrants; and adds, that the French political writers, diſſatisfied with their own plan, had pre⯑ſented ſeveral memorials to the miniſtry, pro⯑poſing to adopt the Engliſh parochial aſſeſſments, as greatly preferable. This is a curious fact; for at the very ſame time people in London, no leſs diſſatisfied with theſe aſſeſſments, were wri⯑ting pamphlets in praiſe of the French hoſpitals. One thing is certain, that no plan hitherto inven⯑ted has given ſatisfaction. Whether an unexcep⯑tionable plan is at all poſſible, ſeems extremely doubtful.
[54] In every plan for the poor that I have ſeen, workhouſes make one article; to provide work for thoſe who are willing, and to make thoſe work who are unwilling. With reſpect to the former, men need never be idle in England for want of employment; and they always ſucceed the beſt at the employment they chuſe for themſelves. With reſpect to the latter, puniſhment will not compel a man to labour ſeriouſly: he may aſſume the appearance, but will make no progreſs; and the pretext of ſickneſs or weakneſs is ever at hand for an excuſe. The only compulſion to make a man work ſeriouſly, is fear of want.
A hoſpital for the ſick, for the wounded, and for the maimed, is an excellent eſtabliſhment; being productive of good, without doing any harm. Such a hoſpital ſhould depend partly on voluntary charity; to procure which a general conviction of its being well managed, is neceſſa⯑ry. Hoſpitals that have a ſufficient fund of their own, and that have no dependence on the good will of others, are commonly ill managed.
Lies there any objection againſt a workhouſe, for training to labour deſtitute orphans, and beg⯑ging children? It is an article in Mr. Hay's plan, that the workhouſe ſhould relieve poor families of all their children above three. This has an enticing appearance, but is unſound at bottom. Children require the tenderneſs of a mother, du⯑ring the period of infantine diſeaſes; and even af⯑ter that period, they are far from being ſafe in the hands of mercenaries, who ſtudy nothing but their own eaſe and intereſt. Would it not be better, to diſtribute ſmall ſums from time to time among poor families overburdened with children, ſo as to relieve them from famine, not from la⯑bour? And with reſpect to orphans and begging [55] children, I incline to think, that it would be a more ſalutary meaſure, to encourage mechanicks, manufactures, and farmers above all, to edu⯑cate ſuch children. A premium for each, the half in hand, and the other half when they can work for themſelves, would be a proper encou⯑ragement. The beſt-regulated orphans-hoſpital I am acquainted with, is that of Edinburgh. Or⯑phans are taken in from every corner, provided only they be not under the age of ſeven, nor above that of twelve: under ſeven, they are too tender for a hoſpital; above twelve, their relations can find employment for them. Beſide the being taught to read and write, they are carefully in⯑ſtructed in ſome art, that may afford them com⯑fortable ſubſiſtence.
No man ever called in queſtion the utility of the marine ſociety; which will reflect honour on the members as long as we have a navy to protect us: they deſerve a rank above that of gartered knights. That inſtitution is the nobleſt exertion of charity and patriotiſm, that ever was known in any country.
A ſort of hoſpital for ſervants who for twenty years have faithfully adhered to the ſame maſter, would be much to my taſte; with a few adjoin⯑ing acres for a kitchen-garden. The fund for purchaſing, building, and maintenance, muſt be raiſed by contribution; and none but the contri⯑butors ſhould be entitled to offer ſervants to the houſe. By ſuch encouragement, a malady would be remedied, that of wandering from maſter to maſter for better wages, or eaſier ſervice, which ſeldom fails to corrupt ſervants. They ought to be comfortably provided for, adding to the allow⯑ance of the houſe what pot-herbs are raiſed by their own labour. A number of virtuous men thus aſſociated, would end their days in com⯑fort; [56] and the proſpect of attaining a ſettlement ſo agreeable, would form excellent ſervants. How advantageous would ſuch a hoſpital prove to huſ⯑bandry in particular!
Of all the miſchiefs that have been engendered by over-anxiety about the poor, none have prov⯑ed more fatal than foundling-hoſpitals. They tend to cool affection for children, ſtill more ef⯑fectually than the Engliſh pariſh-charity. At every occaſional pinch for food, away goes a child to the hoſpital; and parental affection among the lower ſort turns ſo languid, that many who are in no pinch, relieve themſelves of trouble by the ſame means. It is affirmed, that of the chil⯑dren born annually in Paris, about a third part are ſent to the foundling-hoſpital. The Paris almanack for the year 1768, mentions, that there were baptized 18,576 infants, of whom the foundling-hoſpital received 6025. The propor⯑tion originally was much leſs; but vice creeps on with a ſwift pace. How enormous muſt be the degeneracy of the Pariſian populace, and their want of parental affection!
Let us next turn to infants ſhut up in this hoſ⯑pital. Of all animals, infants of the human race are the weakeſt: they require a mother's affecti⯑on to guard them againſt numberleſs diſeaſes and accidents; a wiſe appointment of Providence to connect parents and children in the ſtricteſt union. In a foundling-hoſpital, there is no fond mother to watch over her tender babe; and the hireling nurſe has no fondneſs but for her own little profit. Need we any other cauſe for the deſtruction of in⯑fants in a foundling-hoſpital, much greater in proportion than of thoſe under the care of a mo⯑ther? And yet there is another cauſe equally po⯑tent, which is corrupted air. What Hanway obſerves upon pariſh-workhouſes, is equally ap⯑plicable [57] to a foundling-hoſpital. ‘"To at⯑tempt,"’ ſays he, ‘"to nouriſh an infant in a workhouſe, where a number of nurſes are congregated into one room, and conſequently the air become putrid, I will pronounce, from intimate knowledge of the ſubject, to be but a ſmall remove from ſlaughter; for the child muſt die."’ Down then with foundling-hoſ⯑pitals, more noxious than peſtilence or famine. An infant expoſed at the door of a dwelling-houſe, muſt be taken up: but in that caſe, which ſel⯑dom happens, the infant has a better chance for life with a hired nurſe than in a hoſpital; and a chance perhaps little worſe, bad as it is, than with an unnatural mother. I approve not indeed of a quarterly payment to ſuch a nurſe: would it not do better to furniſh her bare maintenance for three years; and if the child be alive at that time, to give her a handſome addition?
A houſe of correction is neceſſary for good or⯑der; but belongs not to the preſent eſſay, which concerns maintenance of the poor, not puniſh⯑ment of vagrants. I ſhall only by the way bor⯑row a thought from Fielding, that faſting is the proper puniſhment of profligacy, not any puniſh⯑ment that is attended with ſhame. Puniſhment, he obſerves, that deprives a man of all ſenſe of honour, never will contribute to make him vir⯑tuous.
Charity-ſchools might have been proper, when few could read, and fewer write; but theſe arts are now ſo common, that in moſt fami⯑lies children may be taught to read at home, and to write in a private ſchool at little expence. Cha⯑rity-ſchools at preſent are more hurtful than be⯑neficial: young perſons who continue there ſo long as to read and write fluently, become too delicate for hard labour, and too proud for ordi⯑nary [58] labour. Knowledge is a dangerous acquiſi⯑tion to the labouring poor: the more of it that is poſſeſſed by a ſhepherd, a ploughman, or any drudge, the leſs fitted is he to labour with content. The only plauſible argument for a charity-ſchool, is, ‘"That children of the labouring poor are taught there the principles of religion and of morality, which they cannot acquire at home."’ The argument would be invincible, if with⯑out education we could have no knowledge of theſe principles. But Providence has not left man in a ſtate ſo imperfect: the principles of theology and of morality are ſtamped on his heart; and none can be ignorant of them, who attend to their own perceptions. Education is indeed of uſe to ripen ſuch perceptions; and it is a ſingular uſe to thoſe who have time for reading and thinking: but education in a charity-ſchool is ſo ſlight, as to render it doubtful, whether it be not more hurtful by foſtering lazineſs, than advantageous by conveying inſtruction. The natural impreſſi⯑ons of religion and morality, if not obſcured by vicious habits, are ſufficient for good conduct: preſerve a man from vice by conſtant labour, and he will not be deficient in his duty either to God or to man. Heſiod, an ancient and reſpectable poet, ſays, that God hath placed labour as a guard to virtue. More integrity accordingly will be found among a number of induſtrious poor ta⯑ken at random, than among the ſame number in any other claſs.
I heartily approve every regulation that tends to prevent idleneſs. Chief Juſtice Hale ſays, ‘"That prevention of poverty and idleneſs would do more good than all the gibbets, whipping⯑poſts, and goals in the kingdom."’ In that view, gaming-houſes ought to be heavily taxed, as well as horſe-racing, cock-fighting, and all [59] meetings that encourage idleneſs. The admitting low people to vote for members of parliament, is a ſource of idleneſs, corruption, and poverty. The ſame privilege is ruinous to every ſmall parliament borough. Nor have I any difficulty to pronounce, that the admitting the populace to vote in the election of a miniſter, a frequent practice in Scotland, is productive of the ſame pernicious effects.
What then is to be the reſult of the forego⯑ing enquiry? Is it from defect of invention that a good legal eſtabliſhment for the poor is not yet diſcovered? or is it impracticable to make any legal eſtabliſhment that is not fraught with corruption? I incline to the latter, for the follow⯑ing reaſons, no leſs obvious than ſolid, That in a legal eſtabliſhment for the poor, no diſtinction can be made between virtue and vice; and con⯑ſequently that every ſucheſt abliſhment muſt be a premium for idleneſs. And where is the neceſſi⯑ty, after all, of any public eſtabliſhment? By what unhappy prejudice have people been led to think, that the Author of our nature, ſo benefi⯑cent to his favourite man in every other reſpect, has abandoned the indigent to famine and death, if municipal law interpoſe not? We need but in⯑ſpect the human heart to be convinced, that per⯑ſons in diſtreſs are his peculiar care. Not only has he made it our duty to afford them relief, but has ſuperadded the paſſion of pity to enforce the performance of that duty. This branch of our nature fulfils in perfection all the ſalutary purpoſes of charity, without admitting any one of the deplorable evils that a legal proviſion is fraught with. The contrivance, at the ſame time, is extremely ſimple: it leaves to every man the objects as well as meaſure of his charity. No man eſteems it a duty to relieve wretches reduced [60] to poverty by idleneſs and profligacy: they move not our pity; nor do they expect any good from us. Wiſely therefore is it ordered by Provi⯑dence, that charity ſhould in every reſpect be vo⯑luntary, to prevent the idle and profligate from depending on it for ſupport.
This plan is in many reſpects excellent. The exerciſe of charity, when free from compulſion, is extremely pleaſant. The pleaſure, it is true, is ſcarce felt where charity is rendered unneceſſa⯑ry by municipal law; but were that law laid aſide, the gratification of pity would become one of our ſweeteſt pleaſures. Charity, like other affecti⯑ons, is invigorated by exerciſe, and no leſs en⯑feebled by diſuſe. Providence withal hath ſcat⯑tered benevolence among the ſons of men with a liberal hand: and notwithſtanding the obſtruction of municipal law, ſeldom is there found one ſo obdurate, as to reſiſt the impulſe of compaſſion, when a proper object is preſented. In a well re⯑gulated government, promoting induſtry and vir⯑tue, the perſons who need charity are not many: and ſuch perſons may, with aſſurance, depend on the charity of their neighbours*.
It may, at the ſame time, be boldly affirmed, that thoſe who need charity, would be more com⯑fortably provided for by the plan of Providence, than by any legal eſtabliſhment. Creatures, loathſome by diſeaſe or naſtineſs, affect the air in a poor-houſe, and have little chance for life, without more care and kindlineſs, than can be hoped from ſervants, render callous by continual ſcenes of miſery. Conſider, on the other hand, [61] the conſequences of voluntary charity, equally agreeable to the giver and receiver. The kind⯑ly connection it forms between them, grows ſtronger and ſtronger by reiteration; and ſqual⯑lid poverty, far from being an obſtruction, ex⯑cites a degree of pity, proportioned to the di⯑ſtreſs. It may happen for a wonder, that an indigent perſon is overlooked; but for one who will ſuffer by ſuch neglect, multitudes ſuffer by compelled charity.
But what I inſiſt on with peculiar ſatisfaction is, that natural charity is an illuſtrious ſupport to virtue. Indigent virtue can never fail of re⯑lief, becauſe it never fails to enflame compaſſion. Indigent vice, on the contrary, raiſes indignation more than pitya; and therefore can have lit⯑tle proſpect of relief. What a glorious incite⯑ment to induſtry and virtue, and how diſcou⯑raging to idleneſs and vice! Lamentable it is, that ſo beautiful a ſtructure ſhould be razed to the ground by municipal law, which, in provi⯑ding for the poor, makes no diſtinction between virtue and vice. The execution of the poor⯑laws would indeed be impracticable, were ſuch a diſtinction attempted by enquiring into the conduct and character of every pauper. Where are judges to be found who will patiently follow out ſuch a dark and intricate expiſcation? To accompliſh the taſk, a man muſt abandon every other concern.
In the firſt Engliſh ſtatutes mentioned above, the legiſlature appear carefully to have avoided compulſory charity: every meaſure for promo⯑ting voluntary charity was firſt tried, before the fatal blow was ſtruck, empowering pariſh-offi⯑cers [62] to impoſe a tax for the poor. The legiſla⯑ture certainly did not foreſee the baneful conſe⯑quences: but how came they not to ſee that they were diſtruſting Providence, declaring in effect, that the plan eſtabliſhed by our Maker for the poor, is inſufficient? Many are the mu⯑nicipal laws that enforce the laws of nature, by additional rewards and puniſhments; but it was ſingularly bold to aboliſh the natural law of cha⯑rity, by eſtabliſhing a legal tax in its ſtead. Men will always be mending: what a confuſed jumble do they make, when they attempt to mend the laws of Nature! Leave Nature to her own operations: ſhe underſtands them the beſt.
Few regulations are more plauſible than what are political; and yet few are more deceitful. An ingenious writer makes the following obſer⯑vations upon the 43o Eliz. eſtabliſhing a mainte⯑nance for the poor. ‘"Laws have been enacted in many other countries, which have puniſh⯑ed the idle beggar, and exhorted the rich to extend their charity to the poor: but it is peculiar to the humanity of England, to have made their ſupport a matter of obligation and neceſſity on the more wealthy. The Engliſh ſeem to be the firſt nation in Europe in ſcience, arts, and arms: they likewiſe are poſſeſſed of the freeſt and moſt perfect of conſtitutions, and the bleſſings conſequential to that freedom. If virtues in an individual are ſometimes ſuppoſed to be rewarded in this world, I do not think it too preſumptuous to ſuppoſe, that national virtues may likewiſe meet with their reward. England hath, to its peculiar honour, not only made their poor free, but hath provided a certain and ſolid eſtabliſhment to prevent their neceſſities and indigence, when they ariſe from what the law [63] calls the act of God: and are not theſe benefi⯑cent and humane attentions to the miſeries of our fellow-creatures, the firſt of thoſe poor pleas which we are capable of offering, in behalf of our imperfections, to an all-wiſe and merciful Creator!"’ To this writer, who ſhows more zeal than knowledge, I oppoſe ano⯑ther, whoſe reflections are more rational. ‘"In England, there is an act of the legiſlature, obliging every pariſh to maintain its own poor. Scarce any man living, who has not ſeen the effects of this law, but muſt approve of it; and yet ſuch are its effects, that the ſtreets of London are filled with objects of miſery be⯑yond what is ſeen in any other city. The la⯑bouring poor, depending on this law to be provided in ſickneſs and old age, are little ſo⯑licitous to ſave, and become habitually pro⯑fuſe. The principle of charity is eſtabliſhed by Providence in the human heart, for reliev⯑ing thoſe who are diſabled to work for them⯑ſelves. And if the labouring poor had no de⯑pendence but on the principle of charity, they would be more religious; and if they were influenced by religion, they would be leſs abandoned in their behaviour. Thus this ſeeming-good act turns to a national evil: there is more diſtreſs among the poor in Lon⯑don than any where in Europe; and more drunkenneſs both in males and femalesa."’
I am aware, that during the reign of Elizabeth, ſome compulſion might be neceſſary to preſerve the poor from ſtarving. Henry VIII. had ſeque⯑ſtered all the hoſpitals, a hundred and ten in number, and ſquandered their revenues; he had [64] alſo demoliſhed all the abbeys. By theſe means, the poor were reduced to a miſerable condition: eſpecially as private charity, for want of exer⯑ciſe, was at a low ebb. That critical juncture required indeed help from the legiſlature; and a temporary proviſion for the poor would have been a proper meaſure; ſo contrived as not to ſuperſede voluntary charity, but rather to pro⯑mote it. Unlucky it is for England, that ſuch a meaſure was overlooked; but Queen Elizabeth and her parliaments had not the talent of foreſee⯑ing conſequences without the aid of experience. A perpetual tax for the poor was impoſed, the moſt pernicious tax that ever was impoſed in any country.
With reſpect to the preſent times, the reaſon now given pleads againſt aboliſhing at once a le⯑gal proviſion for the poor. It may be taken for granted, that charity is in England not more vi⯑gorous at preſent, than it was in the days of Eli⯑zabeth. Would our miniſtry but lead the way, by ſhowing ſome zeal for a reformation, expe⯑dients would probably be invented, for ſupport⯑ing the poor, without unhinging voluntary cha⯑rity. The following expedient, is propoſed, merely as a ſpecimen. Let a tax be impoſed by parliament on every pariſh for their poor, varia⯑ble in proportion to the number; but not to ex⯑ceed the half of what is neceſſary; and directing the landholders to make up quarterly, a liſt of the names and condition of ſuch perſons as in their opinion need charity; with an eſtimate of what each ought to have weekly. The public tax makes the half, and the other half is to be raiſed by voluntary contribution. To prevent colluſion, the roll of the poor, and their weekly appointment, with a ſubſcription of gentlemen for their part of the ſum, ſhall be examined by [65] the juſtices of peace at a quarterly meeting; who, on receiving ſatisfaction, muſt order the ſum ari⯑ſing from the public tax to be diſtributed among the poor contained in the roll, according to the eſtimate of the landholders. As the public fund lies dead till the ſubſcription is completed, it is not to be imagined, that any gentleman will ſtand out: it would be a public imputation on his character. Far from apprehending any deficien⯑cy, confident I am, that every gentleman would conſider it as honourable to contribute largely. This agreeable work muſt be blended with what is rather diſagreeable, that of excluding from the roll every profligate, male or female. If that rule be followed out with a proper degree of ſeverity, the innocent poor will diminiſh daily; ſo as in time to be ſafely left upon voluntary charity, without neceſſity of any tax.
But muſt miſerable wretches, reduced to po⯑verty by idleneſs or intemperance, be, in a Chriſti⯑an country, abandoned to diſeaſes and famine? It is this very argument, ſhallow as it is, that has corrupted the induſtry of England, and reduced multitudes to diſeaſes and famine. Thoſe who are able to work, may be locked up in a houſe of correction, to be fed with bread and water; but with liberty of working for themſelves. And as for the remainder, their caſe is not deſperate, when they have acceſs to ſuch tender-hearted perſons as are more eminent for pity than for prin⯑ciple. If by neglect or overſight any happen to die of want, the example will tend more to re⯑formation, than the moſt pathetic diſcourſe from the pulpit.
Even at the hazard of loſing a few lives by neglect or overſight, common begging ought ab⯑ſolutely to be prohibited. The moſt profligate are the moſt impudent, and the moſt expert at [66] feigning diſtreſs. If begging be indulged to any, all will ruſh into the public: idlers are fond of that wandering and indolent ſort of life; and there is no temptation to idleneſs more ſucceſsful, than liberty to beg. In order to be relieved from common beggars, it has been propoſed, to fine thoſe who gave them alms. Little penetration muſt they have, to whom the inſufficiency of ſuch a remedy is not palpable. It is eaſy to give alms without been ſeen; and compaſſion will ex⯑tort alms, even at the hazard of ſuffering for it; not to mention, that every one in ſuch a caſe will avoid the odious character of an informer. The following remedy is ſuggeſted, as what probably may anſwer better. An officer muſt be appoint⯑ed in every pariſh, with a competent ſalary, for apprehending and carrying to the workhouſe every ſtrolling beggar; under the penalty of loſing his office, with what ſalary is due to him, if any beggar be found ſtrolling four and twenty hours after the fact comes to his knowledge. In the workhouſe ſuch beggars ſhall be fed with bread and water for a year, but with liberty of working for themſelves.
I declare reſolutely againſt a perpetual tax for the poor. But if there muſt be ſuch a tax, I know of none leſs ſubverſive of induſtry and mo⯑rals, than that eſtabliſhed in Scotland, obliging the landholders in every pariſh to meet at ſtated times, in order to provide a fund for the poor; but leaving the objects of their charity, and the meaſure, to their own humanity and diſcretion. In this plan, there is no encroachment on the natural duty of charity, but only that the mi⯑nority muſt ſubmit to the opinion of the majo⯑rity.
In large towns, where the character and cir⯑cumſtances of the poor-are not ſo well known as [67] in country-pariſhes, the following variation is propoſed. Inſtead of landholders, who are pro⯑per in country-pariſhes, let there be in each town-pariſh a ſtanding committee, to be choſen by the proprietors of houſes, the third part to be chang⯑ed annually. This committee, with the miniſter, make up a liſt of ſuch as deſerve charity, adding an eſtimate of what, with their own labour, may be ſufficient for each of them. The miniſter, with one or two of the committee, carry about this liſt to every family that can afford charity, ſuggeſting what may be proper for each to contri⯑bute. This liſt, with an addition of the ſum contributed or promiſed by each houſeholder, muſt be affixed on the principal door of the pariſh⯑church, to honour the contributors, and to inform the poor of the proviſion made for them. Some ſuch mode may probably be effectual, without tranſgreſſing the bounds of voluntary charity. But if any one obſtinately refuſe to contribute after ſeveral applications, the committee at their diſcretion may tax him. If it be the poſſeſſor who declines contributing, the tax muſt be laid upon him, reſerving relief againſt his land⯑lord.
In great towns, the poor, who ought to be pro⯑hibited from begging, are leſs known than in country pariſhes. And among a crowd of inha⯑bitants, it is eaſier for an individual to eſcape the eye of the public, when he with-holds charity, than in country-pariſhes. Both defects will be remedied by the plan above propoſed: it will bring to light, in great cities, the poor who de⯑ſerve charity; and it will bring to light every perſon who with-holds charity.
SKETCH XI.
A GREAT CITY conſidered in Phyſical, Moral, and Political Views.
[68]IN all ages an opinion ſeems to have been pre⯑valent, that a great city is a great evil, and that a capital may be too great for the ſtate, as a head may be for the body. Conſidering however the very ſhallow reaſons that have been given for this opinion, it ſhould ſeem to be but ſlightly founded. There are ſeveral ordinances limiting the extent of Paris, and prohibiting new buildings beyond the preſcribed bounds; the firſt of which is by Henry II. ann. 1549. Theſe ordinances have been renewed from time to time, down to the year 1672, in which year there is an edict of Louis XIV. to the ſame purpoſe. The reaſons aſſigned are, ‘"Firſt, That by enlarging the city, the air would be rendered unwholeſome. Second, That cleaning the ſtreets would prove a great additional labour. Third, That adding to the number of inhabitants would raiſe the price of proviſions, of labour, and of manu⯑factures. Fourth, That ground would be [69] covered with buildings inſtead of corn, which might hazard a ſcarcity. Fifth, That the country would be depopulated by the deſire that people have to reſort to the capital. And, laſtly, That the difficulty of governing ſuch numbers would be an encouragement to robbery and murder."’
Theſe reaſons for confining the city of Paris within certain bounds are wonderfully ſhallow. The moſt important of them conclude juſtly againſt permitting an increaſe of inhabitants: the ſecond and fourth conclude only againſt enlarging the city; and theſe, at the beſt, are trifling. The firſt reaſon urged againſt enlarging the city, is a ſolid reaſon for enlarging it, ſuppoſing the num⯑bers to be limited; for to prevent crouding is an excellent preventive of unwholeſome air. Paris, with the ſame number of inhabitants that were in the days of the fourth Henry, occupies thrice the ſpace, much to the health as well as comfort of the inhabitants. Had the ordinances mentioned been made effectual, the houſes in Paris muſt all have been built, like thoſe in the old town, ſtory above ſtory, aſcending to the ſky like the tower of Babel. Before the great fire anno 1666, the plague was frequent in London; but by widening the ſtreets, and enlarging the houſes, there has not ſince been known in that great city, any contagious diſtemper that deſerves the name of a plague. The third, fifth, and laſt reaſons, conclude againſt permitting any addition to the number of inhabitants; but conclude nothing againſt enlarging the town. In a word, the mea⯑ſure adopted in theſe ordinances has little or no tendency to correct the evils complained of; and infallibly would enflame the chief of them. The [70] meaſure that ought to have been adopted, is to limit the number of inhabitants, not the extent of the town.
Queen Elizabeth of England, copying the French ordinances, iſſued a proclamation anno 1602, prohibiting any new buildings within three miles of London. The preamble is in the fol⯑lowing words: ‘"That foreſeeing the great and manifold inconveniencies and miſchiefs which daily grow, and are likely to increaſe, in the city and ſuburbs of London, by confluence of people to inhabit the ſame; not only by reaſon that ſuch multitudes can hardly be governed to ſerve God, and obey her Majeſty, without conſtituting an addition of new officers, and enlarging their authority; but alſo can hardly be provided of food and other neceſſaries at a reaſonable price; and finally, that as ſuch multitudes of people, many of them poor, who muſt live by begging, or worſe means, are heaped up together, and in a ſort ſmo⯑thered, with many children and ſervants, in one houſe or ſmall tenement; it muſt needs follow, if any plague or other univerſal ſickneſs come amongſt them, that it would preſently ſpread through the whole city and confines, and alſo into all parts of the realm."’
There appears no deeper penetration in this pro⯑clamation, than in the French ordinances. The ſame error is obſervable in both, which is the li⯑miting the extent of the town, inſtead of limiting the number of inhabitants. True it is indeed, that the regulation would have a better effect in London than in Paris. As ſtone is in plenty about Paris, houſes there may be carried to a very great height; and are actually ſo carried in the old town: but there being no ſtone about [71] London, the houſes formerly were built of timber, now of brick; materials too frail for a lofty edifice.
Proceeding to particulars, the firſt objection, which is the expence of governing a great multi⯑tude, concludes againſt the numbers, not againſt the extent of the city. At the ſame time, the objection is at beſt doubtful in point of fact. Though vices abound in a great city, requiring the ſtricteſt attention of the magiſtrate; yet with a well-regulated police, it is much leſs expenſive to govern 600,000 in one city, than the ſame number in ten different cities. The ſecond ob⯑jection, viz. the high price of proviſions, ſtrikes only againſt numbers, not extent. Beſide, what⯑ever might have been the caſe in the days of Elizabeth, when agriculture and internal com⯑merce were in their infancy; there are at preſent not many towns in England, where a temperate man may live cheaper than in London. The hazard of contagious diſtempers, which is the third objection, is an invincible argument againſt limiting the extent of a great town. It is men⯑tioned above, that from the year 1666, when the ſtreets were widened, and the houſes enlarged, London has never been once viſited by the plague. If the proclamation had taken effect, the houſes muſt have been ſo crouded upon each other, and the ſtreets ſo contracted, as to have occaſioned plagues ſtill more frequently than before the year 1666.
The miniſtry of the Queen's immediate ſuc⯑ceſſors were not more clear-ſighted than ſhe and her miniſters were. In the year 1624, King James iſſued a proclamation againſt building in London upon new foundations. Charles I. iſ⯑ſued two proclamations to the ſame purpoſe; one in the year 1625, and one in the year 1630.
[72] The progreſs of political knowledge has un⯑folded many bad effects of a great city, more weighty than any urged in theſe proclamations. The firſt I ſhall mention is, that people born and bred in a great city are commonly weak and ef⯑feminate. Vegetiusa obſerving, that men bred to huſbandry make the beſt ſoldiers, adds what follows. ‘"Interdum tamen neceſſitas exigit, etiam urbanos ad arma compelli: qui ubi nomen dedere militiae, primum laborare, decurrere, portare pondus, et ſolem pulveremque ferre, condiſcant; parco victu utantur et ruſtico; interdum ſub divo, interdum ſub papilionibus, commorentur. Tunc demum ad uſum erudi⯑antur armorum: et ſi longior expeditio emer⯑git, in angariis plurimum detinendi ſunt, pro⯑culque habendi a civitatis illecebris: ut eo modo, et corporibus eorum robur accedat, et animis*."’ The luxury of a great city deſ⯑cends from the higheſt to the loweſt, infecting all ranks of men; and there is little opportunity in it for ſuch exerciſe as renders the body vigor⯑ous [73] and robuſt. This is a phyſical objection againſt a great city: the next regards morality. Virtue is exerted chiefly in reſtraint: vice, in giving freedom to deſire. Moderation and ſelf⯑command form a character the moſt ſuſceptible of virtue: ſuperfluity of animal ſpirits, and love of pleaſure, form a character the moſt liable to vice. Low vices, pilfering for example, or ly⯑ing, draw few or no imitators; but vices that indicate a ſoul above reſtraint, fail not to pro⯑duce admirers. Where a man boldly ſtruggles againſt unlawful reſtraint, he is juſtly applauded and imitated; and the vulgar are not apt to diſ⯑tinguiſh nicely between lawful and unlawful re⯑ſtraint: the boldneſs is viſible, and they pierce no deeper. It is the unruly boy, full of animal ſpirits, who at a public ſchool is admired and imi⯑tated; not the virtuous and modeſt. Vices ac⯑cordingly that ſhow ſpirit, are extremely infec⯑tious; virtue very little. Hence the corrupti⯑on of a great city, which increaſes more and more in proportion to the number of inhabitants. But it is ſufficient here barely to mention that objection; becauſe it has been much inſiſted on in antecedent parts of this work.
The following bad effects are more of a poli⯑tical nature. A great town is a profeſſed enemy to the free circulation of money. The current coin is accumulated in the capital: and diſtant provinces muſt ſink into idleneſs; for without ready money neither arts nor manufactures can flouriſh. Thus we find leſs and leſs activity, in proportion commonly to the diſtance from the capital, and an abſolute torpor in the extremities. It may be obſerved beſide, that as horſes in a great city muſt be provided with provender from a diſtance, the country is robbed of its dung for the benefit of the rich fields round the city. But [74] as manure laid upon poor land is of more advan⯑tage to the farmer than upon what is already highly improved, the depriving diſtant parts of manure is a loſs to the country in general. Nor is this all: The dung of an extenſive city, the bulk of it at leaſt, is ſo remote from the fields to which it muſt be carried, that the expence of carriage ſwallows up the profit.
Another bad effect of accumulating money in the capital is, to raiſe there the price of labour; and the temptation of high wages, making every one flock to the capital, robs the country of its beſt hands. And as they who reſort to the ca⯑pital are commonly young people, who remove as ſoon as they are fit for work, diſtant provin⯑ces are burdened with their maintenance, with⯑out reaping any benefit by their labour.
But of all, the moſt deplorable effect of a great city, is the preventing of population, by ſhortening the lives of its inhabitants. Does a capital ſwell in proportion to the numbers that are drained from the country? Far from it. The air of a populous city is infected by multitudes crouded together; and people there ſeldom make out the uſual time of life. With reſpect to London in particular, the fact is but too well aſcertained. The burials in that immenſe city greatly exceed the births: the difference ſome affirm to be no leſs than ten thouſand yearly: by the moſt moderate computation, not under ſeven or eight thouſand. As London is far from being on the decline, the conſumption of ſo many inhabitants muſt be ſupplied from the country; and the annual ſupply amounts pro⯑bably to a greater number than were needed an⯑nually for recruiting our armies and navies in the late war with France. If ſo, London is a greater enemy to population, than a bloody war [75] would be, ſuppoſing it even to be perpetual. What an enormous tax is Britain thus ſubjected to for ſupporting her capital! The rearing and educating yearly for London 7 or 8000 perſons, require an immenſe ſum.
In Paris, if the bills of mortality can be relied on, the births and burials are nearly equal, be⯑ing each of them about 19,000 yearly; and ac⯑cording to that computation, Paris ſhould need no recruits from the country. But in that city, the bills of mortality cannot be depended on for burials. It is there univerſally the practice of high and low, to have their infants nurſed in the country, till they be three years of age; and conſequently thoſe who die before that age, are not inliſted. What proportion theſe bear to the whole is uncertain. But a gueſs may be made from ſuch as die in London; which are comput⯑ed to be one half of the whole that diea. Now giving the utmoſt allowance for the healthi⯑neſs of the country above that of a town, Paris children that die in the country before the age of three, cannot be brought ſo low as a third of thoſe that die. On the other hand, the London bills of mortality are leſs to be depended on for births than for burials. None are inliſted but infants baptized by clergymen of the Engliſh church; and the numerous children of Papiſts, Diſſenters, and other ſectaries, are left out of the account. Upon the whole, the difference between the births and burials in Paris and in London, is much leſs than it appears to be on comparing the bills of mortality of theſe two cities.
[76] At the ſame time, giving full allowance for children that are not brought into the London bills of mortality, there is the higheſt probabili⯑ty that a greater number of children are born in Paris than in London; and conſequently that the former requires fewer recruits from the coun⯑try than the latter. In Paris, domeſtic ſervants are encouraged to marry: they are obſerved to be more ſettled than when batchelors, and more attentive to their duty. In London, ſuch mar⯑riages are diſcouraged, as rendering a ſervant more attentive to his own family, than to that of his maſter. But a ſervant attentive to his own family, will not, for his own ſake, neglect that of his maſter. At any rate, is he not more to be depended on, than a ſervant who continues a batchelor? What can be expected of idle and pampered batchelors, but debauchery, and every ſort of corruption? Nothing reſtrains them from abſolute profligacy, but the eye of the maſ⯑ter, who for that reaſon is their averſion not their love. If the poor-laws be named the folio of corruption, batchelor-ſervants in London may well be conſidered as a large appendix. And this attracts the eye to the poor-laws, which indeed make the chief difference between Paris and London, with reſpect to the preſent point. In Paris, certain funds are eſtabliſhed for the poor, the yearly produce of which admits but a limit⯑ed number. As that fund is always pre-occu⯑pied, the low people who are not on the liſt, have little or no proſpect of bread, but from their own induſtry; and to the induſtrious, mar⯑riage is in a great meaſure neceſſary. In Lon⯑don, a pariſh is taxed in proportion to the num⯑ber of its poor; and every perſon who is pleaſed to be idle, is entitled to maintenance. Moſt things thrive by encouragement, and idleneſs [77] above all. Certainty of maintenance, renders the low people in England idle and profligate; eſpecially in London, where luxury prevails, and infects every rank. So inſolent are the London poor, that ſcarce one of them will condeſcend to eat brown bread. There are accordingly in Lon⯑don, a much greater number of idle and profli⯑gate wretches, than in Paris, or in any other town in proportion to the number of inhabitants. Theſe wretches, in Doctor Swift's ſtyle, never think of poſterity, becauſe poſterity never thinks of them: men who hunt after pleaſure, and live from day to day, have no notion of being bur⯑dened with a family. Theſe cauſes produce a greater number of children in Paris than in Lon⯑don; though probably they differ not much in populouſneſs.
I ſhall add but one other objection to a great city, which is not ſlight. An overgrown capi⯑tal, far above a rival, has, by numbers and riches, a diſtreſſing influence in public affairs. The populace are ductile, and eaſily miſled by ambitious and deſigning magiſtrates. Nor are there wanting critical times, in which ſuch ma⯑giſtrates, acquiring artificial influence, may have power to diſturb the public peace. That an overgrown capital may prove dangerous to ſove⯑reignty, has more than once been experienced both in Paris and London.
It would give one the ſpleen, to hear the French and Engliſh zealouſly diſputing about the extent of their capitals, as if the proſperity of their country depended on that circumſtance. To me it appears like one glorying in the king's-evil, or in any contagious diſtemper. Much bet⯑ter employed would they be, in contriving means for leſſening thoſe cities. There is not a politi⯑cal meaſure, that, in my opinion, would tend [78] more to aggrandize the kingdom of France, or of Britain, than to ſplit its capital into ſeveral great towns. My plan would be, to confine the inhabitants of London to 100,000, compoſed of the king and his houſehold, ſupreme courts of juſtice, government-boards, prime nobility and gentry, with neceſſary ſhop-keepers, artiſts, and other dependents. Let the reſt of the inhabitants be diſtributed into nine towns properly ſituated, ſome for internal commerce, ſome for foreign. Such a plan would diffuſe life and vigour through every corner of the iſland.
To execute ſuch a plan, would, I acknow⯑ledge, require the deepeſt political ſkill, and much perſeverance. I ſhall ſuggeſt what occurs at preſent. The firſt ſtep muſt be, to mark proper ſpots for the nine towns, the moſt advan⯑tageous for trade, or for manufactures. If any of theſe ſpots be occupied already with ſmall towns, ſo much the better. The next ſtep is a capitation-tax on the inhabitants of London; the ſum levied to be appropriated for encouraging the new towns. One encouragement would have a good effect; which is, a premium to every man who builds in any of theſe towns, more or leſs, in proportion to the ſize of the houſe. This tax would baniſh from London, every manufacture but of the moſt lucrative kind. When, by this means, the inhabitants of London are reduced to a number not much above 100,000, the near proſpect of being relieved from the tax, will make every houſeholder active to baniſh all above that number: and to prevent a renewal of the tax, a greater number will never again be per⯑mitted. It would require great penetration to proportion the ſums to be levied and diſtributed, ſo as to have their proper effect, without over⯑burdening [79] the capital on the one hand, or giving too great encouragement for building on the other, which might tempt people to build for the premium merely, without any further view. Much will depend on an advantageous ſituation: houſes built there will always find inhabitants.
The two great cities of London and Weſtmin⯑ſter are extremely ill fitted for local union. The latter, the ſeat of government and of the nobleſſe, infects the former with luxury and with love of ſhow. The former, the ſeat of commerce, infects the latter with love of gain. The mixture of theſe oppoſite paſſions, is productive of every groveling vice.
SKETCH XII.
Origin and Progreſs of AMERICAN NATIONS.
[80]HAVING no authentic materials for a natural hiſtory of all the Americans, the following obſervations ſhall be confined to a few tribes, the beſt known; and to the kingdoms of Peru and Mexico, as they were at the date of the Spaniſh conqueſt.
As there appears no paſſage by land to America from the old world, no problem has more embar⯑raſſed the learned, than to give an account from whence the Americans ſprang: there are as many different opinions, as there are writers. Many attempts have been made for diſcovering a paſſage by land; but hitherto in vain. Kamſkatka, it is true, is divided from America by a narrow ſtrait, full of iſlands: and M. Buffon, to render the paſſage ſtill more eaſy than by ſea, conjectures, that thereabout there may formerly have been a land-paſſage, though now waſhed away by vio⯑lence of the ocean. There is indeed great ap⯑pearance of truth in this conjecture; as all the [81] quadrupeds of the north of Aſia ſeem to have made their way to America; the bear, for ex⯑ample, the roe, the deer, the rain-deer, the beaver, the wolf, the fox, the hare, the rat, the mole. He admits that in America there is not to be ſeen a lion, a tiger, a panther, or any other Aſiatic quadruped of a hot climate: not, ſays he, for want of a land-paſſage; but becauſe the cold climate of Tartary, in which ſuch ani⯑mals cannot ſubſiſt, is an effectual bar againſt them*.
But in my apprehenſion, much more is required to give ſatisfaction upon this ſubject, than a paſ⯑ſage from Kamſkatka to America, whether by land or ſea. An enquiry much more deciſive is totally overlooked, relative to the people on the two ſides of the ſtreight; particularly, whether they ſpeak the ſame language. Now by late ac⯑counts from Ruſſia we are informed, that there is no affinity between the Kamſkatkan tongue, and that of the Americans on the oppoſite ſide of the ſtreight. Whence we may conclude with great certainty, that the latter are not a colony of the former.
But I go farther. There are ſeveral cogent ar⯑guments to evince, that the Americans are not deſcended from any people in the north of Aſia or in the north of Europe. Were they deſcended from either, Labrador, or the adjacent countries, [82] muſt have been firſt peopled. And as ſavages are remarkably fond of their natal ſoil, they would have continued there, till by over-population they ſhould have been compelled to ſpread wider for food. But the fact is directly contrary. When America was diſcovered by the Spaniards, Mexico and Peru were fully peopled; and the other parts leſs and leſs, in proportion to their diſtance from theſe central countries. Fabry reports, that one may travel one or two hundred leagues north-weſt from the Miſſiſippi, without ſeeing a human face, or any veſtige of a houſe. And ſome French officers ſay, that they travelled more than a hundred leagues from the delicious country watered by the Ohio, through Louiſiana, without meeting a ſingle family of ſavages. Labrador is very thin of inhabitants; no people having been diſcovered in it, but the Eſquimaux, a very ſmall tribe. And as that tribe has plenty of food at home, there is no appearance, that they ever ſent a colony to any other part of America. The civilization of the Mexicans and Peruvians, as well as their populouſneſs, make it extremely probable that they were the firſt inhabitants of America. In travelling northward, the people are more and more ignorant and ſavage: the Eſquimaux, the moſt northern of all, are the moſt ſavage. In travelling ſouthward, the Pa⯑tagonians, the moſt ſouthern of all, are ſo ſtupid as to go naked in a bitter cold region.
I venture ſtill farther; which is, to conjecture, that America has not bee peopled from any part of the old world. The external appearance of the inhabitants, makes this conjecture approach to a certainty; as that appearance differs widely from the appearance of any other known people. Excepting the eye-laſhes, eye-brows, and hair of [83] the head, which is invariably jet black, there is not a ſingle hair on the body of any American▪ not the leaſt appearance of a beard. Another diſtinguiſhing mark is their copper-colour, uni⯑formly the ſame in all climates, hot and cold; and differing from the colour of all other nations. Ulloa remarks, that the Americans of Cape Breton, reſemble the Peruvians in complexion, in manners, and in cuſtoms; the only viſible dif⯑ference being, that the former are of a larger ſtature. A third circumſtance no leſs diſtinguiſh⯑ing is, that American children are born with down upon the ſkin, which diſappears the eighth or ninth day, and never grows again. Children of the old world are born with ſkins ſmooth and poliſhed, and no down appears till pu⯑berty.
That the original inhabitants of America are a race diſtinct from all others, I once thought de⯑monſtrable from ſome reports concerning the Eſquimaux. The author of the hiſtory of New France, and ſeveral other writers report, that the Eſquimaux are bold, miſchievous, ſuſpicious, and untamable; that it is not even ſafe to con⯑verſe with them but at a diſtance; that no European ſkin is whiter; and that they are beard⯑ed up to the eyes. Suppoſing theſe facts to be true, had I not reaſon to believe, that the Eſqui⯑maux muſt have ſprung from ſome nation in the north of Europe or Aſia, though I could not pretend to ſay, whether the tranſmigration was by land or ſea? From the ſame facts, however, I was forced to conclude, that the reſt of the Americans could not have had the ſame origin: for if the Canadians or any other American na⯑tion were of Aſiatic or European extraction, they muſt, like the Eſquimaux, have had a [84] beard and white ſkin to this day. But one cannot be too cautious in giving faith to odd or ſingular facts, reported of diſtant nations. It is diſcovered by later accounts more worthy of credit, that the foregoing deſcription of the Eſquimaux is falſe in every particular. Of all the northern nations, not excepting the Lap⯑landers, the Eſquimaux are of the ſmalleſt ſize, few of them exceeding four feet in height. They have heads extremely groſs, feet and hands very ſmall. That they are neither cruel nor ſuſpicious, appears from what Ellis ſays in his account of a voyage anno 1747, for diſ⯑covering a north-weſt paſſage, that they offer⯑ed their wives to the Engliſh ſailors, with ex⯑preſſions of ſatisfaction for being able to ac⯑commodate them. But what is the moſt to the preſent purpoſe; they are of a copper colour, like the other Americans, only a degree lighter, occaſioned probably by the intenſe cold of their climate; and they are alſo altogether deſtitute of a beard. It is common indeed among them, to bring forward the hair of the head upon the face, for preſerving it from flies, which rage in that country during ſummer; an appearance that probably has been miſtaken by travellers for a beard.
It has been lately diſcovered, that the lan⯑guage of the Eſquimaux is the ſame with that of the Greenlanders. A Daniſh miſſionary, who by ſome years reſidence in Greenland had acqui⯑red the language of that country, made a voy⯑age with Commodore Paliſer to Newfoundland ann. 1764. Meeting a company of about two hundred Eſquimaux, he was agreeably ſurpriſed to hear the Greenland tongue. They received him kindly, and drew from him a promiſe to re⯑turn [85] the next year. And we are informed by Crantz, in his hiſtory of Greenland, that the ſame Daniſh miſſionary viſited them the very next year, in company with the Rev. Mr. Dra⯑chart. They agreed, that the difference be⯑tween the Eſquimaux language and that of Greenland was not greater than between the dia⯑lects of North and South Greenland, which dif⯑fer not ſo much as the High and Low Dutch. Both nations call themſelves Innuit or Karalit, and call the Europeans Kablunet. Their ſtature, features, manners, dreſs, tents, darts, and boats, are entirely the ſame. As the language of Greenland reſembles not the language of Fin⯑land, Lapland, Norway, Tartary, nor that of the Samoides, it is evident, that neither the Eſquimaux nor Greenlanders are a colony from any of the countries mentioned. Geographers begin now to conjecture, that Greenland is a part of the continent of North America, without intervention of any ſea*. One thing is certain, that the Greenlanders reſemble the North-Ame⯑ricans in every particular: they are of a copper colour, and have no beard; they are of a ſmall ſize, like the Eſquimaux, and have the ſame language. And thus I am obliged to abandon my favourite argument, for proving the Ameri⯑cans, the Eſquimaux excepted, to be indigenous, and not indebted to the old world for their exiſt⯑ence. At the ſame time, the other arguments urged above remain entire; and from what is now [86] ſaid a circumſtance occurs, that fortifies greatly the chief of them. People, who with a bold face ſurmount all difficulties rather than give up a favourite opinion, make light of the copper co⯑lour and want of beard, willing to attribute all to the climate. We want data, I acknowledge, to determine with accuracy what effects can be pro⯑duced by a climate. But luckily we have no oc⯑caſion at preſent to determine that difficult point. It is ſufficient that the climate of Labrador is much the ſame with that of the northern parts of Europe and Aſia. From that circumſtance I conclude with certainty, that the copper colour and want of beard in the Eſquimaux cannot be the reſult of climate. And if ſo, what foundation can there be for making theſe circumſtances de⯑pend on the climate in any other part of Ameri⯑ca? Truly none at all. I add, that as the cop⯑per colour and want of beard continue invariably the ſame in every variety of climate, hot and cold, moiſt and dry, they muſt depend on ſome invariable cauſe acting uniformly; which may be a ſingularity in the race of peoplea, but cannot proceed from the climate.
If we can rely on the conjectures of an eminent writerb, America emerged from the ſea later than any other part of the known world: and ſuppoſing the human race to have been planted in America by the hand of God later than the days of Moſes, Adam and Eve might have been the firſt parents of mankind, i. e. of all who at that time exiſted, without being the firſt parents of the Americans.
[87] The Terra Auſtralis incognita is ſeparated from the reſt of the world by a wide ocean, which carries a ſhip round the earth without interrup⯑tion. How has that continent been peopled? There is not the ſlighteſt probability, that it ever has been joined to any other land. Here a local creation, if it may be termed ſo, appears una⯑voidable; and if we muſt admit more than one act of creation, even the appearance of difficulty, from reiteration of acts, totally vaniſheth. M. Buffon, in his natural hiſtory, bears teſtimony, that not a ſingle American quadruped of a hot cli⯑mate is found in any other part of the earth: with reſpect to theſe we muſt unavoidably admit a local creation; and nothing ſeems more natural, than under the ſame act to comprehend the firſt parents of the American people.
It is poſſible, indeed, that a ſhip with men and women may, by contrary winds, be carried to a very diſtant ſhore. But to account thus for the peopling of America, will not be much reliſhed: Mexico and Peru muſt have been planted before navigation was known in the old world, at leaſt before a ſhip was brought to ſuch perfection as to bear a long courſe of bad weather. Will it be thought, that any ſuppoſition ought to be embra⯑ced, however improbable, rather than admit a ſeparate creation? We are, it is true, much in the dark as to the conduct of creative Provi⯑dence; but every rational conjecture leans to a ſeparate creation. America and the Terra Au⯑ſtralis muſt have been planted by the Almighty with a number of animals and vegetables, ſome of them peculiar to thoſe vaſt continents: and when ſuch care has been taken about inferior life, can ſo wild a thought be admitted, as that man, the nobleſt work of terreſtrial creation, would be left to chance? But it is ſcarce neceſſary to inſiſt [88] upon this topic, as the external characters of the Americans above mentioned reject the ſuppoſition of their being deſcended from any people of the old world.
It is highly probable, that the fertile and de⯑licious plains of Peru and Mexico were the firſt planted of all the American countries; being more populous at the time of the Spaniſh invaſion than any other part of that great continent. This conjecture is ſupported by analogy: we believe that a ſpot, not centrical only, but extremely fertile, was choſen for the parents of the old world; and there is not in America a ſpot more centrical, or more fertile, than Mexico or Peru, for the parents of the new world.
Having thus ventured to throw out what oc⯑curred upon the origin of the Americans, with⯑out pretending to affirm any thing as certain, we proceed to their progreſs. The North-American tribes are remarkable with reſpect to one branch of their hiſtory, that, inſtead of advancing, like other nations, toward the maturity of ſociety and government, they continue to this hour in their original ſtate of hunting and fiſhing. A caſe ſo ſingular rouſes our curioſity; and we wiſh to be made acquainted with the cauſe.
It is not the want of animals capable to be do⯑meſticated, that obliges them to remain hunters and fiſhers. The horſe, it is true, the ſheep, the goat, were imported from Europe; but there are plenty of American quadrupeds no leſs docile than thoſe mentioned. There is, in particular, a ſpecies of horned cattle peculiar to America, having long wool inſtead of hair, and an excre⯑ſcence upon the ſhoulder like that of the Eaſt-In⯑dia buffalo. Theſe wild cattle multiply exceed⯑ingly in the fertile countries which the Miſſiſippi traverſes; and Hennepin reports, that the Indi⯑ans, [89] after killing numbers, take no part away but the tongue, which is reckoned a delicious morſel. Theſe creatures are not extremely wild; and, if taken young, are eaſily tamed: a calf, when its dam is killed, will follow the hunter and lick his hand. The wool, the hide, the tallow, would be of great value in the Britiſh colonies.
If the ſhepherd-ſtate be not obſtructed in America by want of proper cattle, the only ac⯑count that can or need be given is, paucity of in⯑habitants. Conſider only the influence of cuſtom, in rivetting men to their local ſituation and man⯑ner of life: once hunters, they will always be hunters, till ſome cauſe more potent than cuſtom force them out of that ſtate. Want of food, oc⯑caſioned by rapid population, brought on the ſhepherd-ſtate in the old world. That cauſe has not hitherto taken place in North America: the inhabitants, few in number, remain hunters and fiſhers, becauſe that ſtate affords them a compe⯑tency of food. I am aware, that the natives have been decreaſing in number from the time of the firſt European ſettlements. But even at that time the country was ill peopled: take for exam⯑ple the country above deſcribed, ſtretching north⯑weſt from the Miſſiſippi: the Europeans never had any footing there, and yet to this day it is little better than a deſert. I give other exam⯑ples. The Indians who ſurround the lake Nippi⯑ſong, from whence the river St. Laurence iſſues, are in whole but five or ſix thouſand; and yet their country is of great extent: they live by hunting and fiſhing, having bows and arrows, but no fire-arms; and their cloathing is the ſkins of beaſts: they are ſeldom, if ever, engaged in war; have no commerce with any other people, Indian or European, but live as if they had a [90] world to themſelvesa. If that country be ill peopled, it is not from ſcarcity of food; for the country is extenſive, and well ſtored with every ſort of game. On the ſouth and weſt of the lake Superior, the country is level and fruitful all the way to the Miſſiſippi, having large plains co⯑vered with rank graſs, and ſcarce a tree for hundreds of miles: the inhabitants enjoy the grea⯑teſt plenty of fiſh, fowl, deer, &c.; and yet their numbers are far from being in proportion to their means of ſubſiſtence. In ſhort, it is the conjecture of the ableſt writers, that in the vaſt extent of North America, when diſcovered, there were not as many people, laying aſide Mex⯑ico, as in the half of Europe.
Paucity of inhabitants explains clearly why the North-American tribes remain hunters and fiſh⯑ers, without advancing to the ſhepherd-ſtate. But if the foregoing difficulty be removed, an⯑other ſtarts up, no leſs puzzling, viz. By what adverſe fate are ſo rich countries ſo ill peopled? It is a conjecture of M. Buffon, mentioned above, that America has been planted later than the other parts of this globe. But ſuppoſing the fact, it has however not been planted ſo late as to prevent a great population, witneſs Mexico and Peru, fully peopled at the aera of the Spaniſh in⯑vaſion. We muſt therefore ſearch for another cauſe; and none occurs but the infecundity of the North-American ſavages. M. Buffon, a re⯑ſpectable author, and for that reaſon often quo⯑ted, remarks, that theſe ſavages are feeble in their organs of generation, that they have no ar⯑dor for the female ſex, and that they have few children; to enforce which remark he adds, that [91] the quadrupeds of America, both native and tran⯑ſplanted, are of a diminutive ſize, compared with thoſe of the old world. A woman never ad⯑mits her huſband, till the child ſhe is nurſing be three years old; and this led Frenchmen to go often aſtray from their Canadian wives. The caſe was reported by the prieſts to their ſuperiors in France; but what order was taken has eſcaped my memory. Among the males, it is an invio⯑lable law, to abſtain from females while they are engaged in a military expedition. This is preg⯑nant evidence of their frigidity; for among ſava⯑ges the authority of law, or of opinion, ſeldom prevails over any ſtrong appetite: vain would be the attempt to reſtrain them from ſpirituous li⯑quors, tho' much more debilitating. Neither is there any inſtance, of violence offered by any North-American ſavage, to European women taken captives in war.
Mexico and Peru, when conquered by the Spaniards, afforded to their numerous inhabitants the neceſſaries of life in profuſion. Cotton was in plenty, more than ſufficient for the cloathing needed in warm climates: Indian wheat was uni⯑verſal, and was cultivated without much labour. The natural wants of the inhabitants were thus ſupplied with very little trouble; and artificial wants had made no progreſs. But the preſent ſtate of theſe countries is very different. The Indians have learned from their conquerors a mul⯑titude of artificial wants, good houſes, variety of food, and rich cloaths, which muſt be imported, becauſe not manufactured at home. They are prohibited from exerciſing any art or calling ex⯑cept agriculture, which ſcarce affords them ne⯑ceſſaries; and this obliges a great proportion of them to live ſingle. Even agriculture itſelf is cramped; for in moſt of the provinces there is a [92] prohibition to plant vines or olives. In ſhort, it is believed that the inhabitants who exiſted at the Spaniſh invaſion are reduced to a fourth part. The ſavages alſo of North-America who border on the European ſettlements are viſibly diminiſh⯑ing. When the Engliſh ſettled in America, the five nations could raiſe 15,000 fighting men: at preſent they are not able to raiſe 2000. Upon the whole it is computed by able writers, that the preſent inhabitants of America amount not to a twentieth part of thoſe who exiſted when that continent was diſcovered by Columbus. This decay is aſcribed to the intemperate uſe of ſpirits, and to the ſmall-pox, both of them introduced by the Europeans*.
[93] It is obſervable, that every ſort of plague becomes more virulent when tranſplanted, than in its na⯑tive place. The plague commits leſs ravage in Egypt, its native place, than in any other coun⯑try. The venereal diſeaſe was for many ages more violent and deſtructive in Europe, than ever it was in America, where it was firſt known. The people who ſailed with Chriſtopher Colum⯑bus, brought it to Spain from Hiſpaniola. Co⯑lumbus, with thirty or forty of his ſailors, went directly to Barcelona, where the King then was, to render an account of his voyage. All the in⯑habitants, who at that time tripled the pre⯑ſent number, were immediately ſeized with the venereal diſeaſe, which raged ſo furiouſly as to threaten deſtruction to all. The ſmall pox comes under the ſame obſervation; for it has ſwept away many more in America, than ever it did in Europe. In the year 1713, the crew of a Dutch veſſel infected the Hottentots with the ſmall pox; which left ſcarce a third of the inhabi⯑tants. And the ſame fate befel the Laplanders and Greenlanders. In all appearance, that diſ⯑eaſe, if it abate not ſoon of its tranſplanted vi⯑rulence, will extirpate the natives of North Ame⯑rica; for they know little of inoculation.
But ſpirituous liquors are a ſtill more effectual cauſe of depopulation. The American ſavages, male and female, are inordinately fond of ſpiritu⯑ous liquors; and ſavages generally abandon them⯑ſelves to appetite, without the leaſt control from ſhame. The noxious effects of intemperance in ſpirits, are too well known, from fatal experi⯑ence among ourſelves: before the uſe of gin was prohibited, the populace of London were debi⯑litated by it to a degree of loſing, in a great mea⯑ſure, the power of procreation. Happily for the human ſpecies, the invention of ſavages ne⯑ver [94] reached the production of gin; for ſpirits in that early period would have left not one perſon alive, not a ſingle Noah to reſtore the race of men: in order to accompliſh the plan of Provi⯑dence, creation muſt have been renewed oftener than once*.
In the temperate climates of the old world, there is great uniformity in the gradual progreſs of men from the ſavage ſtate to the higheſt civi⯑lization; beginning with hunting and fiſhing, advancing to flocks and herds, and thereafter to agriculture and commerce. One would be much diſappointed if he expected the ſame progreſs in America. Among the northern tribes, there is nothing that reſembles the ſhepherd-ſtate: they continue hunters and fiſhers as originally; be⯑cauſe there is no cauſe ſo potent as to force them from that ſtate to become ſhepherds. So far clear. But there is another fact of which we have no example in the old world, that ſeems not ſo eaſily explained; theſe people, without paſſing through the ſhepherd-ſtate, have advan⯑ced to ſome degree of agriculture. Before the ſeventeenth century, the Iroquois, or five nati⯑ons, had villages, and cultivated Indian corn: the Cherokees have many ſmall towns; they raiſe corn in abundance, and fence in their fields: they breed poultry, and have orchards of peach⯑trees: The Chickeſaws and Creek Indians live [95] pretty much in the ſame manner. The Apala⯑chites ſow and reap in common; and put up the corn in granaries, to be diſtrubuted among in⯑dividuals when they want food. The Hurons raiſe great quantities of corn, not only for their own uſe, but for commerce. Many of theſe na⯑tions, particularly the Cherokees, have of late got horſes, ſwine, and tame cattle; an improve⯑ment borrowed from the Europeans. But corn is of an early date: when Sir Richard Greenville took poſſeſſion of Virginia in the reign of Queen Elizabeth, the natives had corn; and Hennepin aſſures us, that the nations bordering on the Miſ⯑ſiſippi had corn long before they were viſited by any European. Huſbandry, it is true, is among thoſe people ſtill in its infancy; being left to the women, who ſow, who reap, who ſtore up in public granaries, and who diſtribute as need re⯑quires. The inhabitants of Guiana in South America, continue to this day hunters and fiſh⯑ers. But though they have neither flocks nor herds, they have ſome huſbandry; for the wo⯑men plant caſſava, yams, and plantains. They make a liquor, like our ale, termed piworee, which they drink with their food. And though they are extremely fond of that liquor, their indolence makes them often neglect to provide againſt want. To a people having a violent pro⯑penſity to intemperance, as all ſavages have, this improvidence is a bleſſing; for otherwiſe they would wallow in perpetual drunkenneſs. They are by no means ſingular; for unconcern about futurity is the characteriſtic of all ſavages. To forego an immediate for a diſtant enjoyment, can only be ſuggeſted by cultivated reaſon. When the Canary Iſlands were firſt viſited by the Eu⯑ropeans, which was in the fourteenth century, the inhabitants bad corn; for which the ground [96] was prepared in the following manner. They had a wooden inſtrument, not unlike a hoe, with a ſpur or tooth at the end, on which was fixed a goat's horn. With this inſtrument the ground was ſtirred; and if rain came not in its proper ſeaſon, water was brought by canals from the ri⯑vulets. It was the womens province to reap the corn: they took only the ears; which they threſhed with ſticks, or beat with their feet, and then winnowed in their hands. Huſbandry pro⯑bably will remain in its preſent ſtate among American ſavages; for as they are decreaſing daily, they can have no difficulty about food. The fact however is ſingular, of a people uſing corn before tame cattle: there muſt be a cauſe, which, on better acquaintance with that people, will probably be diſcovered.
America is full of political wonders. At the time of the Spaniſh invaſion, the Mexicans and Peruvians had made great advances toward the perfection of ſociety, while the northern tribes, ſeparated from them by diſtance only, remained in the original ſtate of hunters and fiſhers, and remain ſo at this day. To explain the difference, appears difficult. It is ſtill more difficult to ex⯑plain, why the Mexicans and Peruvians, in⯑habitants of the torrid zone, were highly poliſh⯑ed in the arts of ſociety and government; con⯑ſidering that in the old world, the inhabitants of the torrid zone are, for the moſt part, little better than ſavages. We are not ſufficiently ac⯑quainted with the natural hiſtory of America, nor with that of its people, to attempt an ex⯑planation of theſe wonders: it is however part of our taſk, to ſtate the progreſs of ſociety among the Mexicans and Peruvians; which cannot fail to amuſe the reader, as he will find theſe two na⯑tions differing eſſentially from the North-Ameri⯑can [97] tribes, in every article of manners, govern⯑ment, and police.
When the Spaniards invaded America, the Mexicans were ſkilful in agriculture. Maize was their chief grain, which, by careful culture, produced great plenty, even in the mountainous country of Tlaſcalla. They had gardening and botany, as well as agriculture: a phyſic-garden belonging to the Emperor was open to every one for gathering medicinal plants.
The art of cookery was far advanced among that people. Montezuma's table was generally covered with 200 diſhes, many of them exqui⯑ſitely dreſſed in the opinion even of the Spaniards. They uſed ſalt, which was made by the ſun.
The women were dexterous at ſpinning; and manufactures of cotton and hair abounded every where.
The populouſneſs of Mexico and Peru afford irrefragable evidence, that the arts of peace were there carried to a great height. The city of Mexico contained 60,000 families*; and Mon⯑tezuma had thirty vaſſals who could bring into the field, each of them, 100,000 fighting men. Tlaſcalla, a neighbouring republic, governed by a ſenate, was ſo populous as to be almoſt a match for the Emperor of Mexico.
The public edifices in the city of Mexico, and houſes of the nobility, were of ſtone, and well built. The royal palace had thirty gates [98] opening to as many ſtreets. The principal front was of jaſper, black, red, and white, well po⯑liſhed. Three ſquares, built and adorned like the front, led to Montezuma's apartment, hav⯑ing large rooms, floors covered with mats of dif⯑ferent kinds, walls hung with a mixture of cot⯑ton-cloth and rabbit-furs; the innermoſt room adorned with hangings of feathers, beautified with various figures in lively colours. In that building, large ceilings were formed ſo artifici⯑ally without nails, as to make the planks ſuſtain each other. Water was brought into the city of Mexico, from a mountain at a league's diſtance.
Gold and ſilver were in ſo high eſteem, that veſſels made of theſe metals were permitted to none but to the Emperor. Conſidering the value put upon gold and ſilver, the want of current coin would argue great dulneſs in that nation, if inſtances did not daily occur of improvements, after being carried to a conſiderable height, ſtop⯑ping ſhort at the very threſhold of perfection. The want of current coin made fairs the more neceſſary, which were carried on with the moſt perfect regularity: judges on the ſpot decided mercantile differences; and inferior officers, making conſtant circuits, preſerved peace and order. The abundance and variety of the com⯑modities brought to market, and the order pre⯑ſerved by ſuch multitudes, amazed the Spani⯑ards; a ſpectacle deſerving admiration, as a teſ⯑timony of the grandeur and good government of that extenſive empire.
The fine arts were not unknown in Mexico. Their goldſmiths were excellent workmen, par⯑ticularly in moulding gold and ſilver into the form of animals. Their painters made land⯑ſcapes and other imitations of nature with fea⯑thers, ſo artfully mixed as to beſtow both life [99] and colouring; of which ſort of work, there were inſtances no leſs extraordinary for pati⯑ence than for ſkill. Their drinking-cups were of the fineſt earth exquiſitely made, differing from each other in colour, and even in ſmell. Of the ſame materials, they made great variety of veſſels both for uſe and ornament.
They were not ignorant either of muſic or of poetry; and one of their capital amuſements was ſongs ſet to muſic upon the atchievements of their kings and anceſtors.
With ſuch a progreſs both in the uſeful and fine arts, is it not ſurpriſing, that though they had meaſures, they knew nothing of weights?
As to the art of writing, a capital article in the conduct of government, they were extreme⯑ly deficient. That art, as mentioned above, was no farther advanced than the uſing figures com⯑poſed of painted feathers, by which they made a ſhift to communicate ſome ſimple thoughts; and in that manner was Montezuma informed of the Spaniſh invaſion.
There was great ingenuity ſhewn in regulating the calendar: the Mexican year was divided into 365 days; and into 18 months, containing 20 days each, which made 360; the remaining five intercalary days were added at the end of the year, for making it correſpond to the courſe of the ſun. They religiouſly employed theſe five days upon diverſions, being of opinion that they were appropriated to that end by their anceſtors.
Murder, theft, and corruption in officers of ſtate, were capital crimes. Adultery alſo was capital; for female chaſtity was in high eſtima⯑tion. At the ſame time, conſent was deem⯑ed a ſufficient cauſe of divorce, the law leaving it to the parties concerned, who ought to be the [100] beſt judges. In caſe of a divorce, the father took care of the male children, leaving the fe⯑male children with the mother. But to prevent raſh ſeparations, it was capital for them to unite again.
It may be gathered from what has been ſaid, that there was a diſtinction of rank among the Mexicans. So religiouſly was it obſerved, as to be diſplayed even in their buildings: the city of Mexico was divided into two parts, one appro⯑priated to the Emperor and nobility, and one left to plebeians.
Education of children was an important article in the Mexican police. Public ſchools were al⯑lotted for plebeian children; and colleges well endowed for the ſons of the nobility, where they continued till they were fit for buſineſs. The maſters were conſidered as officers of ſtate; not without reaſon, as their office was to qualify young men for ſerving their king and country. Such of the young nobles as made choice of a military life, were ſent to the army, and made to ſuffer great hardſhips before they could be inliſt⯑ed. They had indeed a powerful motive for perſeverance, the moſt honourable of all em⯑ployments being that of a ſoldier. Young wo⯑men of quality were educated with no leſs care, by proper matrons choſen with the utmoſt cir⯑cumſpection.
As hereditary nobility, eſpecially in an exten⯑ſive empire, leads to monarchy, the government of Mexico was monarchichal; and as the pro⯑greſs of monarchy is from being elective to be hereditary, Mexico had advanced no farther than to be an elective monarchy, of which Montezu⯑ma was the eleventh king. It would in time have become hereditary, had it not been ſubdued by [101] the Spaniards. And it was an example of an elective monarchy that approaches the neareſt to hereditary; for the power of election, as well as the privilege of being elected, were confined to the princes of the blood royal. As a talent for war was chiefly regarded in chuſing a ſucceſſor to the throne, the Mexican kings always command⯑ed their own armies. The Emperor-elect, be⯑fore his coronation, was obliged to make ſome conqueſt, or perform ſome warlike exploit; a cuſtom that ſupported the military ſpirit, and en⯑larged the kingdom. From every king was ex⯑acted a coronation-oath, to adhere to the religi⯑on of his anceſtors, to maintain the laws and cuſtoms of the empire, and to be a father to his people.
The various affairs of government were diſtri⯑buted among different boards with great proprie⯑ty. The management of the royal patrimony was allotted to one board; appeals from inferior tribunals, to another; the levying of troops, and the providing of magazines, to a third: matters of ſupreme importance were reſerved to a coun⯑cil of ſtate, held generally in the king's preſence. Theſe boards, all of them, were compoſed of men experienced in the arts of war and of peace: the council of ſtate was compoſed of thoſe who elected the Emperor.
Concerning the patrimony of the crown, mines of gold and ſilver belonged to the Emperor; and the duty on ſalt brought in a great revenue. But the capital duty was, a third of the land-rents, the eſtates of the nobles excepted; upon whom no tribute was impoſed, but to ſerve in the army with a number of their vaſſals, and to guard the Emperor's perſon. Goods manufactured and ſold were ſubjected to a duty; which was not preju⯑dicial [102] to their manufactures, becauſe there was no rival nation within reach.
Montezuma introduced a multitude of ceremo⯑nies into his court, tending to inſpire veneration for his perſon; an excellent policy in rude times, of however little ſignificancy among nations en⯑lightened and rational. Veneration and humility were ſo much the tone of the court, that it was even thought indecent in the Mexican lords, to appear before the King in their richeſt habits. Veſſels of gold and ſilver were appropriated to his table, and not permitted even to the princes of the blood. The table-cloths and napkins, made of the fineſt cotton, with the earthen ware, ne⯑ver made a ſecond appearance at the Emperor's table, but were diſtributed among the ſervants.
In war, their offenſive weapons were bows and arrows; and as iron was not known in America, their arrows were headed with bones ſharpened at the point. They uſed alſo darts, and long wooden ſwords, in which were fixed ſharp flints; and men of more than ordinary ſtrength fought with clubs. They beſide had ſlingers, who threw ſtones with great force and dexterity. Their defenſive arms, uſed only by commanders and perſons of diſtinction, were a coat of quilted cotton, a ſort of breaſt-plate, and a ſhield of wood or tortoiſe-ſhell, adorned with plates of ſuch metal as they could procure. The private men ſought naked; their faces and bodies being deformed with paint, in order to terrify the ene⯑my. They had warlike inſtruments of muſic, ſuch as ſea-ſhells, flutes made of large canes, and a ſort of drum made of the trunk of a tree hollowed. Their battalions conſiſted of great numbers crouded together, without even the ap⯑pearance of order. They attacked with fury, and terrible outcries, in order to intimidate the [103] enemy; a practice prompted by nature, and for⯑merly uſed by many nations. It was not deſpiſed even by the Romans; for Cato the elder was wont to ſay, that he had obtained more victories by the throats of his ſoldiers, than by their ſwords; and Caeſar applauds his own ſoldiers, above thoſe of Pompey, for their warlike ſhouts. Eagerneſs to engage is vented in loud cries: and the effects are excellent: they redouble the ardor of thoſe who attack, at the ſame time that they ſtrike terror into the enemy.
Their armies were formed with eaſe: the prin⯑ces of the empire, with the cacics or governors of provinces, were obliged to repair to the general rendezvous, each with his quota of men.
Their fortifications were trunks of large trees, fixed in the ground like palliſades, leaving no in⯑tervals but what were barely ſufficient for diſ⯑charging their arrows upon the enemy.
Military orders were inſtituted, with peculiar habits, as marks of diſtinction and honour; and each cavalier bore the device of his order, paint⯑ed upon his robe, or fixed to it. Montezuma founded a new order of knighthood, into which princes only were admitted, or nobles deſcended from the royal ſtock; and as a token of its ſupe⯑riority, he became one of its members. The knights of that order had part of their hair bound with a red ribbon, to which a taſſel was fixed hanging down to the ſhoulder. Every new ex⯑ploit was honoured with an additional taſſel; which made the knights with ardor embrace eve⯑ry opportunity to ſignalize themſelves. As no⯑thing can be better contrived than ſuch a regula⯑tion for ſupporting a military ſpirit, the Mexi⯑cans would have been invincible had they under⯑ſtood the order of battle: for want of which that potent empire fell a prey to a handful of ſtrangers. [104] I differ from thoſe who aſcribe that event to the fire-arms of the Spaniards, and to their horſes. Theſe could not be more terrible to the Mexi⯑cans, than elephants were at firſt to the Romans: but familiarity with theſe unwieldy animals, re⯑ſtored to the Romans their wonted courage; and the Mexicans probably would have behaved like the Romans, had they equalled the Romans in the art of war.
When that illuſtrious people, by their own ge⯑nius, without borrowing from others, had made ſuch proficiency in the arts of peace, as well as of war; is it not ſtrange, that with reſpect to religion they were no better than ſavages? They not only practiſed human ſacrifices, but dreſſed and eat the fleſh of thoſe that were ſacrificed. Their great temple was contrived to raiſe horror: upon the walls were multiplied the figures of nox⯑ious ſerpents: the heads of perſons ſacrificed were ſtuck up in different places, and carefully renewed when waſted by time. There were eight temples in the city, nearly of the ſame ar⯑chitecture; 2000 of a ſmaller ſize, dedicated to different idols; ſcarce a ſtreet without a tutelar deity; nor a calamity that had not an altar, to which the diſtreſſed might have recourſe for a re⯑medy. Unparallelled ignorance and ſtupidity, obliged every Emperor, at his coronation, to ſwear, that there ſhould be no unſeaſonable rains, no overflowing of rivers, no fields affected with ſterility, nor any man hurt with the bad influen⯑ces of the ſun. In ſhort, it was a ſlaviſh religi⯑on, built upon fear, not love. At the ſame time, they believed the immortality of the ſoul, and rewards and puniſhments in a future ſtate; which made them bury with their dead, quanti⯑ties of gold and ſilver, for defraying the expence of their journey; and alſo made them put to [105] death ſome of their ſervants to attend them. Women ſometimes, actuated with the ſame be⯑lief, were authors of their own death, in order to accompany their huſbands.
The author that we muſt chiefly rely on for an account of Peru is Garcilaſſo de la Vega: tho' he may be juſtly ſuſpected of partiality; for being of the Inca race, he beſtows on the Peruvian go⯑vernment, improvements of later times. The ar⯑ticles that appear the leaſt ſuſpicious are what fol⯑low.
The principle of the Peruvian conſtitution ſeems to have been an Agrarian law, of the ſtrict⯑eſt kind. To the ſovereign was firſt allotted a large proportion of land, for defraying the ex⯑pences of government; and the remainder was divided among his ſubjects in proportion to the number of each family. Theſe portions were not alienable: the ſovereign was held proprietor of the whole, as in the feudal ſyſtem; and from time to time the diſtribution was varied according to the circumſtances of families. This Agrarian law contributed undoubtedly to the populouſneſs of the kingdom of Peru.
It is a ſure ſign of improved agriculture, that aqueducts were made by the Peruvians for wa⯑tering their land. Their plough was of wood, a yard long, flat before, round behind, and point⯑ed at the end for piercing the ground. Agricul⯑ture ſeems to have been carried on by united la⯑bour: lands appropriated for maintaining the poor were firſt ploughed; next the portion al⯑lotted to ſoldiers performing duty in the field: then every man ſeparately ploughed his own field; after which he aſſiſted his neighbour: they pro⯑ceeded to the portion of the curaca or lord: and laſtly to the King's portion. In the month of [106] March they reaped their maize, and celebrated the harveſt with joy and feaſting.
There being no artiſt nor manufacturer by profeſſion, individuals were taught to do every thing for themſelves. Every one knew how to plough and manure the land: every one was a carpenter, a maſon, a ſhoemaker, a weaver, &c. and the women were the moſt ingenious and dili⯑gent of all. Blas Valera mentions a law, named the law of brotherhood, which, without the pro⯑ſpect of reward, obliged them to be mutually aid⯑ing and aſſiſting in ploughing, ſowing, and reap⯑ing, in building their houſes, and in every ſort of occupation.
As the art was unknown of melting down me⯑tals by means of bellows, long copper pipes were contrived, contracted at the further end, that the breath might act the more forcibly on the fire; and they uſed ten or twelve of theſe pipes toge⯑ther, when they wanted a very hot fire. Ha⯑ving no iron, their hatchets and pick-axes were of copper, and they had neither ſaw nor augre, nor any inſtrument of iron: ignorant of the uſe of nails, they tied their timber with cords of hemp. The tool they had for cutting ſtone, was a ſharp flint; and with that tool they ſhaped the ſtone by continual rubbing, more than by cut⯑ting. Having no engines for raiſing ſtones, they did all by ſtrength of arm. Theſe defects not⯑withſtanding, they erected great edifices; wit⯑neſs the fortreſs of Cuſco, a ſtupendous fabric. It paſſes all underſtanding, by what means the ſtones, or rather the great rocks, employed in that building, were brought from the quarry. One of theſe ſtones, meaſured by Acoſta, was thirty feet in length, eighteen in breadth, and ſix in thickneſs.
[107] Having neither ſciſſars nor needles of metal, they uſed a certain long thorn for a needle. The mirrors uſed by ladies of quality were of burniſh⯑ed copper: but ſuch implements of dreſs were reckoned too effeminate for the men.
With reſpect to muſic, they had an inſtru⯑ment of hollow canes glewed together, the notes of which were like thoſe of an organ. They had love-ſongs accompanied with a pipe; and war-ſongs, which were their feſtival entertain⯑ment. They compoſed and acted comedies and tragedies. The art of writing, properly ſo call⯑ed, was unknown: but ſilken threads, with knots caſt upon them of divers colours, enabled them to keep exact accounts, and to ſum them up with a readineſs that would have rivaled an expert European arithmetician. They had alſo attained to as much geometry as to meaſure their fields.
In war, their offenſive arms were the bow and arrow, lance, dart, club, and bill. Their de⯑fenſive arms, were the helmet and target. The army was provided from the King's ſtores, and was no burden upon the people.
In philoſophy, they had made no progreſs. An eclipſe of the moon was attributed to her be⯑ing ſick; and they fancied the milky way to be a ewe giving ſuck to a lamb. With regard to the ſetting ſun, they ſaid, that he was a good ſwim⯑mer, and that he pierced through the waves, to riſe next morning in the eaſt. But ſuch igno⯑rance is not wonderful; for no branch of ſcience can make a progreſs without writing.
The people were divided into ſmall bodies of ten families each: every diviſion had a head, and a regiſter was kept of the whole; a branch of public police, that very much reſembles the Eng⯑liſh decennaries.
[108] They made but two meals, one between eight and nine in the morning, the other before ſun⯑ſet. Idleneſs was puniſhed with infamy: even children were employed according to their capa⯑city. Public viſitors or monitors were appointed, having acceſs to every houſe, for inſpecting the manners of the inhabitants; who were rewarded or puniſhed according to their behaviour. Mo⯑deration and induſtry were ſo effectually enforced by this article of police, that few were reduced to indigence; and theſe got their food and cloth⯑ing out of the King's ſtores.
With reſpect to their laws and cuſtoms, chil⯑dren were bound to ſerve their parents until the age of twenty five; and marriage contracted before that time, without conſent of parents, was null. Polygamy was prohibited, and perſons were con⯑fined to marry within their own tribe. The tra⯑dition, that the Inca family were children of the ſun, introduced inceſt among them; for it was a matter of religion to preſerve their divine blood pure and unmixed.
It was the chief article of the Peruvian creed, upon which every other article of their religion depended, that the Inca family were children of their great god the ſun, and ſent by him to ſpread his worſhip and his laws among them. Nothing could have a greater influence upon an ignorant and credulous people, than ſuch a doctrine. The ſanctity of the Inca family was ſo deeply rooted in the hearts of the Peruvians, that no perſon of that family was thought capable of committing a crime. Such blind veneration for a family, makes it probable, that the government of Peru under the Incas had not ſubſiſted many years; for a government founded upon deceit and ſuperſtition, cannot long continue its authority. However that be, ſuch belief of the origin of the Incas, is [109] evidence of great virtue and moderation in that family; for any groſs act of tyranny or injuſtice, would have opened the eyes of the people to ſee their error. Moderation in the ſovereign, and in the ſubjects obedience without reſerve, cannot fail to produce a government mild and gentle; which was verified in that of Peru, ſo mild and gentle, that to manure and cultivate the lands of the Inca, and to ſay up the produce in ſtore⯑houſes, were the only burdens impoſed upon the people, if it was not ſometimes to make cloaths and weapons for the army. At the ſame time their kings were ſo revered, that theſe articles of labour were performed with great alacrity.
The government was equally gentle with regard to puniſhments. Indeed very few crimes were committed, being conſidered as a ſort of rebellion againſt their great god the ſun. The only crime that ſeems to have been puniſhed with ſeverity, is the marauding of ſoldiers; for death was inflicted, however inconſiderable the damage.
In this empire, there appears to have been the moſt perfect union between law and religion; which could not fail to produce obedience, order, and tranquility, among that people, though ex⯑tremely numerous. The Inca family was famed for moderation: they made conqueſts in order to civilize their neighbours; and as they ſeldom if ever tranſgreſſed the bounds of morality, no other art was neceſſary to preſerve the government entire, but to keep the people ignorant of true religion. They had virgins dedicated to the ſun, who, like the veſtal virgins in Rome, were under a vow of perpetual chaſtity.
This ſubject ſhall be concluded with ſome ſlight obſervations on the two governments I have been deſcribing. Comparing them together, the Mex⯑ican [110] government ſeems to have been ſupported by arms; that of Peru by religion.
The kings of Peru were hereditary and abſo⯑lute: thoſe of Mexico elective. In contradiction however to political principles, the government of Peru was by far the milder. It is mentioned above, that the electors of the Mexican kings were hereditary princes; and the ſame electors compoſed the great council of ſtate. Monteſquieu therefore has been miſinformed when he terms this a deſpotic monarchya: a monarchy can never be deſpotic, where the ſovereign is limited by a great council, the members of which are in⯑dependent of him. As little reaſon has he to term Peru deſpotic. An abſolute monarchy it was, but the fartheſt in the world from being deſpotic: on the contrary, we find not in hiſtory any government ſo well contrived for the good of the people. An Agrarian law, firmly rooted, prevented that great inequality of rank and riches which lead to luxury, and diſſolution of manners: a commonwealth was naturally the reſult of ſuch a conſtitution; and probably would have taken place, had it not been for a government no leſs ſuitable, and ſtill more mild, viz. a theocracy under a family ſent from heaven to make them happy. This wild opinion, ſupported by igno⯑rance and ſuperſtition, proved an effectual bar againſt tyranny in the monarch; a moſt exempla⯑ry conduct on his part being neceſſary for ſup⯑porting the opinion of his divinity. Upon the whole, comprehending king and ſubject, there perhaps never exiſted more virtue in any other [111] government, whether monarchical or republi⯑can.
In Peru there are traces of ſome diſtinction of ranks, ariſing probably from office merely, which, as in France, were a bulwark to the monarch againſt the peaſants. The great ſuperiority of the Peruvian Incas, as demi-gods, did not admit a he⯑reditary nobility.
With reſpect to the progreſs of arts and manu⯑factures, the two nations differed widely: in Mexico, arts and manufactures were carried to a ſurpriſing height, conſidering the tools they had to work with: in Peru, they had made no progreſs, every man, as among mere ſavages, providing the neceſſaries of life for himſelf. As the world goes at preſent, ſuch numbers are employed upon our multiplied wants, that not above one of a hund⯑red can be ſpared for war. In ancient times, when theſe wants were few, and not much en⯑larged beyond nature, it is computed that an eighth part could be ſpared for war: and hence the numerous armies we read of in the hiſtory of ancient nations. The Peruvians had it in their power to go ſtill farther: it was poſſible to arm the whole males capable of ſervice: leaving the women to ſupply the few neceſſaries that might be wanted during a ſhort campaign; and ac⯑cordingly we find that the Incas were great con⯑querors.
The religion of the Peruvians, conſidered in a political light, was excellent. The veneration they paid their ſovereign upon a falſe religious principle, was their only ſuperſtition; and that ſuperſtition contributed greatly to improve their morals and their manners: on the other hand, the religion of Mexico was abominable.
[112] Upon the whole, there never was a country deſtitute of iron, where arts ſeem to have been carried higher than in Mexico; and, bating their religion, there never was a country deſtitute of writing, where government ſeems to have been more perfect. I except not the government of Peru, which, not being founded on political prin⯑ciples, but on ſuperſtition, might be more mild, but was far from being ſo ſolidly founded.
SKETCHES OF THE HISTORY OF MAN.
BOOK III.
Progreſs of SCIENCES.
[]PREFACE.
MORALITY, theology, and the art of rea⯑ſoning, are three great branches of a learn⯑ed education; and are juſtly held to be ſo, be⯑cauſe they are our only ſure guides in paſſing through the intricate paths of life. They are indeed not eſſential to thoſe termed men of the world: the moſt profound philoſopher makes but an inſipid figure in faſhionable company; would be ſomewhat ridicu⯑lous at a court-ball; and an abſolute abſurdity among the gameſters at Arthur's, or jockeys at New⯑market. But, theſe cogent objections notwithſtand⯑ing, I venture to pronounce ſuch ſtudies to be not al⯑together [114] unſuitable to a gentleman. Man is a creature full of curioſity; and to gratify that appe⯑tite, many roam through the world, ſubmitting to heat and cold, nay to hunger and thirſt, without a ſigh. Could indeed that troubleſome gueſt be expelled, we might hug ourſelves in ignorance; and, like true men of the world, undervalue knowledge, that can neither procure money, nor a new ſenſual plea⯑ſure. But, alas! the expulſion is not in the power of every one; and thoſe who have not that power, will probably think it not amiſs, to employ their curioſity upon ſtudies that make them good mem⯑bers of ſociety, and endear them to every perſon of virtue.
And were we even men of the world in ſuch per⯑fection, as to regard nothing but our own intereſt; yet does not ignorance lay us open to the crafty and deſigning? and does not the art of reaſoning guard many an honeſt man from being miſled by ſubtle ſo⯑phiſms? With reſpect to right and wrong, not even paſſion is more dangerous than error. And as to re⯑ligion, better it were to ſettle in a conviction that there is no God, than to be in a ſtate of wavering and ſluctuation; ſometimes indulging every looſe de⯑ſire, as if we were not accountable beings; and ſometimes yielding to ſuperſtitious fears, as if there were no god but the devil. To a well-diſpoſed mind, the exiſtence of a ſupreme benevolent Deity, appears highly probable: and if happily the ſtudy of theology lead us to a conviction that there really is ſuch a be⯑ing; the conviction will be a ſource of conſtant en⯑joyment, which I boldly ſet above the titillating plea⯑ſures of external ſenſe. Poſſibly there may be leſs preſent amuſement in abſtract ſtudies, than in news⯑papers, in party-pamphlets, or in Hoyle upon Whiſt: but let us for a moment anticipate futurity, and ima⯑gine that we are reviewing paſt tranſactions,—how pleaſant the retroſpect of thoſe who have maintained [115] the dignity of their nature, and employed their ta⯑lents to the beſt purpoſes!
Contradictory opinions that have influence on prac⯑tice, will be regretted by every perſon of a ſound heart; and as erroneous opinions are commonly the reſult of imperfect education, I would gladly hope, that a remedy is not altogether out of reach. At the revival of arts and ſciences, the learned languages were our ſole ſtudy, becauſe in them were locked up all the treaſures of uſeful knowledge. This ſtudy has long ago ceaſed to be the chief object of educati⯑on; and yet the original plan is handed down to us with very little variation. Wiſhing to contribute to a more perfect ſyſtem of education, I preſent to the public the following ſketches. The books that have been publiſhed upon morality, theology, and the art of reaſoning, are not eminent either for ſimplicity, or for clear ideas. To introduce theſe into the ſubjects mentioned, is my aim; with what ſucceſs, is chear⯑fully ſubmitted to the judgment of others. The hiſ⯑torical part, hitherto much neglected, is neceſſary as a branch of my general plan; and I am hopeful, that beſide inſtruction, it will contribute to recreation, which, in abſtract ſtudies, is no leſs neceſſary than pleaſant.
SKETCH I.
Principles and Progreſs of REASON.
[116]SECTION I.
PRINCIPLES OF REASON.
EVERY affirmation whatever be the ſubject, is termed a propoſition.
Truth and error are qualities of propoſitions. A propoſition that ſays a thing is what it is in re⯑ality, is termed a true propoſition. A propoſition that ſays a thing is what it is not in reality, is termed an erroneous propoſition.
Our knowledge of what is agreeable and diſa⯑greeable in objects is derived from the ſenſe of beauty, handled in Elements of Criticiſm. Our knowledge of right and wrong in actions, is de⯑rived from the moral ſenſe, to be handled in the ſketch immediately following. Our knowledge of truth and error is derived from various ſour⯑ces.
[117] Our external ſenſes are one ſource of know⯑ledge: they lay open to us external ſubjects, their qualities, their actions, with events produced by theſe actions. The internal ſenſes are another ſource of knowledge: they lay open to us things paſſing in the mind; thinking, for example, de⯑liberating, inclining, reſolving, willing, conſent⯑ing, and other actions; and they alſo lay open to us our emotions and paſſions. There is a ſenſe by which we perceive the truth of many propoſi⯑tions; ſuch as, That every thing which begins to exiſt, muſt have a cauſe; That every effect adapted to ſome end or purpoſe, proceeds from a deſigning cauſe; and, That every effect adapted to a good end or purpoſe, proceeds from a de⯑ſigning and benevolent cauſe. A multitude of axioms in every ſcience, particularly in mathe⯑matics, are perceived to be equally true. By a peculiar ſenſe, of which afterward, we know that there is a Deity. By another ſenſe we know, that the external ſigns of paſſion are the ſame in all men; that animals of the ſame external ap⯑pearance, are of the ſame ſpecies; and that ani⯑mals of the ſame ſpecies, have the ſame proper⯑tiesa. By another ſenſe we ſee into futurity: we know that the ſun will riſe to-morrow; that the earth will perform its wonted courſe round the ſun; that winter and ſummer will follow each other in ſucceſſion; that a ſtone dropt from the hand will fall to the ground; and a thouſand other ſuch propoſitions.
There are many propoſitions, the truth of which is not ſo apparent: a proceſs of reaſoning is neceſſary, of which afterward.
[118] Human teſtimony is another ſource of know⯑ledge. So framed are we by nature, as to rely on human teſtimony; by which we are informed of beings, attributes, and events, that never came under any of our ſenſes.
The knowledge that is derived from the ſources mentioned, is of different kinds. In ſome caſes, our knowledge includes abſolute certainty, and produces the higheſt degree of conviction: in other caſes, probability comes in place of certain⯑ty, and the conviction is inferior in degree. Know⯑ledge of the latter kind is diſtinguiſhed into belief, which concerns facts; and opinion, which con⯑cerns relations, and other things that fall not un⯑der the denomination of facts. In contradiſtinc⯑tion to opinion and belief, that ſort of know⯑ledge which includes abſolute certainty, and pro⯑duces the higheſt degree of conviction, retains its proper name. To explain what is here ſaid, I enter into particulars.
The ſenſe of ſeeing, with very few exceptions, affords knowledge in its proper ſenſe. It is not in our power to doubt of the exiſtence of a perſon we ſee, touch, and converſe with; and when ſuch is our conſtitution, it is a vain attempt to call in queſtion the authority of our ſenſe of ſeeing, as ſome writers pretend to do. No one ever call⯑ed in queſtion the exiſtence of internal actions and paſſions, laid open to us by internal ſenſe; and there is as little ground for doubting of what we ſee. The ſenſe of ſeeing, it is true, is not always correct: through different mediums the ſame object is ſeen differently: to a jaundiced eye every thing appears yellow; and to one intoxi⯑cated with liquor, two candles ſometimes appear four. But we are never left without remedy in ſuch a caſe: it is the province of the reaſoning faculty, to correct every error of that kind.
[119] An objection of ſight, when recalled to mind by the power of memory, is termed an idea or ſecondary perception. An original perception, as ſaid above, affords knowledge in its proper ſenſe; but a ſecondary perception affords belief only. And Nature in this, as in all other inſtances, is faithful to truth; for it is evident, that we cannot be ſo certain of the exiſtence of an object in its abſence, as when preſent.
With reſpect to many abſtract propoſitions, of which inſtances are above given, we have an ab⯑ſolute certainty and conviction of their truth, derived to us from various ſenſes. We can, for example, entertain as little doubt, that every thing which begins to exiſt, muſt have a cauſe, as that the ſun is in the firmament; and as little doubt that he will riſe to-morrow, as that he is now ſet. There are many other propoſitions, the truth of which is probable only, not abſolutely certain; as, for example, that things will conti⯑nue in their ordinary ſtate. That natural ope⯑rations are performed in the ſimpleſt manner, is an axiom of natural philoſophy: it may be pro⯑bable, but is far from being certain*.
[120] In every one of the inſtances given, conviction ariſes from a ſingle act of perception: for which reaſon, knowledge acquired by means of that perception, not only knowledge in its proper ſenſe, but alſo opinion and belief, are termed intuitive knowledge. But there are many things, the knowledge of which is not obtained with ſo much facility. Propoſitions for the moſt part require a proceſs or operation in the mind, termed reaſoning; leading, by certain intermediate ſteps, to the propoſition that is to be demonſtrated or made evident; which, in oppoſition to intuitive knowledge, is termed diſcurſive knowledge. This proceſs or operation muſt be explained, in order to underſtand the nature of reaſoning. And as reaſoning is moſtly employed in diſcovering relati⯑ons, I ſhall draw my examples from them. Every propoſition concerning relations, is an affirmation of a certain relation between two ſubjects. If the relation affirmed appear not intuitively, we muſt ſearch for a third ſubject, that appears in⯑tuitively to be connected with each of the others, by the relation affirmed: and if ſuch a ſubject be found, the propoſition is demonſtrated; for it is intuitively certain, that two ſubjects, connected with a third by any particular relation, muſt be connected together by the ſame relation. The longeſt chain of reaſoning may be linked together in this manner. Running over ſuch a chain, every one of the ſubjects muſt appear intuitively to be connected with that immediately preceding, and with that immediately ſubſequent, by the relation affirmed in the propoſition; and from the whole united, the propoſition, as above mention⯑ed, muſt appear intuitively certain. The laſt ſtep of the proceſs is termed a concluſion, being the laſt or concluding perception.
[121] No ſort of reaſoning affords ſo clear a notion of the foregoing progreſs, as that which is mathematical. Equality is the only mathematical relation; and compariſon therefore is the only means by which mathematical propoſitions are aſcertained. To that ſcience belong a ſet of intuitive propoſitions, termed axioms, which are all founded on equality. For ex⯑ample: Divide two equal lines, each of them, into a thouſand equal parts, a ſingle part of the one line muſt be equal to a ſingle part of the other. Second: Take ten of theſe parts from the one line, and as many from the other, and the remaining parts muſt be equal: which is more ſhortly expreſ⯑ſed thus: From two equal lines take equal parts, and the remainders will be equal; or add equal parts, and the ſums will be equal. Third: If two things be, in the ſame reſpect, equal to a third, the one is equal to the other in the ſame reſpect. I proceed to ſhow the uſe of theſe axi⯑oms. Two things may be equal without being intuitively ſo; which is the caſe of the equality between the three angles of a triangle and two right angles. To demonſtrate that truth, it is neceſſary to ſearch for ſome other angles, which appear by intuition to be equal to both. If this property cannot be diſcovered in any one ſet of angles, we muſt go more leiſurely to work, by trying to find angles that are equal to the three angles of a triangle. Theſe being diſcovered, we next try to find other angles equal to the an⯑gles now diſcovered; and ſo on in the compariſon, till at laſt we diſcover a ſet of angles, equal not only to thoſe thus introduced, but alſo to two right angles. We thus connect the two parts of the original propoſition, by a number of interme⯑diate equalities; and by that means perceive, that theſe two parts are equal among themſelves: it being an intuitive propoſition, as mentioned [122] above, That two things are equal, each of which in the ſame reſpect, is equal to a third.
I proceed to a different example, which con⯑cerns the relation between cauſe and effect. The propoſition to be demonſtrated is, ‘"That there exiſts a good and intelligent Being, who is the cauſe of all the wiſe and benevolent effects that are produced in the government of this world."’ That there are ſuch effects, is in the preſent ex⯑ample the fundamental propoſition, which is ta⯑ken for granted, becauſe it is verified by experi⯑ence. In order to diſcover the cauſe of theſe ef⯑fects, I begin with an intuitive propoſition men⯑tioned above, ‘"That every effect adapted to a good end or purpoſe, proceeds from a deſign⯑ing and benevolent cauſe."’ The next ſtep is, to examine whether man can be the cauſe: he is provided indeed with ſome ſhare of wiſdom and benevolence; but the effects mentioned are far above his power, and no leſs above his wiſdom. Neither can this earth be the cauſe, nor the ſun, the moon, the ſtars; for, far from being wiſe and benevolent, they are not even ſenſible. If theſe be excluded, we are unavoidably led to an inviſible being, endowed with boundleſs power, goodneſs, and intelligence; and that inviſible be⯑ing is termed God.
Reaſoning requires two mental powers, name⯑ly, the powers of invention, and of perceiving relations. By the former are diſcovered interme⯑diate propoſitions, equally related to the funda⯑mental propoſition, and to the concluſion: and by the latter we perceive, that the different links which compoſe the chain of reaſoning, are all connected together by the ſame relation.
We can reaſon about matters of opinion and be⯑lief, as well as about matters of knowledge, pro⯑perly ſo termed. Hence reaſoning is diſtinguiſhed [123] into two kinds; demonſtrative, and probable. Demonſtrative reaſoning is alſo of two kinds; in the firſt, the concluſion is drawn from the nature and inherent properties of the ſubject: in the o⯑ther, the concluſion is drawn from ſome principle, of which we are certain by intuition. With re⯑ſpect to the firſt, we have no ſuch knowledge of the nature or inherent properties of any being, material or immaterial, as to draw concluſions from it with certainty. I except not even figure conſidered as a quality of matter, tho' it is the object of mathematical reaſoning. As we have no ſtandard for determining with preciſion the fi⯑gure of any portion of matter, we cannot with preciſion reaſon upon it: what appears to us a ſtraight line may be a curve, and what appears a rectilinear angle may be curvilinear. How then comes mathematical reaſoning to be demonſtra⯑tive? This queſtion may appear at firſt ſight puz⯑zling; and I know not that it has any where been diſtinctly explained. Perhaps what follows may be ſatisfactory.
The ſubjects of arithmetical reaſoning are num⯑bers. The ſubjects of mathematical reaſoning are figures. But what figures are ſubjects of mathematical reaſoning? Not ſuch as I ſee; but ſuch as I form an idea of, abſtracting from every imperfection. I explain myſelf. There is a power in man to form images of things that never exiſted; a golden mountain, for example, or a river running upward. This power operates up⯑on figures. There is perhaps no figure exiſting the ſides of which are ſtraight lines. But it is ea⯑ſy to form an idea of a line, that has no waving or crookedneſs in it; and it is eaſy to form an idea of a figure bounded by ſuch lines. Such ideal figures are the ſubjects of mathematical rea⯑ſoning; and theſe being perfectly clear and di⯑ſtinct, [124] are proper ſubjects for demonſtrative rea⯑ſoning of the firſt kind. Mathematical reaſoning however is not merely a mental entertainment: it is of real uſe in life, by directing the powers and properties of matter. There poſſibly may not be found any where a perfect globe, to an⯑ſwer the idea we form of that figure: but a globe may be made ſo near perfection, as that the properties demonſtrated to belong to the idea of a perfect globe will be nearly applicable to that figure. In a word, tho' ideas are, properly ſpeaking, the ſubject of mathematical evidence; yet the end and purpoſe of that evidence is, to di⯑rect us with reſpect to figures as they really ex⯑iſt; and the nearer any real figure approaches to the idea we form of it, with the greater accuracy will the mathematical truth be applicable.
The component parts of figures, viz. lines and angles, are extremely ſimple, requiring no defi⯑nition. Place before a child a crooked line, and one that has no appearance of being crooked; call the former a crooked line, the latter a ſtraight line; and the child will uſe theſe terms familiarly, without hazard of a miſtake. Draw a perpendi⯑cular upon paper; let the child advert, that the upward line leans neither to the right nor the left, and for that reaſon is termed a perpendicular: the child will apply that term familiarly to a tree, to the wall of a houſe, or to any other perpendi⯑cular. In the ſame manner, place before the child two lines diverging from each other, and two that have no appearance of diverging: call the latter parallel lines, and the child will have no difficulty of applying the ſame term to the ſides of a door or of a window. Yet ſo accuſtomed are we to definitions, that even theſe ſimple ideas are not ſuffered to eſcape. A ſtraight line, for example, is defined to be the ſhorteſt that can be [125] drawn between two given points. The fact is certain; but ſo far from a definition, that it is an inference drawn from the idea of a ſtraight line: and had I not beforehand a clear idea of a ſtraight line, I could not infer that it is the ſhorteſt be⯑tween two given points. D'Alembert ſtrains hard, but without ſucceſs, for a definition of a ſtraight line, and of the others mentioned. It is difficult to avoid ſmiling at his definition of paral⯑lel lines. Draw, ſays he, a ſtraight line: erect upon it two perpendiculars of the ſame length: upon their two extremities draw another ſtraight line; and that line is ſaid to be parallel to the firſt mentioned: as if, to underſtand what is meant by the expreſſion two parallel lines, we muſt firſt underſtand what is meant by a ſtraight line, by a perpendicular, and by two lines equal in length. A very ſlight reflection upon the ope⯑rations of his own mind, would have taught this author, that he could form the idea of parallel lines without running through ſo many intermedi⯑ate ſteps: ſight alone is ſufficient to explain the term to a boy, and even to a girl. At any rate, where is the neceſſity of introducing the line laſt mentioned? If the idea of parallels cannot be ob⯑tained from the two perpendiculars alone, the ad⯑ditional line drawn through their extremities will certainly not make it more clear.
Mathematical figures being in their nature com⯑plex, are capable of being defined; and from the foregoing ſimple ideas, it is eaſy to define every one of them. For example, a circle is a figure having a point within it, named the centre, through which all the ſtraight lines that can be drawn, and extended to the circumference, are equal; a ſurface bounded by four equal ſtraight lines, and having four right angles, is termed a [126] ſquare; and a cube is a ſolid, of which all the ſix ſurfaces are ſquares.
In the inveſtigation of mathematical truths, we aſſiſt the imagination, by drawing figures upon paper that reſemble our ideas. There is no ne⯑ceſſity for a perfect reſemblance: a black ſpot, which in reality is a ſmall round ſurface, ſerves to repreſent a mathematical point; and a black line, which in reality is a long narrow ſurface, ſerves to repreſent a mathematical line. When we rea⯑ſon about the figures compoſed of ſuch lines, it is ſufficient that theſe figures have ſome appearance of regularity: leſs or more is of no importance; becauſe our reaſoning is not founded upon them, but upon our ideas. Thus, to demonſtrate that the three angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles, a triangle is drawn upon paper, in order to keep the mind ſteady to its object, and to prevent wandering. After tracing the ſteps that lead to the concluſion, we are ſatisfied that the propoſition is true; being conſcious that the reaſoning is built upon the ideal figure, not upon that which is drawn upon the paper. And being alſo conſcious that the enquiry is carried on inde⯑pendent of any particular length of the ſides, we are ſatisfied of the univerſality of the propoſition, and of its being applicable to all triangles what⯑ever.
Numbers conſidered by themſelves, abſtract⯑edly from things, make the ſubject of arithme⯑tic. And with reſpect both to mathematical and arithmetical reaſonings, which frequently conſiſt of many ſteps, the proceſs is ſhortened by the in⯑vention of ſigns, which, by a ſingle daſh of the pen, expreſs clearly what would require many words. By that means, a very long chain of rea⯑ſoning is expreſſed by a few ſymbols; a method that contributes greatly to readineſs of compre⯑henſion. [127] If in ſuch reaſonings words were ne⯑ceſſary, the mind, embarraſſed with their multi⯑plicity, would have great difficulty to follow any long chain of reaſoning. A line drawn upon pa⯑per repreſents an ideal line, and a few ſimple characters repreſent the abſtract ideas of num⯑ber.
Arithmetical reaſoning, like mathematical, de⯑pends entirely upon the relation of equality, which can be aſcertained with the greateſt cer⯑tainty among many ideas. Hence, reaſonings upon ſuch ideas afford the higheſt degree of con⯑viction. I do not ſay, however, that this is al⯑ways the caſe; for a man who is conſcious of his own fallibility, is ſeldom without ſome de⯑gree of diffidence, where the reaſoning conſiſts of many ſteps. And though on a review no er⯑ror is diſcovered, yet he is conſcious there may be errors, though they have eſcaped him.
As to the other kind of demonſtrative reaſon⯑ing, founded on ſome propoſition of which we are intuitively certain; I juſtly call it demonſtra⯑tive, becauſe it affords the ſame conviction that ariſes from mathematical reaſoning. In both, the means of conviction are the ſame, viz. a clear perception of the relation between two ideas: and there are many relations of which we have ideas no leſs clear than of equality; wit⯑neſs ſubſtance and quality, the whole and its parts, cauſe and effect, and many others. From the intuitive propoſition, for example, That no⯑thing which begins to exiſt can exiſt without a cauſe, I can conclude, that ſome one being muſt have exiſted from all eternity, with no leſs cer⯑tainty, than that the three angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles.
What falls next in order, is that inferior kind of knowledge which is termed opinion; and [128] which, like knowledge properly ſo termed, is founded in ſome inſtances upon intuition, and in ſome upon reaſoning. But it differs from knowledge in the following particular, that it produces different degrees of conviction, ſome⯑times approaching to certainty, and ſometimes ſinking toward the verge of improbability. The conſtancy and uniformity of natural operations, is a fit ſubject for illuſtrating that difference. The future ſucceſſive changes of day and night, of winter and ſummer, and of other ſucceſſions which have hitherto been regular and uniform, fall under intuitive knowledge, becauſe of theſe we have the higheſt conviction. As the convic⯑tion is inferior of ſucceſſions that hitherto have been varied in any degree, theſe fall under intui⯑tive opinion. We expect ſummer after winter with the utmoſt confidence; but we have not the ſame confidence in expecting a hot ſummer or a cold winter. And yet the probability approaches much nearer to certainty, than the intuitive opi⯑nion we have, that the operations of nature are extremely ſimple, a propoſition that is very little relied on.
As to opinion founded on reaſoning, it is ob⯑vious, that the conviction produced by the rea⯑ſoning, can never riſe above what is produced by the intuitive propoſition upon which the rea⯑ſoning is founded. And that it may be weaker, will appear from conſidering, that even where the fundamental propoſition is certain, it may lead to the concluſive opinion by intermediate propoſitions, that are probable only, not certain. In a word, it holds in general with reſpect to every ſort of reaſoning, that the concluſive pro⯑poſition can never riſe higher in point of convic⯑tion, than the very loweſt of the intuitive pro⯑poſitions employed as ſteps in the reaſoning.
[129] The perception we have of the contingency of future events, opens a wide field to our reaſon⯑ing about probabilities. That perception involves more or leſs doubt according to its ſubject. In ſome inſtances, the event is perceived to be ex⯑tremely doubtful; in others it is perceived to be leſs doubtful. It appears altogether doubtful, in throwing a dye, which of the ſix ſides will turn up; and for that reaſon, we cannot juſtly con⯑clude for one rather than another. If one only of the ſix ſides be marked with a figure, we con⯑clude, that a blank will turn up; and five to one is an equal wager that ſuch will be the effect. In judging of the future behaviour of a man who has hitherto been governed by intereſt, we may conclude with a probability approaching to cer⯑tainty, that intereſt will continue to prevail.
Belief comes laſt in order, which, as defined above, is knowledge of the truth of facts that falls below certainty, and involves in its nature ſome degree of doubt. It is alſo of two kinds; one founded upon intuition, and one upon rea⯑ſoning. Thus, knowledge, opinion, belief, are all of them equally diſtinguiſhable into intuitive and diſcurſive. Of intuitive belief, I diſcover three different ſources or cauſes. Firſt, A preſent ob⯑ject. Secondly, An object formerly preſent. Third⯑ly, The teſtimony of others.
To have a clear conception of the firſt cauſe, it muſt be obſerved, that among the ſimple per⯑ceptions that compoſe the complex perception of a preſent object, a perception of real and preſent exiſtence is one. This perception riſes common⯑ly to certainty; in which caſe it is a branch of knowledge properly ſo termed; and is handled as ſuch above. But this perception falls below certainty in ſome inſtances; as when an object, ſeen at a great diſtance, or in a fog, is perceived [130] to be a horſe, but ſo indiſtinctly as to make it a probability only. The perception in ſuch a caſe is termed belief. Both perceptions are fundamen⯑tally of the ſame nature; being ſimple percepti⯑ons of real exiſtence. They differ only in point of accuracy: the perception of reality that makes a branch of knowledge, is ſo clear and diſtinct as to exclude all doubt or heſitation: the perception of reality that occaſions belief, being leſs clear and diſtinct, makes not the exiſtence of the object certain to us, but only probable.
With reſpect to the ſecond cauſe; the ex⯑iſtence of an abſent object, formerly ſeen, amounts not to a certainty; and therefore is the ſubject of belief only, not of knowledge. Things are in a continual flux from production to diſſolu⯑tion; and our ſenſes are accommodated to that variable ſcene: a preſent object admits no doubt of its exiſtence; but after it is removed, its ex⯑ſtence becomes leſs certain, and in time ſinks down to a ſlight degree of probability.
Human teſtimony, the third cauſe, produces belief, more or leſs ſtrong, according to circum⯑ſtances. In general, nature leads us to rely upon the veracity of each other; and commonly the degree of reliance is proportioned to the degree of veracity. Sometimes belief approaches to cer⯑tainty, as when it is founded on the evidence of perſons above all exception. Sometimes it ſinks to the loweſt degree of probability, as when a fact is told by one who has no great reputation for truth. The nature of the fact, common or uncommon, has likewiſe an influence: an ordinary incident gains credit upon very ſlight evidence; but it re⯑quires the ſtrongeſt evidence to overcome the im⯑probability of an event that deviates from the or⯑dinary courſe of nature. At the ſame time, it muſt be obſerved, that belief is not always found⯑ed [131] upon rational principles. There are biaſſes and weakneſſes in human nature that ſometimes diſturb the operation, and produce belief without ſufficient or proper evidence: we are diſpoſed to believe on every ſlight evidence, an intereſting event, however rare or ſingular, that alarms and agitates the mind; becauſe the mind, in agitati⯑on is remarkably ſuſceptible of impreſſions: for which reaſon, ſtories of ghoſts and apparitions paſs current with the vulgar. Eloquence alſo has great power over the mind; and, by making deep impreſſions, enforces the belief of facts upon evi⯑dence that would not be regarded in a cool mo⯑ment.
The dependence that our perception of real exiſtence, and conſequently belief, hath upon oral evidence, enlivens ſocial intercourſe, and promotes ſociety. But the perception of real exiſtence has a ſtill more extenſive influence; for from that perception is derived a great part of the entertainment we find in hiſtory, and in hiſtori⯑cal fablesa. At the ſame time, a perception that may be raiſed by fiction as well as by truth, would often miſlead, were we abandoned to its impulſe: but the God of nature hath provided a remedy for that evil, by erecting within the mind a tribunal, to which there lies an appeal from the raſh impreſſions of ſenſe. When the deluſion of eloquence or of dread ſubſides, the perplexed mind is uncertain what to believe. A regular proceſs commences, counſel is heard, evidence produced, and a final judgment pronounced, ſometimes confirming, ſometimes varying, the belief impreſſed upon us by the lively perception [132] of reality. Thus, by a wiſe appointment of nature, intuitive belief is ſubjected to rational diſcuſſion: when confirmed by reaſon, it turns more vigorous and authoritative: when contra⯑dicted by reaſon, it diſappears among ſenſible people. In ſome inſtances, it is too headſtrong for reaſon; as in the caſe of hobgoblins and ap⯑paritions, which paſs current among the vulgar in ſpite of reaſon.
We proceed to the other kind of belief, viz. that which is founded on reaſoning, to which, when intuition fails us, we muſt have recourſe for aſcertaining certain facts. Thus, from known effects, we infer the exiſtence of unknown cauſes. That an effect muſt have a cauſe, is an intuitive propoſition; but to aſcertain what par⯑ticular thing is the cauſe, requires commonly a proceſs of reaſoning. This is one of the means by which the Deity, the primary cauſe, is made known to us, as mentioned above. Reaſon, in tracing cauſes from known effects, produces dif⯑ferent degrees of conviction. It ſometimes pro⯑duces certainty, as in proving the exiſtence of the Deity; which on that account is handled above, under the head of knowledge. For the moſt part it produces belief only, which, according to the ſtrength of the reaſoning, ſometimes approaches to certainty, and ſometimes is ſo weak as barely to turn the ſcale on the ſide of probability. Take the following examples of different degrees of belief founded on probable reaſoning. When Inigo Jones flouriſhed, and was the only architect of note in England, let it be ſuppoſed that his model of the Palace of Whitehall had been pre⯑ſented to a ſtranger, without mentioning the author. The ſtranger, in the firſt place, would have been intuitively certain, that this was the work of ſome being intelligent and ſkilful. Se⯑condly, [133] He would have had a conviction ap⯑proaching to certainty, that the operator was a man. And, thirdly, He would have had a con⯑viction that the man was Inigo Jones; but leſs firm than the former. Let us next ſuppoſe another Engliſh architect little inferior in reputa⯑tion to Jones: the ſtranger would ſtill have pro⯑nounced in favour of the latter; but his belief would have been in the loweſt degree.
When we inveſtigate the cauſes of certain ef⯑fects, the reaſoning is often founded upon the known nature of man. In the high country, for example, between Edinburgh and Glaſgow, the people lay their coals at the end of their houſes, without any fence to ſecure them from theft: whence it is rationally inferred, that coals are there in plenty. In the weſt of Scotland, the corn-ſtacks are covered with great care and nicety: whence it is inferred, that the climate is rainy. Placentia is the capital town of Biſcay; and the only town in Newfoundland bears the ſame name; from which circumſtance it is con⯑jectured, that the Biſcayners were the firſt Europeans who made a ſettlement in that iſland.
Analogical reaſoning, founded upon the unifor⯑mity of nature, is frequently employed in the in⯑veſtigation of facts; and we infer, that facts of which we are uncertain, muſt reſemble thoſe of the ſame kind that are known. The bulk of the reaſonings in natural philoſophy are of that kind. Take the following examples. We learn from experience, that proceeding from the humbleſt vegetable to man, there are numberleſs claſſes of beings riſing one above another, by differences ſcarce perceptible, and leaving no where a ſingle gap or interval: and from conviction of the uni⯑formity of nature, we infer, that the line is not [134] broken off here, but is carried on in the other worlds, till it end in the Deity. I proceed to another example. Every man is conſcious of a ſelf-motive power in himſelf; and from the uni⯑formity of nature, we infer the ſame power in every one of our own ſpecies. The argument here from analogy carries great weight, becauſe we entertain no doubt of the uniformity of nature with reſpect to beings of our own kind. We apply the ſame argument to other animals, though their reſemblance to man appears not ſo certain, as that of one man to another. But why not alſo apply the ſame argument to infer a ſelf-motive power in matter? When we ſee mat⯑ter in motion without an external mover, we naturally infer, that, like us, it moves itſelf. Another example is borrowed from Maupertuis. ‘"As there is no known ſpace of the earth co⯑vered with water ſo large as the Terra Auſtra⯑lis incognita, we may reaſonably infer, that ſo great a part of the earth is not altogether ſea, but that there muſt be ſome proportion of land."’ The uniformity of nature with reſpect to the intermixture of ſea and land, is an argu⯑ment that affords but a very ſlender degree of conviction. The following argument of the ſame kind, though it cannot be much relied on, ſeems however better founded. ‘"The inhabitants of the northern hemiſphere, have, in arts and ſciences, excelled ſuch of the ſouthern as we have any knowledge of: and therefore, if in⯑habitants be found in the Terra Auſtralis incognita, we ought not to expect among them many arts, nor much cultivation."’
After a fatiguing inveſtigation of numberleſs particulars which divide and ſcatter the thought, it may not be unpleaſant to bring all under one view by a ſuccinct recapitulation.
[135] We have two means for diſcovering truth, and acquiring knowledge, viz. intuition and reaſoning. By intuition we diſcover ſubjects, and their at⯑tributes, paſſions, internal action, and in ſhort every thing that is matter of fact. By intuition we alſo diſcover ſeveral relations. There are ſome facts, and many relations, that cannot be diſco⯑vered by a ſingle act of intuition, but require ſeveral ſuch acts linked together in a chain of reaſoning.
Knowledge acquired by intuition, includes for the moſt part certainty: in ſome inſtances it includes probability only. Knowledge acquired by reaſoning, frequently includes certainty; but more frequently includes probability only.
Probable knowledge, whether founded on in⯑tuition or on reaſoning, is termed opinion when it concerns relations; and is termed belief when it concerns facts. When knowledge includes cer⯑tainty, it retains its proper name.
Reaſoning that produces certainty, is termed demonſtrative; and is termed probable, when it only produces probability.
Demonſtrative reaſoning is of two kinds. The firſt is, where the concluſion is derived from the nature and inherent properties of the ſubject: mathematical reaſoning is of that kind; and per⯑haps the only inſtance. The ſecond is, where the concluſion is derived from ſome propoſition, of which we are certain by intuition.
Probable reaſoning is endleſs in its varieties; and affords different degrees of conviction, de⯑pending on the nature of the ſubject upon which it is employed.
SECT. II.
PROGRESS OF REASON.
[136]A PROGRESS from infancy to maturity in the mind of man, ſimilar to that in his body, has been often mentioned. The external ſenſes, being early neceſſary for ſelf-preſervation, arrive quickly at maturity. The internal ſenſes are of a ſlower growth, as well as every other mental power: their maturity would be of little or no uſe while the body is weak, and unfit for action. Reaſoning, as obſerved in the firſt ſec⯑tion, requires two mental powers, viz. the pow⯑er of invention, and that of perceiving relations. By the former power are diſcovered intermediate propoſitions, equally related to the fundamental propoſition and to the concluſion; and that rela⯑tion is verified by the latter power. Both pow⯑ers are neceſſary to the perſon who frames an ar⯑gument, or a chain of reaſoning: the latter only to the perſon who judges of it. Savages are mi⯑ſerably deficient in both. With reſpect to the former, a ſavage may have a pregnant talent for [137] invention; but it will ſtand him in little ſtead without a ſtock of ideas enabling him to ſelect what may anſwer the purpoſe; and what oppor⯑tunity has a ſavage to acquire ſuch a ſtock? With reſpect to the latter, he knows little of relations: and how ſhould he know, when both ſtudy and practice are neceſſary for diſtinguiſhing between relations, and for preventing the being impoſed on by the ſhadow of a relation inſtead of the ſub⯑ſtance? The underſtanding, at the ſame time, among the illiterate, is obſequious to paſſion and prepoſſeſſion; and among them the imagina⯑tion acts without control, forming concluſions often no better than mere dreams. In ſhort, conſidering the many cauſes that miſlead from juſt reaſoning, in days eſpecially of ignorance, the erroneous and abſurd opinions that have pre⯑vailed in the world, and that continue in ſome meaſure to prevail, are far from being ſurpriſing. Were reaſon our only guide in the conduct of life, we ſhould have cauſe to complain; but our Maker has provided us with the moral ſenſe, a guide little ſubject to error in matters of impor⯑tance. In the ſciences, reaſon is eſſential; but in the conduct of life, which is our chief concern, reaſon may be an uſeful aſſiſtant; but to be our director is not its province.
The national progreſs of reaſon has been ſlow⯑er in Europe, than that of any other art. Statu⯑ary, painting, architecture, and other fine arts, approach nearer perfection, as well as morality and natural hiſtory. Manners, it is true, and every art that appears externally, may in part be acquired by imitation and example: in reaſoning there is nothing external to be laid hold of. But there is beſide a particular cauſe that regards Eu⯑rope, which is the blind deference that for many [138] ages was paid to Ariſtotle; who has kept the rea⯑ſoning faculty in chains more than two thouſand years. In his logics, the plain and ſimple mode of reaſoning is rejected, that which Nature dic⯑tates; and in its ſtead is introduced an artificial mode, ſhowy but unſubſtantial: it is of no uſe in diſcovering truth, but nobly contrived for wrang⯑ling and diſputation. Conſidering that reaſon for ſo many ages has been locked up in the enchanted caſtle of ſyllogiſm, where empty phantoms paſs for realities, the ſlow progreſs of reaſon toward maturity is far from being ſurpriſing. The ta⯑king of Conſtantinople, ann. 1453, opened a new ſcene, which in time relieved the world from the uſurpation of Ariſtotle, and reſtored reaſon to her privileges. All the knowledge of Europe was centered in Conſtantinople; and the learned men of that city, abhorring the Turks and their government, took refuge in Italy. The Greek language was introduced among the weſtern nati⯑ons of Europe; and the ſtudy of Greek and Roman claſſics became faſhionable. Men, hav⯑ing acquired new ideas, began to think for themſelves: they exerted their native faculty of reaſon: the futility of Ariſtotle's logics became apparent to the penetrating; and is now appa⯑rent to all. Yet ſo late as the year 1621, ſeve⯑ral perſons were baniſhed from Paris for contra⯑dicting that philoſopher, about matter and form, and about the number of the elements. And ſhortly after, the parliament of Paris prohibited, under pain of death, any thing to be thought contrary to the doctrines of Ariſtotle. Julius II. and Leo X. Roman Pontiffs, contributed zea⯑louſly to the reformation of letters; but they did not foreſee that they were alſo contributing to the reformation of religion, and of every ſcience that depends on reaſoning. Tho' the fetters of ſyl⯑logiſm [139] have many years ago been ſhaken off, yet, like a limb long kept from motion, the reaſoning faculty has ſcarcely to this day attained its free and natural exerciſe. Mathematics is the only ſcience that never has been cramped by ſyllogiſm, and we find reaſoning there in great perfection at an early period. The very ſlow progreſs of rea⯑ſoning in other matters, will appear from the fol⯑lowing induction.
To exemplify erroneous and abſurd reaſonings of every ſort, would be endleſs. The reader, I preſume, will be ſatisfied with a few inſtances; and I ſhall endeavour to ſelect what are amuſing. For the ſake of order, I divide them into three heads. Firſt, Inſtances ſhowing the imbecility of human reaſon during its nonage. Second, Er⯑roneous reaſoning occaſioned by natural biaſſes. Third, Erroneous reaſoning occaſioned by acqui⯑red biaſſes. With reſpect to the firſt, inſtances are endleſs of reaſonings founded on erroneous premiſſes. It was an Epicurean doctrine, That the gods have all of them a human figure; moved by the following argument, that no being of any other figure has the uſe of reaſon. Plato, taking for granted the following erroneous propoſition, That every being which moves itſelf, muſt have a ſoul, concludes that the world muſt have a ſoul, becauſe it moves itſelfa. Ariſtotle taking it for granted, without the leaſt evidence, and con⯑trary to truth, that all heavy bodies tend to the centre of the univerſe, proves the earth to be the centre of the univerſe by the following argument. ‘"Heavy bodies naturally tend to the centre of the univerſe; we know by experience that heavy bodies tend to the centre of the earth: therefore the centre of the earth is the centre [140] of the univerſe."’ Appion ridicules the Jews for adhering ſo literally to the precept of reſting on their ſabbath, as to ſuffer Jeruſalem to be ta⯑ken that day by Ptolomy ſon of Lagus. Mark the anſwer of Joſephus: ‘"Whoever paſſes a ſo⯑ber judgment on this matter, will find our practice agreeable to honour and virtue; for what can be more honourable and virtuous, than to poſtpone our country, and even life it⯑ſelf, to the ſervice of God, and of his holy re⯑ligion?"’ A ſtrange idea of religion, to put it in direct oppoſition to every moral principle! A ſuperſtitious and abſurd doctrine, That God will interpoſe by a miracle, to declare what is right in every matter of controverſy, has occaſioned much erroneous reaſoning and abſurd practice. The practice of determining controverſies by ſingle combat, commenced about the ſeventh century, when religion had degenerated into ſuperſtition, and courage was eſteemed the only moral virtue. The parliament of Paris, in the reign of Charles VI. appointed a ſingle combat between two gen⯑tlemen, in order to have the judgment of God, whether the one had committed a rape on the other's wife. In 1454, John Picard being ac⯑cuſed by his ſon-in-law for too great familiarity with his wife, a duel between them was appoint⯑ed by the ſame parliament. Voltaire juſtly ob⯑ſerves, that the parliament decreed a parricide to be committed, in order to try an accuſation of inceſt, which poſſibly was not committed. The trials by water and by fire, reſt on the ſame er⯑roneous foundation. In the former, if the per⯑ſon accuſed ſunk to the bottom, it was a judg⯑ment pronounced by God, that he was innocent: if he kept above, it was a judgment that he was [141] guilty. Fleurya remarks, that if ever the per⯑ſon accuſed was found guilty, it was his own fault. In Sicily, a woman accuſed of adultery, was compelled to ſwear to her innocence: the oath, taken down in writing, was laid on water; and if it did not ſink, the woman was innocent. We find the ſame practice in Japan, and in Ma⯑labar. One of the articles inſiſted on by the re⯑formers in Scotland, was, That public prayers be made and the ſacraments adminiſtered in the vul⯑gar tongue. The anſwer of a provincial council was in the following words: ‘"That to conceive public prayers, or adminiſter the ſacraments, in any language but Latin, is contrary to the traditions and practice of the Catholic church for many ages paſt; and that the demand can⯑not be granted, without impiety to God, and diſobedience to the church."’ Here it is ta⯑ken for granted, that the practice of the church is always right: which is building an argument on a very rotten foundation. The Caribbeans ab⯑ſtain from ſwines fleſh; taking it erroneouſly for granted, that ſuch food would make them have ſmall eyes, held by them a great deformity. They alſo abſtain from eating turtle; which they think would infect them with the lazineſs and ſtupidity of that animal. Upon the ſame errone⯑ous notion, the Braſilians abſtain from the fleſh of ducks, and of every creature that moves ſlowly.
A talent for writing ſeems in Germany to be eſtimated by weight, as beauty is ſaid to be in Holland. Cocceius, for writing three weighty folio volumes on law, has obtained among his countrymen the epithet of Great. This author, handling the rules of ſucceſſion in land-eſtates, has with moſt profound erudition founded all of [142] them upon a very ſimple propoſition, viz. That in a competition, that deſcendent is intitled to be preferred who has the greateſt quantity of the predeceſſor's blood in his veins. Quaeritur, has a man any of his predeceſſor's blood in his veins, otherwiſe than metaphorically? Strange! to build an argument in law upon a pure metaphor.
Next of reaſonings where the concluſion fol⯑lows not from the premiſſes, or fundamental pro⯑poſition. Plato endeavours to prove, that the world is endowed with wiſdom, by the following argument. ‘"The world is greater than any of its parts: therefore it is endowed with wiſ⯑dom; for otherwiſe a man who is endowed with wiſdom would be greater than the worlda."’ The concluſion here does not follow; for tho' a man is endowed with wiſdom it follows not, that he is greater than the world in point of ſize. Zeno endeavours to prove, that the world has the uſe of reaſon, by an argument of the ſame kind. Pope Gregory, writing in favour of the four councils, viz. Nice, Conſtantinople, Ephe⯑ſus, and Calcedon, reaſons thus: ‘"That as there are four evangeliſts, there ought alſo to be four councils."’ What would he have ſaid, if he had lived 100 years later, when there were many more than four? In adminiſtering the ſa⯑crament of the Lord's ſupper, it was ordered, that the hoſt ſhould be covered with a clean linen cloth; becauſe, ſays the Canon law, the body of our Lord Jeſus Chriſt was buried in a clean linen cloth. Joſephus, in his anſwer to Appion, urges the following argument for the temple of Jeruſa⯑lem: ‘"As there is but one God, and one world, it holds in analogy, that there ſhould be but one temple."’ At that rate, there [143] ſhould be but one worſhipper. And why ſhould that one temple be at Jeruſalem rather than at Rome or at Pekin? The Syrians and Greeks did not for a long time eat fiſh. Two reaſons are aſſigned: one is, That fiſh is not ſacrificed to the gods; the other, That being immerſed in the ſea, they look not up to heavena. The firſt would afford a more plauſible argument for ea⯑ting fiſh. And if the other have any weight, it would be an argument for ſacrificing men, and neither fiſh nor cattle. In juſtification of the Salic law, which prohibits female ſucceſſion, it was long held a concluſive argument, That in the ſcripture the lilies are ſaid neither to work nor to ſpin. Vieira, termed by his countrymen the Luſitanian Cicero, publiſhed ſermons, one of which begins thus, ‘"Were the Supreme Being to ſhow himſelf viſibly, he would chuſe the circle rather than the triangle, the ſquare, the pentagon, the duodecagon, or any other fi⯑gure."’ But why appear in any of theſe fi⯑gures? And if he were obliged to appear in ſo mean a ſhape, a globe is undoubtedly more beau⯑tiful than a circle. Peter Hantz of Horn, who lived in the laſt century, imagined that Noah's ark is the true conſtruction of a ſhip; ‘"which,"’ ſaid he, ‘"is the workmanſhip of God, and therefore perfect;"’ as if a veſſel made merely for floating on the water, were the beſt alſo for ſailing. Sixty or ſeventy years ago, the faſhion prevailed, in imitation of birds, to ſwallow ſmall ſtones for the ſake of digeſtion; as if what is proper for birds, were equally proper for men. The Spaniards, who laid waſte a great part of the Weſt Indies, endeavoured to excuſe their cruelties, by maintaining, that the natives were [144] not men, but a ſpecies of the Ouran Outang; for no better reaſon, than that they were of a copper colour, ſpoke an unknown language, and had no beard. The Pope iſſued a bull, decla⯑ring, that it pleaſed him and the Holy Ghoſt to acknowledge the Americans to be of the human race. This bull was not received cordially. In the council of Lima, ann. 1583, it was violent⯑ly diſputed, whether the Americans had ſo much underſtanding as to be admitted to the ſacraments of the church. In 1440, the Portugueſe ſoli⯑cited the Pope's permiſſion to double the Cape of Good hope, and to reduce to perpetual ſervitude the negroes, becauſe they had the colour of the damned, and never went to church. In the Fre⯑derician Code, a propoſition is laid down, That by the law of nature no man can make a teſta⯑ment. And in ſupport of that propoſition the fol⯑lowing argument is urged, which is ſaid to be a demonſtration: ‘"No deed can be a teſtament while a man is alive, becauſe it is not neceſſa⯑rily his ultima voluntas; and no man can make a teſtament after his death."’ Both premiſſes are true, but the negative concluſion does not fol⯑low. It is true a man's deed is not his ultima vo⯑luntas, while he is alive: but does it not become his ultima voluntas, when he dies without alte⯑ring the deed?
Many reaſonings have paſſed current in the world as good coin, where premiſſes and con⯑cluſion are both of them falſe. Ariſtotle, who wrote a book upon mechanics, was much puz⯑zled about the equilibrium of a balance, when unequal weights are hung upon it at different diſ⯑tances from the centre. Having obſerved, that the arms of the balance deſcribe portions of a cir⯑cle, he accounted for the equilibrium by a nota⯑ble argument: ‘"All the properties of the circle [145] are wonderful: the equilibrium of the two weights that deſcribe portions of a circle is wonderful. Ergo, the equilibrium muſt be one of the properties of the circle."’ What are we to think of Ariſtotle's logics, when we find him capable of ſuch childiſh reaſoning? And yet that work has been the admiration of all the world for centuries upon centuries. Nay, that fooliſh argument has been eſpouſed and commen⯑ted upon by his diſciples, for the ſame length of time. To proceed to another inſtance: Marri⯑age within the fourth degree of conſanguinity, as well as of affinity, is prohibited by the Lateran council; and the reaſon given is, That the body being made up of the four elements, has four dif⯑ferent humours in it*. The Roman Catholics began with beheading heretics, hanging them, or ſtoning them to death. But ſuch puniſhments were diſcovered to be too ſlight, in matters of faith. It was demonſtrated, that heretics ought to be burnt in a ſlow fire: it was taken for grant⯑ed, that God puniſhes them in the other world with a ſlow fire; and hence it was inferred, ‘"That as every prince and every magiſtrate is the image of God in this world, they ought to follow his example."’ Here is a double error in reaſoning: firſt the taking for granted the fun⯑damental [146] propoſition, which is ſurely not ſelf-evi⯑dent; and next the drawing a concluſion from it without any connection.
It once was a general opinion among thoſe who dwelt near the ſea, that people never die but du⯑ring the ebb of the tide. And there were not wanting plauſible reaſons. The ſea, in flowing, carries with it vivifying particles that recruit the ſick. The ſea is ſalt, and ſalt preſerves from rottenneſs. When the ſea ſinks in ebbing, every thing ſinks with it: nature languiſhes: the ſick are not vivified: they die.
What ſhall be ſaid of a reaſoning where the concluſion is a flat contradiction to the premiſſes? If a man ſhooting at a wild pigeon happen unfor⯑tunately to kill his neighbour, it is in the Engliſh law excuſable homicide; becauſe the ſhooting an animal that is no man's property is a lawful act. If the aim be at a tame fowl for amuſement, which is a treſpaſs on the property of another, the death of the man will be manſlaughter. If the tame fowl be ſhot at in order to be ſtolen, it will be murder, by reaſon of the felonious intent. From this laſt the following conſequence is drawn, that if a man, endeavouring to kill another, miſſes his blow, and happeneth to kill himſelf, he is in judgment of law guilty of wilful and delibe⯑rate ſelf-murder a. Strange reaſoning! to con⯑ſtrue an act to be wilful and deliberate ſelf-murder, contrary to the very thing that is ſup⯑poſed.
A plentiful ſource of inconcluſive reaſoning which prevails greatly during the infancy of the rational faculty, is the making of no proper diſ⯑tinction between ſtrong and weak relations. Mi⯑nutius [147] Felix, in his apology for the Chriſtians, en⯑deavours to prove the unity of the Deity from a moſt diſtant analogy or relation, viz. That there is but one king of the bees, and that more than one chief magiſtrate would breed confuſion. It is a proſtitution of reaſon to offer ſuch an argument for the unity of the Deity. But any argument paſſes current, in ſupport of a propoſition that we know beforehand to be true. Plutarch ſays, ‘"that it ſeemed to have happened by the pecu⯑liar direction of the gods, that Numa was born on the 21ſt of April, the very day in which Rome was founded by Romulus;"’ a ve⯑ry childiſh inference from a mere accident. Sup⯑poſing Italy to have been tolerably populous, as undoubtedly it was at that period, the 21ſt of April, or any day of April, might have given birth to thouſands. In many countries, the ſur⯑geons and barbers are claſſed together, as mem⯑bers of the ſame trade, from a very ſlight relati⯑on, that both of them operate upon the human body. The Jews enjoyed the reputation for cen⯑turies, of being ſkilful phyſicians. Francis I. of France, having long laboured under a diſeaſe that eluded the art of his own phyſicians, applied to the Emperor Charles V. for a Jewiſh phyſician from Spain. Finding that the perſon ſent had been converted to Chriſtianity, the King refuſed to employ him; as if a Jew were to loſe his ſkill upon being converted to Chriſtianity. Why did not the King order one of his own phyſicians to be converted to Judaiſm? The following childiſh argument is built upon an extreme ſlight relation, that between our Saviour, and the wooden croſs he ſuffered on. ‘"Believe me,"’ ſays Julius Fir⯑micus, ‘"that the devil omits nothing to deſtroy miſerable mortals; converting himſelf into every different form, and employing every ſort [148] of artifice. He appoints wood to be uſed in ſa⯑crificing to him, knowing that our Saviour, fix⯑ed to the croſs, would beſtow immortality upon all his followers. A pine-tree is cut down, and uſed in ſacrificing to the mother of the gods. A wooden image of Oſiris is buried in ſacrificing to Iſis. A wooden image of Proſerpina is bemoaned for forty nights, and then thrown into the flames. Deluded mortals, theſe flames can do you no ſervice. On the contrary, the fire that is deſtined for your puniſhment rages without end. Learn from me to know that divine wood which will ſet you free. A wooden ark ſaved the human race from the univerſal deluge. Abraham put wood upon the ſhoulders of his ſon Iſaac. The wooden rod ſtretched out by Aaron brought the chil⯑dren of Iſrael out of the land of Egypt. Wood ſweetened the bitter waters of Marah, and comforted the children of Iſrael after wandering three days without water. A wooden rod ſtruck water out of the rock. The rod of God in the hand of Moſes overcame Amalek. The patriarch dreamed, that he ſaw angels de⯑ſcending and aſcending upon a wooden ladder: and the law of God was incloſed in a wooden ark. Theſe things were exhibited, that, as if it were by certain ſteps, we might aſcend to the wood of the croſs, which is our ſalvation. The wood of the croſs ſuſtains the heavenly ma⯑chine, ſupports the foundations of the earth, and leads men to eternal life. The wood of the devil burns and periſhes, and its aſhes car⯑ries down ſinners to the loweſt pit of hell."’ The very ſlighteſt relations make an impreſſion on a weak underſtanding. It was a fancy of Antoninus Geta, in ordering his table, to have ſervices compoſed of diſhes beginning with the [149] ſame letter; ſuch as lamb and lobſter; broth, beef, blood-pudding; pork, plumb-cake, pige⯑ons, potatoes. The name of John, King of Scot⯑land, was changed into Robert, for no better reaſon, than that the Johns of France and of England had been unfortunate.
In reaſoning, inſtances are not rare, or miſ⯑taking the cauſe for the effect, and the effect for the cauſe. When a ſtone is thrown from the hand, the continuance of its motion in the air, was once univerſally accounted for as follows: ‘"That the air follows the ſtone at the heels, and puſhes it on."’ The effect here is miſtaken for the cauſe: the air indeed follows the ſtone at the heels; but it only fills the vacuity made by the ſtone, and does not puſh it on. It has been ſlyly urged againſt the art of phyſic, that phyſi⯑cians are rare among temperate people, ſuch as have no wants but thoſe of nature; and that where phyſicians abound, diſeaſes abound. This is miſtaking the cauſe for the effect, and the effect for the cauſe: people in health have no occaſion for a phyſician; but indolence and luxury beget diſeaſes, and diſeaſes beget phyſici⯑ans.
During the nonage of reaſon, men are ſatisfied with words merely, inſtead of an argument. A ſea-proſpect bounded is charming; but we ſoon tire of an unbounded proſpect. It would not give ſatisfaction to ſay, that it is too exten⯑ſive; for why ſhould not a proſpect be reliſhed, however extenſive? But employ a foreign term and ſay, that it is trop vaſte, we enquire no far⯑ther: a term that is not familiar, makes an im⯑preſſion, and captivates weak reaſon. This ob⯑ſervation accounts for a mode of writing formerly in common uſe, that of ſtuffing our language with Latin words and phraſes. Theſe are now [150] laid aſide as uſeleſs; becauſe a proper emphaſis in reading, makes an impreſſion deeper than any foreign term can do.
There is one proof of the imbecility of hu⯑man reaſon in dark times, which would ſcarce be believed, were not the fact ſupported by incon⯑teſtible evidence. Inſtead of explaining any natural appearance by ſearching for a cauſe, it has been common to account for it by inventing a fable, which gave ſatisfaction without enquiring farther. For example, inſtead of giving the true cauſe of the ſucceſſion of day and night, the ſa⯑cred book of the Scandinavians, termed Edda, accounts for that ſucceſſion by a tale: ‘"The giant Nor had a daughter named Night, of a dark complexion. She was wedded to Dag⯑lingar, of the family of the gods. They had a male child, which they named Day, beau⯑tiful and ſhining like all of his father's family. The univerſal father took Night and Day, placed them in heaven, and gave them two horſes and two cars, that they might travel round the world, the one after the other. Night goes firſt upon her horſe named Rimfaxe, [Froſty Mane], who moiſtens the earth with the foam that drops from his bit, which is the dew. The horſe belonging to Day is named Skinfaxe, [Shining Mane], who by his radiant mane illuminates the air and the earth."’ It is obſerved by the tranſlator of the Edda, that this way of accounting for things is well ſuited to the turn of the human mind, which is endowed with curioſity that is extremely keen, but eaſily ſatiſ⯑fied, often with words inſtead of ideas. Zo⯑roaſter, by a ſimilar fable, accounts for the growth of evil in this world. He invents a good and an evil principle named Oromazes and Arimanes, who are in continual conflict for preference. At [151] the laſt day, Oromazes will be reunited to the ſupreme God, from whom he iſſued. Arimanes will be ſubdued, darkneſs deſtroyed; and the world, purified by an univerſal conflagration, will become a luminous and ſhining abode, from which evil will be excluded. I return to the Edda, which is ſtored with fables of this kind. The higheſt notion ſavages can form of the gods, is that of men endowed with extraordinary power and knowledge. The only puzzling circumſtance is, how they differ ſo much from man as to be immortal. The Edda accounts for this by the fol⯑lowing fable. ‘"The gods prevented the effect of old age and decay, by continuing to eat cer⯑tain apples, truſted to the care of Iduna. Loke, the Momus of the Scandinavians, craf⯑tily conveyed away Iduna, and concealed her in a wood, under the cuſtody of a giant. The gods beginning to wax old and gray, detected the author of the theft; and, by terrible me⯑naces, compelled him to employ his utmoſt cunning, for regaining Iduna and her apples, in which he was ſucceſsful."’ The origin of poetry is thus accounted for in the ſame work: ‘"The gods formed Cuaſer, who traverſed the earth, teaching wiſdom to men. He was treacherouſly ſlain by two dwarfs, who, mix⯑ing honey with his blood, compoſed a liquor that renders all who drink of it poets. Theſe dwarfs having incurred the reſentment of a cer⯑tain giant, were expoſed by him upon a rock, ſurrounded on all ſides with the ſea. They gave for their ranſom the ſaid liquor, which the giant delivered to his daughter Gunloda. The precious potion was eagerly ſought for by the gods; but how were they to come at it? Odin, in the ſhape of a worm crept through a crevice into the cavern where the liquor was [152] concealed. Then reſuming his natural ſhape, and obtaining Gunloda's conſent to take three draughts, he ſucked up the whole; and, tranſ⯑forming himſelf into an eagle, flew away to Aſgard. The giant, who was a magician, flew with all ſpeed after Odin, and came up with him near the gate of Aſgard. The gods iſſued out of their palaces to aſſiſt their ma⯑ſter; and preſented to him all the pitchers they could lay hands on, which he inſtantly filled with the precious liquor. But in the hurry of diſcharging his load, Odin poured only part of the liquor through his beak, the reſt being emitted through a leſs pure vent. The former is beſtowed by the gods upon good poets, to inſpire them with divine enthuſiaſm. The latter, which is in much greater plenty, is beſtowed liberally on all who apply for it; by which means the world is peſtered with an endleſs quantity of wretched verſes."’ Igno⯑rance is equally credulous in all ages. Albert, ſurnamed the Great, flouriſhed in the thirteenth century, and was a man of real knowledge. Du⯑ring the courſe of his education he was remarkably dull; and ſome years before he died became a ſort of changeling. That ſingularity produced the following hiſtory: That the only Virgin, ap⯑pearing to him, demanded, whether he would excel in philoſophy or in theology; that upon his chuſing the former, ſhe promiſed, that he ſhould become an incomparable philoſopher; but added, that to puniſh him for not prefer⯑ring theology, he ſhould become ſtupid again as at firſt.
Upon a ſlight view, it may appear unaccounta⯑ble, that even the groſſeſt ſavages ſhould take a childiſh tale for a ſolid reaſon. But nature aids the deception: where things are related in a lively [153] manner, and every circumſtance appears as paſ⯑ſing in our ſight, we take all for granted as truea. Can an ignorant ruſtic doubt of inſpiration, when he ſees as it were the poet ſipping the pure celeſtial liquor? And how can that poet fail to produce bad verſes, who feeds on the excrements that drop from the fundament even of a deity?
In accounting for natural appearances, even good writers have betrayed a weakneſs in reaſon⯑ing, little inferior to that above mentioned. They do not indeed put off their diſciples with a tale; but they put them off with a mere ſuppoſi⯑tion, not more real than the tale. Deſcartes aſcribes the motion of the planets to a vortex of ether whirling round and round. He thought not of enquiring whether there really be ſuch a vor⯑tex, nor what makes it move. M. Buffon forms the earth out of a ſplinter of the ſun, ſtruck off by a comet. May not one be permitted humbly to enquire of that eminent philoſopher, what form⯑ed the comet? This paſſes for ſolid reaſoning; and yet we laugh at the poor Indian, who ſup⯑ports the earth from falling by an elephant, and the elephant by a tortoiſe.
It is ſtill more ridiculous to reaſon upon what is acknowledged to be a fiction, as if it were real. Such are the fictions admitted in the Roman law. A Roman taken captive in war, loſt his privilege of being a Roman citizen; for freedom was held eſſential to that privilege. But what if he made his eſcape, after perhaps an hour's detention? The hardſhip in that caſe ought to have ſuggeſted an alteration of the law, which was, to ſuſpend the privilege no longer than the captivity ſubſiſt⯑ed. But the ancient Romans were not ſo ingeni⯑ous. [154] They remedied the hardſhip by a fiction, that the man never had been a captive. The Fre⯑derician code baniſhes from the law of Pruſſia an endleſs number of fictions that are found in the Roman law (Preface, ſect. 28.). Yet after⯑ward, treating of perſonal rights, it is laid down as a rule, That a child in the womb is feigned or ſuppoſed to be born when the fiction is for its advantage (part 1. b. 1. tit. 4. ſect. 4.). To a weak reaſoner a fiction is a happy contrivance for reſolving intricate queſtions. Such is the conſti⯑tution of England, that the Engliſh law-courts are merely territorial; and that no fact happening abroad comes under their cogniſance. An En⯑gliſhman, after murdering his fellow-traveller in France, returns to his native country. What is to be done? for guilt ought not to paſs unpuniſh⯑ed. The crime is feigned to have been commit⯑ted in England.
Ancient hiſtories are full of incredible facts that paſſed current during the infancy of reaſon, which at preſent would be rejected with contempt. Every man who is converſant in the hiſtory of ancient nations, can recall inſtances without end. Does any one believe at preſent, tho' gravely re⯑ported by hiſtorians, that in old Rome there was a law, for cutting into pieces the body of a bank⯑rupt, and diſtributing the parts among his credi⯑tors? The ſtory of Porſenna and Scevola is high⯑ly romantic; and the Story of Vampires in Hun⯑gary, ſhamefully abſurd. There is no reaſon to believe, that there ever was ſuch a ſtate as that of the Amazons; and the ſtory of Thaleſtris and Alexander the Great is undoubtedly a fiction. Scotch hiſtorians deſcribe gravely and circumſtan⯑tially the battle of Luncarty, as if they had been eye-witneſſes. A country-man and his two ſons, it is ſaid, were ploughing in an adjacent field, [155] during the heat of the action. Enraged at their countrymen for turning their backs, they broke the plough in pieces; and each laying hold of a part, ruſhed into the midſt of the battle, and ob⯑tained a complete victory over the Danes. This ſtory has every mark of fiction: A man follow⯑ing unconcernedly his ordinary occupation of ploughing, in ſight of a battle, on which depend⯑ed his wife and children, his goods, and perhaps his own life. More, Three men, without rank of figure, with only a ſtick in the hand of each, ſtemming the tide of victory, and turning the fate of battle. I mention not that a plough was unknown in Scotland for a century or two after that battle; for that circumſtance could not create a doubt in the hiſtorian, if he was ignorant of it.
Reaſon, with reſpect to its progreſs, is ſingu⯑lar. Morals, manners, and every thing that ap⯑pears externally, may in part be acquired by imi⯑tation and example, which have not the ſlighteſt influence upon the reaſoning faculty. The only means for advancing that faculty to maturity, are indefatigable ſtudy and practice; and even theſe will not carry a man one ſtep beyond the ſubjects he is converſant about: examples are not rare of men extremely expert in one ſcience, and groſſ⯑ly deficient in others. Many able mathematicians are novices in politics, and even in the common arts of life: ſtudy and practice have ripened them in every relation of equality, while they re⯑main ignorant, like the vulgar, about other rela⯑tions. A man in like manner, who has beſtowed much time and thought in political matters, may be a child as to other branches of know⯑ledge*.
[156] I proceed to the ſecond article, containing er⯑roneous reaſoning occaſioned by natural biaſſes. The firſt bias I ſhall mention has an extenſive in⯑fluence. What is ſeen, makes a deeper impreſ⯑ſion, than what is heard by report, or diſcovered by reflection. Hence it is, that in judging of right and wrong, the external act only draws the attention of the ignorant and illiterate, who can⯑not penetrate into will or intention; and hence it is, that in religion great weight is laid upon forms and ceremonies, without much regarding their purpoſe. Theſe particulars come in afterward, in the progreſs of morality and religion. What belongs to the preſent ſketch is to obſerve, that in judging of covenants, laws, vows, and other acts that are completed by words, the whole weight in days of ignorance is laid upon the ex⯑ternal expreſſion, with no regard to the meaning of the ſpeaker or writer. The bleſſing beſtowed by Iſaac upon his ſon Jacob, miſtaking him for Eſau, is an illuſtrious inſtance. Not only was the bleſſing intended for Eſau, but Jacob, by de⯑ceiving his father, had rendered himſelf unwor⯑thy of ita; yet Iſaae had pronounced the ſounds, and it was not in his power to unſay [157] them: Neſcit vox emiſſa reverti. Joſhua, groſsly impoſed on by the Gibeonites denying that they were Canaanites, made a covenant with them; and yet, tho' he found them to be Cana⯑anites, he held himſelf to be bound. Led by the ſame bias, people think it ſufficient to fulfil the words of a vow, however ſhort of intention. The Duke of Lancaſter, vexed at the obſtinate re⯑ſiſtance of Rennes, a town in Britany, vowed in wrath not to raiſe the ſiege till he had planted the Engliſh colours upon one of the gates. This proved a raſh vow. He found it neceſſary to raiſe the ſiege, but his vow ſtood in the way. The governor relieved him from his ſcruple, per⯑mitting him to plant his colours upon one of the gates; and he was ſatisfied that his vow was ful⯑filled. The following is an example of an ab⯑ſurd concluſion deduced from a precept taken li⯑terally, againſt common ſenſe. We are ordered by the Apoſtle, to pray always; from which Je⯑rom, one of the fathers, argues thus: ‘"Conju⯑gal enjoyment is inconſiſtent with praying; ergo, conjugal enjoyment is a ſin."’ By the ſame argument it may be proved, that eating and drinking are ſins; and that ſleeping is a great ſin, being a great interruption to praying. With re⯑ſpect to another text, viz. ‘"That a biſhop muſt be blameleſs, the huſband of one wife,"’ taken literally, a very different concluſion is drawn in Abyſſinia, viz. That no man can be or⯑dained a preſbyter till he be married. Prohibiti⯑ons have been interpreted in the ſame ſhallow manner. Clarendon gives two inſtances, both of them relative to the great fire of London. The mayor propoſing to pull down a houſe in order to ſtop the progreſs of the fire, was oppoſed by the lawyers, who declared the act to be unlawful; and the houſe was burnt without being pul⯑led [158] down. About the ſame time it was propoſed to break open ſome houſes in the Temple for ſav⯑ing the furniture, the poſſeſſors being in the country; but it was declared burglary to force open the door without conſent of the poſſeſſor. Such literal interpretation, contrary to common ſenſe, has been extended even to inflict puniſh⯑ment. Iſadas was bathing when the alarm was given in Lacedemon, that Epaminondas was at hand with a numerous army. Naked as he was, he ruſhed againſt the enemy with a ſpear in one hand and a ſword in the other, bearing down all before him. The Ephori fined him for going to battle unarmed: but honoured him with a gar⯑land for his gallant behaviour. How abſurd to think, that the law was intended for ſuch a caſe! and how much more abſured to think, that the ſame act ought to be both puniſhed and rewarded! The King of Caſtile being carried off his horſe by a hunted hart, was ſaved by a perſon at hand, who cut his belt. The judges thought a pardon abſolutely requiſite, to relieve from capital pu⯑niſhment a man who had lifted a ſword againſt his ſovereign*. It is a ſalutary regulation, that a man who is abſent cannot be tried for his life. Pope Formoſus died ſuddenly, without ſuffering any puniſhment for his crimes. But this did not ſave his goods from confiſcation: he was dug out of his grave, dreſſed in his pontifical habit; and [159] in that ſhape a criminal proceſs went on againſt him. Could it ſeriouſly be thought, that a rot⯑ten carcaſe brought into court was ſufficient to fulfil the law? The ſame abſurd farce was play⯑ed in Scotland, upon the body of Logan of Reſ⯑talrig, ſeveral years after his interment. The body of Tancred King of Sicily was raiſed from the grave, and the head cut off for ſuppoſed re⯑bellion. Henry IV. of Caſtile was depoſed in his abſence; but, for a colour of juſtice, the following ridiculous ſcene was acted. A wooden ſtatue dreſſed in a royal habit, was placed on a theatre; and the ſentence of depoſition was ſolemnly read to it, as if it had been the King himſelf. The Archbiſhop of Toledo ſeized the crown, another the ſceptre, a third the ſword; and the ceremo⯑ny was concluded with proclaiming another king. How humbling are ſuch ſcenes to man, who va⯑lues himſelf upon the faculty of reaſon as his prime attribute! An expedient of that kind would now be rejected with diſdain, as fit only to amuſe children; and yet it grives me to obſerve that law-proceedings are not yet totally purged of ſuch droſs. By a law in Holland, the criminal's con⯑feſſion is eſſential to a capital puniſhment, no meaner evidence being held ſufficient: and yet if he inſiſt on his innocence, he is tortured till he pronounce the words of confeſſion; as if founds merely were ſufficient, without will or intention. The practice of England in a ſimilar caſe, is no leſs abſurd. Confeſſion is not there required; but it is required, that the perſon accuſed ſhould plead, and ſay whether he is innocent or guilty. But what if he ſtand mute? He is preſſed down by weights till he plead; and if he continue mute, he is preſſed till he give up the ghoſt, a [160] torture known by the name of Peine forte et dure *. Further, law copying religion, has exalt⯑ed ceremonies above the ſubſtantial part. In England, ſo ſtrictly has form been adhered to, as to make the moſt trivial defect in words fatal, however certain the meaning may be. Murdre⯑davit for murdravit, feloniter for felonice, have been adjudged to vitiate an indictment. Burga⯑riter for burglariter hath been a fatal objection; but burgulariter hath been holden good. Webſter being indicted for murder, and the ſtroke being laid ‘"ſiniſtro bracio"’ inſtead of ‘"brachio,"’ he was diſmiſſed. A. B. alias dictus A. C. Butcher, was found to vitiate the indictment; becauſe it ought to have been A. B. Butcher, alias dictus A. C. Butcher. So gladium in dextr [...] ſua, without manu.
There is no bias in human nature more preva⯑lent than an appetite to anticipate futurity, by being made acquainted beforehand with what will happen. That appetite was indulged without reſerve in dark times; and hence omens, auguries, dreams, judicial aſtrology, oracles, and prophe⯑cies, without end. It ſhows ſtrange weakneſs in the rational faculty, not to ſee, that ſuch fore⯑knowledge would be a gift more pernicious to man than Pandora's box: it would deprive him of every motive to action; and leave no place for [161] ſagacity, nor for contriving means to bring about a deſired event. Life is an enchanted caſtle, that gives play to paſſions, and exerciſe to reaſon: remove the evil that hides futurity—behold the enchanted caſtle gone, and in its ſtead a barren and inſipid proſpect. Anxiety about futurity rouſes our ſagacity to prepare for what may hap⯑pen; but an appetite to know what ſagacity can⯑not diſcover, is a weakneſs in nature inconſiſtent with every rational principle*.
An appetite for things rare and wonderful, is a natural bias no leſs univerſal than the former. Any ſtrange or unaccountable event rouſes the at⯑tention and enflames the mind: we ſuck it in greedily, wiſh it to be true, and believe it to be true upon the ſlighteſt evidence; becauſe ſuch belief gratifies the appetite. A hart taken in the foreſt of Senlis by Charles VI. of France, bore a collar upon which was inſcribed, Caeſar hoc me donavit †. The appetite for wonder made every one believe, that a Roman Emperor was meant, and that the beaſt muſt have lived at leaſt a thouſand years; overlooking that the Emperor of Germany is alſo ſtyled Caeſar, and that it was not neceſſary to go back fifty years. This appetite diſplays itſelf even in childhood: ſtories of ghoſts and apparitions are anxiouſly liſtened to; and firmly believed, by means of the terror they oc⯑caſion: and the vulgar accordingly have been cap⯑tivated with ſuch ſtories, upon evidence that [162] would not be ſufficient to aſcertain the ſimpleſt facta. The abſurd and childiſh prodigies that are every where ſcatteerd through the hiſtory of Titus Livius, not to mention other ancient hiſ⯑torians, would be unaccountable in a writer of ſenſe and gravity, were it not for the appetite mentioned. But human belief is not left at the mercy of every irregular bias. Our Maker has ſubjected belief to the correction of the rational faculty; and accordingly, in proportion as reaſon advances toward maturity, wonders, prodigies, apparitions, incantations, witchcraft, and ſuch ſtuff, loſe their influence. That reformation however has been exceedingly ſlow, becauſe the appetite is exceedingly ſtrong. Such ab⯑ſurdities found credit among wiſe men, even as late as the laſt age. I am ready to verify the charge, by introducing two men of the firſt rank for underſtanding: were a greater number neceſ⯑ſary, there would be no difficulty of making a very bulky liſt. The celebrated Grotius ſhall lead the van. Procopius, in his Vandal hiſtory, relates, that ſome orthodox Chriſtians, whoſe tongues were cut out by the Arians, continued miraculouſly to ſpeak as formerly. And to vouch the fact, he appeals to ſome of thoſe miraculous perſons, alive in Conſtantinople at the time of his writing. In the dark ages of Chriſtianity, when different ſects were violently enflamed againſt each other, it is not ſurpriſing, that groſs abſur⯑dities were ſwallowed as real miracles: but is it not ſurpriſing, and equally mortifying, to find Grotius, the greateſt genius of the age he lived in, adopting ſuch abſurdities? For the truth of the foregoing miracle, he appeals not only to [163] Procopius, but to ſeveral writersa; as if the hearſay of a few writers were ſufficient to make us believe an impoſſibility. Could it ſeriouſly be his opinion, that the great God, who governs by general laws, permitting the ſun to ſhine alike up⯑on men of every religion, would miraculouſly ſuſpend the laws of nature, in order to teſtify his diſpleaſure at an honeſt ſect of Chriſtians, howe⯑ver erroneous their tenets may be? Did he alſo believe what Procopius adds, that two of theſe orthodox Chriſtians were again deprived of ſpeech, as a puniſhment inflicted by the Almighty for co⯑habiting with proſtitutes?
I proceed to our famous hiſtorian, the Earl of Clarendon, the other perſon I had in view. A man long in public buſineſs, a conſummate politi⯑cian, and well ſtored with knowledge from books as well as from experience, might be fortified againſt fooliſh miracles, if any man can be forti⯑fied: and yet behold his ſuperſtitious credulity in childiſh ſtories; no leſs weak in that particular, than was his cotemporary Grotius. He gravely relates an incident regarding the aſſaſſination of the Duke of Buckingham, the ſum of which fol⯑lows. ‘"There were many ſtories ſcattered abroad at that time, of prophecies and pre⯑dictions of the Duke's untimely and violent death; one of which was upon a better foun⯑dation of credit, than uſually ſuch diſcourſes are founded upon. There was an officer in the King's wardrobe in Windſor caſtle, of reputa⯑tion for honeſty and diſcretion, and at that time about the age of fifty. About ſix months before the miſerable end of the Duke, this [164] man being in bed, and in good health, there appeared to him at midnight a man of a vene⯑rable aſpect, who drawing the curtains, and fixing his eye upon him, ſaid, Do you know me, Sir? The poor man, half dead with fear, anſwered, That he thought him to be Sir George Villiers, father to the Duke. Upon which he was ordered by the apparition, to go to the Duke, and tell him, that if he did not ſomewhat to ingratiate himſelf with the peo⯑ple, he would be ſuffered to live but a ſhort time. The ſame perſon appeared to him a ſecond and a third time, reproaching him bit⯑terly for not performing his promiſe. The poor man plucked up as much courage as to excuſe himſelf, that it was difficult to find ac⯑ceſs to the Duke, and that he would be thought a madman. The apparition imparted to him ſome ſecrets, which he ſaid would be his cre⯑dentials to the Duke. The officer, introduced to the Duke by Sir Ralph Freeman, was re⯑ceived courteouſly. They walked together near an hour; and the Duke ſometimes ſpoke with great commotion, though his ſervants, with Sir Ralph, were at ſuch a diſtance that they could not hear a word. The officer, returning from the Duke, told Sir Ralph, that when he mentioned the particulars that were to gain him credit, the Duke's colour changed; and he ſwore the officer could come to that knowledge only by the devil; for that theſe particulars were known only to himſelf, and to one perſon more, of whoſe fidelity he was ſe⯑cure. The Duke, who went to accompany the King at hunting, was obſerved to ride all the morning in deep thought; and before the morning was ſpent, left the field, and alighted [165] at his mother's houſe, with whom he was ſhut up for two or three hours. When the Duke left her, his countenance appeared full of trouble, with a mixture of anger, which ne⯑ver appeared before in converſing with her: and ſhe was found overwhelmed with tears, and in great agony. Whatever there was of all this, it is a notorious truth, that when ſhe heard of the Duke's murder, ſhe ſeemed not in the leaſt ſurpriſed, nor did expreſs much ſorrow."’
The name of Lord Clarendon calls for more attention to the foregoing incident than otherwiſe it would deſerve. It is no article of the Chriſtian faith, that the dead preſerve their connection with the living, or are ever ſuffered to return to this world: we have no ſolid evidence for ſuch a fact; nor ever hear of it, except in tales for amuſing or terrifying children. Secondly, The ſtory is inconſiſtent with the courſe of Providence, which, for the beſt purpoſes, has drawn an impe⯑netrable veil between us and futurity. Thirdly, This apparition, though ſuppoſed to be endowed with a miraculous knowledge of future events, is however deficient in the ſagacity that belongs to a perſon of ordinary underſtanding. It appears twice to the officer, without thinking of giving him proper credentials; nor does it at all think of them till ſuggeſted by the officer. Fourthly, Why did not the apparition go directly to the Duke himſelf; where could be the neceſſity of employing a third perſon? The Duke muſt have been much more affected with an apparition to himſelf, than by hearing it at ſecond hand. The officer was afraid of being taken for a madman; and the Duke had ſome reaſon to think him ſuch. Laſtly, The apparition happened above three [166] months before the Duke's death; and yet we hear not of a ſingle ſtep taken by him, in purſu⯑ance of the advice given him. The authority of the hiſtorian, and the regard we owe him, have drawn from me the foregoing reflections; which with reſpect to the ſtory itſelf are very little ne⯑ceſſary; for the evidence is really not ſuch as to verify any ordinary occurrence. His Lordſhip acknowledges, that he had no evidence but com⯑mon report, ſaying, that it was one of the many ſtories ſcattered about at that time. He does not ſay, that the ſtory was related to him by the of⯑ficer, whoſe name he does not even mention, or by Sir Ralph Freeman, or by the Duke's mother, or by the Duke himſelf. If ever any thing hap⯑pened like the ſtory in queſtion, it may with good reaſon be ſuppoſed, that the officer was crazy, or enthuſiaſtically mad: nor have we any evidence beyond common report, that he communicated any ſecrets to the Duke. I ſhall only add upon this article, that here are two remarkable inſtan⯑ces of an obſervation made above, that a man may be high in one ſcience and very low in another. Had Grotius, or had Clarendon, ſtudied the fundamentals of raſon and religion coolly and impartially, as they did other ſciences, they would never have given faith to reports ſo ill vouched, and ſo contradictory to every ſound prin⯑ciple of theology.
Another ſource of erroneous reaſoning is, a ſingular tendency in the mind of man to myſte⯑ries and hidden meanings. The buſy mind is ſel⯑dom ſatisfied with the ſimple and obvious intend⯑ment, where the object makes a deep impreſſion: invention is rouſed to allegorize, and to pierce into hidden views and purpoſes. I have a notable example at hand, with reſpect to forms and ce⯑remonies [167] in religious worſhip. Joſephusa, talking of the tabernacle, has the following paſ⯑ſage. ‘"Let any man conſider the ſtructure of the tabernacle, the ſacerdotal veſtments, the veſſels dedicated to the ſervice of the altar; and he muſt of neceſſity be convinced, that our lawgiver was a pious man, and that all the clamours againſt us and our profeſſion, are mere calumny. For what are all of theſe but the image of the whole world? This will ap⯑pear to any man who ſoberly and impartially examines the matter. The tabernacle of thir⯑ty cubits is divided into three parts; two for the prieſts in general, and as free to them as the earth and the ſea; the third, where no mortal muſt be admitted, is as the Heaven, reſerved for God himſelf. The twelve loaves of ſhew-bread ſignify the twelve months of the year. The candleſtick, compoſed of ſe⯑ven branches, refers to the twelve ſigns of the zodiac, through which the ſeven planets ſhape their courſe; and the ſeven lamps on the top of the ſeven branches bear an analogy to the planets themſelves. The curtains of four co⯑lours repreſent the four elements. The fine linen ſignifies the earth, as flax is raiſed there. By the purple is underſtood the ſea, from the blood of the murex, which dies that colour. The violet colour is a ſymbol of the air; and the ſcarlet of the fire. By the linen garment of the high prieſt, is deſigned the whole body of the earth: by the violet colour the hea⯑vens. The pomegranates ſignify lightning: the bells tolling ſignify thunder. The four-coloured ephod bears a reſemblance to the ve⯑ry [168] nature of the univerſe, and the interweav⯑ing it with gold has a regard to the rays of light. The girdle about the body of the prieſt is as the ſea about the globe of the earth. The two ſardonyx ſtones are a kind of figure of the ſun and moon; and the twelve other ſtones may be underſtood, either of the twelve months, or of the twelve ſigns in the zodiac. The violet-coloured tiara is a reſemblance of heaven; and it would be irreverent to have written the ſacred name of God upon any other colour. The triple crown and plate of gold give us to underſtand the glory and Ma⯑jeſty of Almighty God. This is a plain illuſ⯑tration of theſe matters; and I would not loſe any opportunity of doing juſtice to the ho⯑nour and wiſdom of our incomparable Law⯑giver."’ How much wire-drawn, and how re⯑mote from any appearance of truth, are the fore⯑ing alluſions and imagined reſemblances! But re⯑ligious forms and ceremonies, however arbitrary, are never held to be ſo. If an uſeful purpoſe do not appear, it is taken for granted, that there muſt be a hidden meaning; and any meaning, however childiſh, will ſerve at a pinch. Such propenſity there is in dark ages for allegorizing, that even our Saviour's miracles have not eſcap⯑ed. Where-ever any ſeeming difficulty occurs in the plain ſenſe, the fathers of the church, Ori⯑gen, Auguſtine, and Hilary, are never at a loſs for a myſtic meaning. ‘"Sacrifice to the celeſtial gods with an odd number, and to the terreſ⯑trial gods with an even number,"’ is a precept of Pythagoras. Another is, ‘"turn round in adoring the gods, and ſit down when thou haſt worſhipped."’ The learned make a ſtrange buſtle about the hidden meaning of theſe precepts. But, after all, have they any hidden [169] meaning? Forms and ceremonies are uſeful in external worſhip, for occupying the vulgar; and it is of no importance what they are, pro⯑vided they prevent the mind from wandering. Why ſuch partiality to ancient ceremonies, when no hidden meaning is ſuppoſed in thoſe of Chri⯑ſtians, ſuch as bowing to the eaſt, or the prieſt performing the liturgy, partly in a black upper garment, partly in a white? No ideas are more ſimple than of numbers, nor leſs ſuſceptible of any hidden meaning; and yet the profound Py⯑thagoras has imagined many ſuch meanings. The number one, ſays he, having no parts, repreſents the Deity: it repreſents alſo order, peace, and tranquility, which reſult from unity of ſentiment. The number two repreſents diſorder, confuſion, and change. He diſcovered in the number three the moſt ſublime myſteries: all things are com⯑poſed, ſays he, of three ſubſtances. The num⯑ber four is holy in its nature, and conſtitutes the divine eſſence, which conſiſts in unity, pow⯑er, benevolence, and wiſdom. Would one be⯑lieve, that the great philoſopher, who demon⯑ſtrated the 47th propoſition of the firſt book of Euclid, was the inventor of ſuch childiſh con⯑ceits? Perhaps Pythagoras meant only to divert himſelf with them. Whether ſo or not, it ſeems difficult to be explained, how ſuch trifles were preſerved in memory, and handed down to us through ſo many generations. All that can be ſaid is, that during the infancy of knowledge, every novelty makes a figure, and that it re⯑quires a long courſe of time to ſeparate the corn from the chaff*. A certain writer, ſmitten with [170] the conceit of hidden meanings, has applied his talent to the conſtellations of the zodiac. The lion typifies the force or heat of the ſun in the month of July, when he enters that conſtellation. The conſtellation where the ſun is in the month of Auguſt is termed the virgin, ſignifying the time of harveſt. He enters the balance in Sep⯑tember, denoting the equality of day and night. The ſcorpion, where he is found in October, is an emblem of the diſeaſes that are frequent dur⯑ing that month, &c. The balance, I acknow⯑ledge, is well hit off; but I ſee not clearly the reſemblance of the force of a lion to the heat of the ſun; and ſtill leſs that of harveſt to a virgin: the ſpring would be more happily repreſented by a virgin, and the harveſt by a woman in the act of delivery.
The tendency in the mind of man to myſteries and allegories, diſplays itſelf with great vigour upon our forefathers, and upon the ancients in general, by means of the great veneration that is paid them. Before writing was known, ancient hiſtory is made up of traditional fables. A Tro⯑jan Brutus peopled England; and the Scots are deſcended from Scota, daughter to an Egyptian king. What reaſon have we to doubt but that the hiſtories of the heathen gods are equally involved [171] in fable? We pretend not to draw any hidden meaning from the former: why ſhould we ſuſpect any ſuch meaning in the latter? Allegory is a ſpecies of writing too refined for a ſavage or bar⯑barian: it is the fruit of a cultivated imagination; and was a late invention even in Greece. The allegories of Eſop are of the ſimpleſt kind, and yet they were compoſed after learning began to flouriſh; and Cebes, whoſe allegory about the life of man is juſtly celebrated, was a diſciple of Socrates. Prepoſſeſſion however in favour of the ancients makes us conclude, that there muſt be ſome hidden meaning or allegory in their hiſtori⯑cal fables; for no better reaſon than that they are deſtitute of common ſenſe. In the Greek my⯑thology, there are numberleſs fables related as hiſtorical facts merely; witneſs the fable of gods mixing with women, and procreating giants, like what we find in the fabulous hiſtories of ma⯑ny other nations; theſe giants attempting to de⯑throne Jupiter; Apollo keeping the ſheep of Ad⯑metus; Minerva ſpringing from the head of Jove*; Bacchus cut out of his thigh; Orpheus going to hell for his wife; Mars and Venus caught by Vulcan in a net; and a thouſand other ſuch childiſh ſtories. But the Greeks, many [172] centuries after the invention of ſuch fooliſh fables, becoming illuſtrious for arts and ſciences, nothing would ſatisfy writers in later times, but to dub them profound Philoſophers even in their cradle, when mere ſavages; and hence endleſs attempts to detect myſteries and hidden meanings in their fables. Let other interpreters of that kind paſs; they give me no concern: but I cannot, without the deepeſt concern, behold our illuſtrious philo⯑ſopher Bacon employing his talents ſo abſurdly. What imbecility muſt there be in human nature, when ſo great a genius is capable of ſuch puerili⯑ties! As a ſubject ſo humbling is far from being agreeable, I confine myſelf to a few inſtances. In an ancient fable, Prometheus formed man out of clay; and kindling a bundle of birch rods at the chariot of the ſun, brought down fire to the earth for the uſe of his creature man. And tho' un⯑grateful man complained to Jupiter of that theft, yet the god, pleaſed with the ingenuity of Pro⯑metheus, not only confirmed to man the uſe of fire, but conferred on him a gift much more con⯑ſiderable: the gift was perpetual youth, which was laid upon an aſs to be carried to the earth. The aſs wanting to drink at a brook, was oppo⯑ſed by a ſerpent, who inſiſted to have the bur⯑den, without which, no drink for the poor aſs. And thus, for a draught of plain water, was per⯑petual youth transferred from man to the ſerpent. This fable has a ſtriking reſemblance to many in the Edda; and, in the manner of the Edda, ac⯑counts for the invention of fire, and for the mor⯑tality of man. Nor is there in all the Edda one more childiſh, or more diſtant from any appear⯑ance of a rational meaning. It is handled however by our philoſopher, with much ſolemn gravity, as if every ſource of wiſdom were locked up in it. The explanation he gives, being too long to be [173] copied here, ſhall be reduced to a few particu⯑lars. After an elogium upon fire, his Lordſhip proceeds thus. ‘"The manner wherein Prome⯑theus ſtole his fire, is properly deſcribed from the nature of the thing; he being ſaid to have done it by applying a rod of birch to the chari⯑ot of the ſun: for birch is uſed in ſtriking and beating; which clearly denotes fire to proceed from violent percuſſions and colliſions of bo⯑dies, whereby the matters ſtruck are ſubtili⯑zed, rarefied, put into motion, and ſo prepa⯑red to receive the heat of the celeſtial bodies. And accordingly they, in a clandeſtine and ſe⯑cret manner, ſnatch fire, as it were by ſtealth, from the chariot of the ſun."’ He goes on as follows. ‘"The next is a remarkable part of the fable; which repreſents, that men, inſtead of gratitude, accuſed both Prometheus and his fire to Jupiter: and yet the accuſation proved ſo pleaſant to Jupiter, that he not only indulged mankind the uſe of fire, but conferred upon them perpetual youth. Here it may ſeem ſtrange, that the ſin of ingratitude ſhould meet with approbation or reward. But the allegory has another view; and denotes, that the accu⯑ſation both of human nature and human art, proceeds from a noble and laudable temper of mind, viz. modeſty; and alſo tends to a very good purpoſe, viz. to ſtir up freſh induſtry and new diſcoveries."’ Can any thing be more wire-drawn?
Vulcan, attempting the chaſtity of Minerva, had recourſe to force. In the ſtruggle, his ſemen, falling upon the ground, produced Ericthonius; whoſe body from the middle upward was comely and well proportioned, his thighs and legs ſmall and deformed like an eel. Conſcious of that de⯑fect, he was the inventer of chariots; which [174] ſhowed the graceful part of his body, and con⯑cealed what was deformed. Liſten to the expla⯑nation of this ridiculous fable, ‘"Art, by the various uſes it makes of fire, is here repreſent⯑ed by Vulcan: and Nature is repreſented by Minerva, becauſe of the induſtry employed in her works. Art when it offers violence to Na⯑ture in order to bend her to its purpoſe, ſel⯑dom attains the end propoſed. Yet, upon great ſtruggle and application, there proceed certain imperfect births, or lame abortive works; which however, with great pomp and deceitful appearances, are triumphantly carri⯑ed about, and ſhown by impoſtors."’ I admit the ingenuity of that forced meaning; but had the inventer of that fable any latent meaning? If he had, why did he conceal it? The ingenious meaning would have merited praiſe; the fable it⯑ſelf none at all.
I ſhall add but one other inſtance, for they grow tireſome. Sphinx was a monſter, having the face and voice of a virgin, the wings of a bird, and the talons of a gryphin. She reſid⯑ed on the ſummit of a mountain, near the city Thebes. Her manner was, to lie in ambuſh for travellers, to propoſe dark riddles which ſhe re⯑ceived from the Muſes, and to tear thoſe to pieces who could not ſolve them. The Thebans having offered their kingdom to the man who ſhould in⯑terpret theſe riddles, Oedipus preſented himſelf before the monſter, and he was required to ex⯑plain the following riddle, viz. What creature is that, which being born four-footed, becomes af⯑terwards two-footed, then three-footed, and laſtly four-footed again. Oedipus anſwered, It was man, who in his infancy crawls upon his hands and feet, then walks upright upon his two feet, walks in old age with a ſtick, and at laſt lies [175] four-footed in bed. Oedipus having thus obtain⯑ed the victory, ſlew the monſter; and laying the carcaſe upon an aſs, carried it off in triumph. Now for the explanation. ‘"This is an elegant and inſtructive fable, invented to repreſent ſcience: for Science may be called a monſter, being ſtrangely gazed at and admired by the ignorant. Her figure and form is various, by reaſon of the vaſt variety of ſubjects that ſci⯑ence conſiders. Her voice and countenance are repreſented female, by reaſon of her gay appearance, and volubility of ſpeech. Wings are added, becauſe the ſciences and their in⯑ventions fly about in a moment; for know⯑ledge, like light communicated from torch to torch, is preſently catched, and copiouſly dif⯑fuſed. Sharp and hooked talons are elegant⯑ly attributed to her; becauſe the axioms and arguments of ſcience fix down the mind, and keep it from moving or ſlipping away."’ A⯑gain: ‘"All ſcience ſeems placed on high, as it were on the tops of mountains that are hard to climb; for ſcience is juſtly imagined a ſublime and lofty thing, looking down upon ignorance, and at the ſame time taking an extenſive view on all ſides, as is uſual on the tops of moun⯑tains. Sphinx is ſaid to propoſe difficult queſ⯑tions and riddles, which ſhe received from the Muſes. Theſe queſtions, while they remain with the Muſes, may be pleaſant, as contem⯑plation and enquiry are when knowledge is their only aim: but after they are delivered to Sphinx, that is, to practice, which impels to action, choice, and determination; then it is that they become ſevere and torturing; and unleſs ſolved, ſtrangely perplex the human mind, and tear it to pieces. It is with the ut⯑moſt elegance added in the fable, that the car⯑caſe [176] of Sphinx was laid upon an aſs; for there is nothing ſo ſubtile and abſtruſe, but after being made plain, may be conceived by the ſloweſt capacity."’ According to ſuch latitude of interpretation, there is nothing more eaſy than to make quidlibet ex quolibet.
I will detain the reader but a moment longer, to hear what our author ſays in juſtification of ſuch myſterious meaning. Out of many reaſons, I ſelect the two following. ‘"It may paſs for a farther indication of a concealed and ſecret meaning, that ſome of theſe fables are ſo ab⯑ſurd and idle in their narration, as to proclaim an allegory even afar off. A fable that car⯑ries probability with it, may be ſuppoſed in⯑vented for pleaſure, or in imitation of hiſtory; but what could never be conceived or related in this way, muſt ſurely have a different uſe. For example, what a monſtrous fiction is this, That Jupiter ſhould take Metis to wife; and as ſoon as he found her pregnant eat her up; whereby he alſo conceived, and out of his head brought forth Pallas armed! Certainly no mortal could, but for the ſake of the moral it couches, invent ſuch an abſurd dream as this, ſo much out of the road of thought."’ At that rate, the more ridiculous or abſurd a fable is, the more inſtructive it muſt be. This opinion reſembles that of the an⯑cient Germans with reſpect to mad women, who were held to be ſo wiſe, as that every thing they uttered was prophetic. Did it never once occur to our author, that in the infancy of the reaſoning fa⯑culty, the imagination is ſuffered to range without control, as in a dream; and that the vulgar in all [177] ages are delighted with wonderful ſtories; the more out of nature, the more to their taſte?
We proceed to the other reaſon. ‘"The ar⯑gument of moſt weight with me is, That many of theſe fables appear not to have been invent⯑ed by the perſons who relate and divulge them, whether Homer, Heſiod, or others; for if I were aſſured they firſt flowed from thoſe later times and authors, I ſhould never expect any thing ſingularly great or noble from ſuch an origin. But whoever attentively conſiders the thing, will find, that theſe fables are delivered down by thoſe writers, not as matters then firſt invented, but as received and embraced in ear⯑lier ages. And this principally raiſes my eſteem of thoſe fables; which I receive, not as the product of the age, or invention of the poets, but as ſacred relics, gentle whiſpers, and the breath of better times, that from the traditions of more ancient nations, came at length into the flutes and trumpets of the Greeks."’ Was it our author's real opinion, that the farther back we trace the hiſtory of man, the more of ſcience and knowledge is found; and conſequently that ſavages are the moſt learned of all men?
The following fable of the ſavage Canadians ought to be myſterious, if either of the reaſons urged above be concluſive. ‘"There were in the beginning but ſix men in the world, (from whence ſprung is not ſaid): one of theſe aſ⯑cended to heaven in queſt of a woman named Atahentſic, and had carnal knowledge of her. She being thrown headlong from the height of the empyrean, was received on the back of a tortoiſe, and delivered of two children, one of whom ſlew the other."’ This fable is ſo ab⯑ſurd, that it muſt have a latent meaning; and one needs but copy our author to pump a deep [178] myſtery out of it, however little intended by the inventer of the fable. And if either abſurdity or antiquity entitle fables to be held ſacred relics, gentle whiſpers, and the breath of better times, the following Japaneſe fables are well entitled to theſe diſtinguiſhing epithets. ‘"Bunſio, in wed⯑lock, having had no children for many years, ad⯑dreſſed her prayers to the gods, was heard, and was delivered of 500 eggs. Fearing that the eggs might produce monſters, ſhe packed them up in a box, and threw them into the river. An old fiſherman finding the box, hatched the eggs in an oven, every one of which produced a child. The children were fed with boiled rice and mug⯑wort-leaves; and being at laſt left to ſhift for themſelves, they fell a robbing on the highway. Hearing of a man famous for great wealth, they told their ſtory at his gate, and begged ſome food. This happening to be the houſe of their mother, ſhe owned them for her children, and gave a great entertainment to her friends and neighbours. She was afterward inliſted among the goddeſſes by the name of Benſaiten: her 500 ſons were ap⯑pointed to be her attendants; and to this day ſhe is worſhipped in Japan as the goddeſs of riches."’ Take another fable of the ſame ſtamp. The Japaneſe have a table of lucky and unlucky days, which they believe to have been compoſed by Abino Seimei, a famous aſtrologer, and a ſort of demi-god. They have the following tradition of him. ‘"A young fox, purſued by hunters, fled into a temple, and took ſhelter in the boſom of Abino Jaſſima, ſon and heir to the king of the country. Refuſing to yield the poor creature to the unmerciful hunters, he defended himſelf with great bravery, and ſet the fox at liberty. The hunters, through reſentment againſt the young prince, murdered his royal father; but Jaſſima [179] revenged his father's death, killing the traitors with his own hand. Upon this ſignal victory, a lady of incomparable beauty appeared to him, and made ſuch an impreſſion on his heat, that he took her to wife. Abino Scimei, procreated of that marriage, was endowed with divine wiſdom, and with the precious gift of prophecy. Jaſſima was ignorant that his wife was the very fox whoſe life he had ſaved, till ſhe reſumed by degrees her former ſhape."’ If there be any hidden myſtery in this tale, I ſhall not deſpair of finding a my⯑ſtery in every fairy-tale invented by Madam Go⯑mez.
It is lamentable, how ſlowly human underſtand⯑ing, and the faculty of reaſon, creep toward ma⯑turity. If this reflection be verified in our cele⯑brated philoſopher Bacon, how much more in the bulk of mankind? It is comfortable, however, that human underſtanding is in a progreſs toward maturity, however ſlow. The fancy of allegori⯑zing ancient fables, is now out of faſhion: en⯑lightened reaſon has unmaſked theſe fables, and left them in their nakedneſs, as the invention of illiterate ages, when wonder was the prevail⯑ing paſſion.
Having diſcuſſed the firſt two heads, I proceed to the third, viz. Erroneous reaſoning, occaſi⯑oned by acquired biaſſes. And one of theſe that has the greateſt influence in perverting the rati⯑onal faculty, is blind religious zeal. There is not in nature a ſyſtem more ſimple or perſpicuous than that of pure religion; and yet what a com⯑poſition hath it been rendered of metaphyſical ſubtilties, and unintelligible jargon! That ſubject being too well known to need illuſtration, I ſhall confine myſelf to a few inſtances of the in⯑fluence that religious ſuperſtition has on other ſub⯑jects.
[180] A hiſtory-painter and a player require the ſame ſort of genius. The one by colours, the other by looks and geſtures, expreſſes various modifications of paſſion, even what are beyond the reach of words; and to accompliſh theſe ends, great ſenſibility is requiſite, as well as judgment. Why then is not a player equally reſpected with a hiſtory-painter? It was thought by zealots, that a play is an entertainment too ſplendid for a mortified Chriſtian; upon which account players fell under church-cenſure, and were held unwor⯑thy of Chriſtian burial. A hiſtory-painter, on the contrary, being employed in painting for the church, was always in high eſteem. It is only among Proteſtants that players are beginning to be reſtored to their privileges as free citizens; and there perhaps never exiſted a hiſtory-painter more juſtly eſteemed, than Garrick, a player, is in Great Britain. Ariſtarchus having taught, that the earth moves round the ſun, was accuſed by the Heathen prieſts, for troubling the repoſe of their houſehold-gods. Copernicus, for the ſame doctrine, was accuſed by Chriſtian prieſts, as contradicting the ſcriptures, which talk of the ſun's moving. And Galileo, for adhering to Copernicus, was condemned to priſon and pe⯑nance: he found it neceſſary to recant upon his knees in a ſolemn manner. A bias acquired from Ariſtotle, kept reaſon in chains for centuries. Scholaſtic divinity in particular, founded on the philoſophy of that author, was more hurtful to the reaſoning faculty than the Goths and Huns. Tycho Brahé ſuffered great perſecution for main⯑taining, that the heavens were ſo far empty of matter as to give free courſe to the comets; con⯑trary to Ariſtotle, who taught, that the heavens are harder than a diamond: it was extremely ill taken, that a ſimple mortal ſhould pretend to [181] give Ariſtotle the lie. During the infancy of reaſon, authority is the prevailing argument*.
Reaſon is extremely apt to be warped by habit. In the diſputes among the Athenians, about ad⯑juſting the form of their government, it is ob⯑ſervable, that thoſe who lived in the high country were for democracy; that the inhabitants of the plains were for oligarchy; and the ſeamen for monarchy. Shepherds are all equal: in a corn⯑country, there are a few maſters and many ſer⯑vants: on ſhipboard, there is one commander, and all the reſt ſubjects. Habit was their adviſer: none of them thought of conſulting reaſon in or⯑der to judge what was the beſt form upon the whole. Habit of a different kind has an influence no leſs powerful. Perſons who are in the habit of reaſoning, require demonſtration for every thing: even a ſelf-evident propoſition is not ſuf⯑fered to eſcape. Theſe ſuperfluous proofs occur more than once in the Elements of Euclid. Nor has Ariſtotle, with all his ſkill in logics, entirely avoided them. Can any thing be more ſelf⯑evident, than the difference between pleaſure and motion? Yet Ariſtotle attempts to demon⯑ſtrate, that they are different. ‘"No motion,"’ [182] ſays he, ‘"except circular motion, is perfect in any one point of time: there is always ſome⯑thing wanting during its courſe, and it is not perfected till it arrive at its end. But pleaſure is perfect in every point of time; being the ſame from the beginning to the end."’ The difference is clear from perception merely; but is far from being clear from this demonſtration. Plato alſo attempts to demonſtrate a ſelf-evident propoſition, viz. That a quality is not a body. ‘"Every body,"’ ſays he, ‘"is a ſubject: qua⯑lity is not a ſubject, but an accident; ergo, quality is not a body. Again, A body cannot be in a ſubject: every quality is in a ſubject; ergo, quality is not a body."’ But Deſcartes affords the moſt illuſtrious inſtance of the kind. He was the greateſt geometer of the age he lived in, and one of the greateſt of any age; which inſenſibly led him to overlook intuitive know⯑ledge, and to admit no propoſition but what is demonſtrated or proved in the regular form of ſyllogiſm. He took a fancy to doubt even of his own exiſtence, till he was convinced of it by the following argument. Cogito, ergo ſum: I think, therefore I exiſt. And what ſort of a demonſtra⯑tion is this after all? In the very fundamental propoſition he acknowledges his exiſtence by the term I; and how abſurd is it, to imagine a proof neceſſary of what is admitted to be true in the fundamental propoſition? In the next place, How does our author know that he thinks? If nothing is to be taken for granted, an argument is no leſs neceſſary to prove that he thinks, than to prove that he exiſts. It is true, that he has intuitive knowledge of his thinking; but has he not the ſame of his exiſting? Would not a man deſerve to be laughed at, who, after warming himſelf at a fire, ſhould imagine the following argument [183] neceſſary to prove its exiſtence, ‘"The fire burns, ergo it exiſts?"’ Liſten to an author of high reputation attempting to demonſtrate a ſelf-evident propoſition. ‘"The labour of B, cannot be the labour of C; becauſe it is the applica⯑tion of the organs and powers of B, not of C, to the effecting of ſomething; and therefore the labour is as much B's as the limbs and faculties made uſe of are his. Again, the effect or produce of the labour of B, is not the effect of the labour of C: and therefore this effect or produce is B's, not C's; as much B's, as the labour was B's, and not C's: Be⯑cauſe, what the labour of B cauſes or produ⯑ces, B produces by his labour; or it is the product of B by his labour: that is, it is B's product, not C's, or any other's. And if C ſhould pretend to any property in that which B can truly call his, he would act contrary to trutha."’
In every ſubject of reaſoning, to define terms is neceſſary in order to avoid miſtakes. But there muſt be words that admit not of a definition, otherwiſe definitions would follow definitions without end: and ſuch words are what ſignify ſimple ideas, which have no parts nor compoſi⯑tion. The habit however of defining is ſo in⯑veterate in ſome men, as to make them attempt to define words ſignifying ſimple ideas. Is there any neceſſity to define motion: do not children underſtand the meaning of the word? And how is it poſſible to define it, when there are not words more ſimple to define it by? Yet Wor⯑ſterb attempts that bold taſk. ‘"A conti⯑nual [184] change of place,"’ ſays he, ‘"or leaving one place for another, without remaining for any ſpace of time in the ſame place, is called motion."’ That every body in motion is con⯑tinually changing place, is true: but change of place is not motion; it is the effect of motion. Graveſenda defines motion thus, ‘"Motus eſt tranſlatio de loco in locum, ſive continua loci mutatio*;"’ which is the ſame with the former. Yet this very author admits locus or place to ſignify a ſimple idea, incapable of a de⯑finition. Is it more ſimple or more intelligible than motion? But, of all, the moſt remarkable definition of motion is that of Ariſtotle, famous for its impenetrability, or rather abſurdity, viz. ‘"Actus entis in potentia, quatenus in poten⯑tia†."’
Extenſion enters into the conception of every particle of matter; becauſe every particle of matter has length, breadth, and thickneſs. Fi⯑gure in the ſame manner enters into the concep⯑tion of every particle of matter; becauſe every particle of matter is bounded. By the power of abſtraction, figure may be conceived independent of the body that is figured; and extenſion may be conceived independent of the body that is ex⯑tended. Theſe particulars are abundantly plain and obvious; and yet obſerve what a heap of jargon is employed by the followers of Leibnitz, in their fruitleſs endeavours to define extenſion. In order to that end, they begin with ſimple ex⯑iſtences, which they ſay are unextended, and [185] without parts. According to that definition, ſimple exiſtences cannot belong to matter, be⯑cauſe the ſmalleſt particle of matter has both parts and extenſion. But to let that paſs, they endeavour to ſhow as follows, how the idea of extenſion ariſes from theſe ſimple exiſtences. ‘"We may look upon ſimple exiſtences, as having mutual relations with reſpect to their internal ſtate; relations that form a certain order in their manner of exiſtence. And this order or arrangement of things, coexiſting and linked together, but ſo as we do not diſtinctly under⯑ſtand how, cauſes in us a confuſed idea, from whence ariſes the appearance of extenſion."’ A Peripatetic philoſopher being aſked, What ſort of things the ſenſible ſpecies of Ariſtotle are? anſwered, That they are neither entities nor non⯑entities, but ſomething intermediate between the two. The famous aſtronomer Iſmael Bulialdus lays down the following propoſition, and attempts a mathematical demonſtration of it, ‘"That light is a mean-proportional between corporeal ſub⯑ſtance and incorporeal."’
I cloſe with a curious ſort of reaſoning, ſo ſin⯑gular indeed as not to come under any of the fore⯑going heads. The firſt editions of the lateſt ver⯑ſion of the Bible into Engliſh have a preface, in which the tranſlators make the following apology for not keeping cloſe to the words of the original. ‘"Another thing we think good to admoniſh thee of, gentle reader, that we have not tied our⯑ſelves to an uniformity of phraſing, or to an identity of words, as ſome peradventure would wiſh that we had done, becauſe they obſerve, that ſome learned men ſomewhere have been as exact as they could be that way. Truly, that we might not vary from the ſenſe of that which we have tranſlated before, if the word [186] ſignified the ſame in both places, (for there be ſome words that be not of the ſame ſenſe every where), we were eſpecially careful, and made a conſcience according to our duty. But that we ſhould expreſs the ſame notion in the ſame particular word; as, for example, if we tranſlate the Hebrew or Greek word once by purpoſe, never to call it intent; if one where journeying, never travelling; if one where think, never ſuppoſe; if one where pain, never ache; if one where joy, never gladneſs, &c.; thus to mince the matter, we thought to favour more of curioſity than wiſdom, and that rather it would breed ſcorn in the Atheiſt, than bring profit to the godly reader. For is the king⯑dom of God become words or ſyllables? Why ſhould we be in bondage to them, if we may be free; uſe one preciſely, when we may uſe another, no leſs fit, as commodiouſly? We might alſo be charged by ſcoffers, with ſome unequal dealing toward a great number of good Engliſh words. For as it is written by a cer⯑tain great philoſopher, that he ſhould ſay, that thoſe logs were happy that were made images to be worſhipped; for their fellows, as good as they, lay for blocks behind the fire: ſo if we ſhould ſay, as it were, unto certain words, Stand up higher, have a place in the Bible always; and to others of like quality, Get ye hence, be baniſhed for ever, we might be taxed peradventure with St. James his words, namely, to be partial in ourſelves, and judges of evil thoughts."’ Quaeritur, Can this tranſlation be ſafely relied on, as the rule of faith, when ſuch are the tranſla⯑tors?
APPENDIX.
[187]IN reviewing the foregoing ſketch, it occurred that a fair analyſis of Ariſtotle's logics, would be a valuable addition to the hiſtorical branch. A diſ⯑tinct and candid account of a ſyſtem that for many ages governed the reaſoning part of man⯑kind, cannot but be acceptable to the public. Curioſity will be gratified, in ſeeing a phantom delineated, that ſo long faſcinated the learned world; a phantom, which, like the pyramids of Egypt, or hanging gardens of Babylon, is a ſtructure of infinite genius, but abſolutely uſeleſs, unleſs for raiſing wonder. Dr. Reid, profeſſor of moral philoſophy in the college of Glaſgow, reliſhed the thought; and his friend⯑ſhip to me prevailed on him, after much ſolli⯑citation, to undertake the laborious taſk. No man is better acquainted with Ariſtotle's writ⯑ings; and, without any enthuſiaſtic attach⯑ment, he holds that philoſopher to be a firſt⯑rate genius.
The logics of Ariſtotle have been on the decline more than a century; and are at preſent relegated to ſchools and colleges. They have occaſionally been criticiſed by different writers; but this is the firſt attempt to draw them out of their obſcurity into day-light. By what follows, one will be enabled to paſs a [188] true judgment on them, and to determine, whether they ought, or ought not, to make a branch of education. The Doctor's eſſay, as a capital article in the progreſs and hiſtory of the ſciences, will, I hope, be made welcome, even with the fatigue of ſqueezing through many thorny paths, before a proper view can be obtained of that ancient and ſtupendous fabric.
It will at the ſame time ſhew the hurt that Ariſtotle has done to the reaſoning faculty, by drawing it out of its natural courſe into devious paths. His artificial mode of reaſoning, is no leſs ſuperficial than intricate. I ſay, ſuperfi⯑cial; for in none of his logical works, is a ſingle truth attempted to be proved by ſyllo⯑giſm that requires a proof: the propoſitions he undertakes to prove by ſyllogiſm, are all of them ſelf evident. Take for inſtance the fol⯑lowing propoſition, That man has a power of ſelf-motion. To prove this, he aſſumes the following axiom, upon which indeed every one of his ſyllogiſms are founded, viz. That whatever is true of a number of particulars joined together, holds true of every one ſepa⯑rately; which is thus expreſſed in logical terms, Whatever is true of the genus, holds true of every ſpecies. Founding upon that axiom, he reaſons thus: ‘"All animals have a power of ſelf-motion: man is an animal: ergo, man has a power of ſelf-motion."’ Now if all animals have a power of ſelf-motion, it requires no argument to prove, that man, an animal, has that power: and therefore, what he gives as a concluſion or conſequence, is not really ſo; it is not inferred from the fundamental propoſition, but is included in it. At the ſame time, the ſelf-motive power of man, is a fact [189] that cannot be known but from experience. I add, that the ſelf-motive power of man, is more clearly aſcertained by experience, than that of any other animal: and in attempting to prove man to be a ſelf-motive animal, is it not abſurd, to found the argument on a propoſi⯑tion leſs certain than that undertaken to be de⯑monſtrated? What is here obſerved, will be found applicable to the bulk, if not the whole, of his ſyllogiſms.
It appears ſingular, that Ariſtotle himſelf never attempts to apply his ſyllogiſtic mode of reaſoning, to any ſubject handled by him: on ethics, on rhetoric, and on poetry, he argues like a rational being, without once putting in practice any of his own rules. But how is it poſſible, that a man of his capacity could long remain ignorant, how inſufficient a ſyllogiſm is for diſcovering any latent truth? He certainly intended his ſyſtem of logics, chiefly, if not ſolely, for diſputation: and if ſuch was his purpoſe, he has been wonderfully ſucceſsful; for nothing can be better contrived than that ſyſtem, for wrangling and diſputing without end. He indeed in a manner, profeſſes this to be his aim, in his books De Sophiſticis elen⯑chis.
Some ages hence, when the goodly fabric of the Romiſh ſpiritual power ſhall be laid low in the duſt, and ſcarce a veſtige remain, it will among antiquaries be a curious enquiry, What was the nature and extent of a tyranny, more oppreſſive to the minds of men, than the tyran⯑ny of ancient Rome was to their perſons? Dur⯑ing every ſtep of the enquiry, poſterity will rejoice over mental liberty, no leſs precious in their eyes than perſonal liberty. The deſpotiſm of Ariſtotle with reſpect to the faculty of rea⯑ſon, [190] was no leſs complete, than that of the Biſhop of Rome with reſpect to religion; and it has now become a proper ſubject of curioſity, to enquire into the nature and extent of that deſpotiſm, from which men are at laſt ſet hap⯑pily free. One cannot peruſe the following ſheets, without ſympathetic pain for the weak⯑neſs of man with reſpect to his nobleſt faculty; but that pain will redouble his ſatisfaction, in now being left free to the dictates of reaſon and common ſenſe.
In my reveries, I have more than once com⯑pared Ariſtotle's logics to a bubble made of ſoap⯑water for amuſing children; a beautiful figure with ſplendid colours; fair on the outſide, emp⯑ty within. It has for more than two thouſand years been the hard fate of Ariſtotle's followers, Ixion like, to embrace a cloud for a goddeſs.—But this is more than ſufficient for a preface: and I had almoſt forgot, that I am detaining my readers from better entertainment, in liſtening to Dr. Reid.
A Brief Account of ARISTOTLE'S LOGIC. With REMARKS.
[191]CHAP. I
Of the Firſt Three Treatiſes.
ARISTOTLE had very uncommon advanta⯑ges: born in an age when the philoſophical ſpirit in Greece had long flouriſhed, and was in its greateſt vigour; brought up in the court of Macedon, where his father was the King's phy⯑ſician; twenty years a favourite ſcholar of Plato, and tutor to Alexander the Great; who both honoured him with his friendſhip, and ſupplied him with every thing neceſſary for the proſecution of his enquiries.
Theſe advantages he improved by indefatiga⯑ble ſtudy, and immenſe reading. He was the firſt we know, ſays Strabo, who compoſed a library. And in this the Egyptian and Pergame⯑nian kings, copied his example. As to his ge⯑nius, [192] it would be diſreſpectful to mankind, not to allow an uncommon ſhare to a man who governed the opinions of the moſt enlightened part of the ſpecies near two thouſand years.
If his talents had been laid out ſolely for the diſcovery of truth, and the good of mankind, his laurels would have remained for every freſh: but he ſeems to have had a greater paſſion for fame than for truth, and to have wanted rather to be admired as the prince of philoſophers, than to be uſeful: ſo that it is dubious whether there be in his character moſt of the philoſopher, or of the ſophiſt. The opinion of Lord Bacon is not without probability, That his ambition was as boundleſs as that of his royal pupil, the one aſpiring at univerſal monarchy over the bodies and fortunes of men, the other over their opini⯑ons. If this was the caſe, it cannot be ſaid, that the philoſopher purſued his aim with leſs induſ⯑try, leſs ability, or leſs ſucceſs, than the hero.
His writings carry too evident marks of that philoſophical pride, vanity, and envy, which have often ſullied the character of the learned. He determines boldly things above all human knowledge; and enters upon the moſt difficult queſtions, as his pupil entered on a battle, with full aſſurance of ſucceſs. He delivers his deci⯑ſions oracularly, and without any fear of miſtake. Rather than confeſs his ignorance, he hides it under hard words and ambiguous expreſſions, of which his interpreters can make what pleaſes them. There is even reaſon to ſuſpect, that he wrote often with affected obſcurity, either that the air of myſtery might procure greater veneration, or that his books might be under⯑ſtood only by the adepts who had been initiated in his philoſophy.
[193] His conduct towards the writers that went be⯑fore him has been much cenſured. After the manner of the Ottoman princes, ſays Lord Veru⯑lam, he thought his throne could not be ſecure unleſs he killed all his brethren. Ludovicus Vives charges him with detracting from all philoſophers, that he might derive that glory to himſelf, of which he robbed them. He rarely quotes an au⯑thor but with a view to cenſure, and is not very fair in repreſenting the opinions which he cen⯑ſures.
The faults we have mentioned are ſuch as might be expected in a man, who had the daring ambition to be tranſmitted to all future ages, as the prince of philoſophers, as one who had carri⯑ed every branch of human knowledge to its ut⯑moſt limit; and who was not very ſcrupulous about the means he took to obtain his end.
We ought, however, to do him the juſtice to obſerve, that although the pride and vanity of the ſophiſt appear too much in his writings in abſtract philoſophy, yet in natural hiſtory the fidelity of his narrations ſeems to be equal to his induſtry; and he always diſtinguiſhes between what he knew and what he had by report. And even in abſtract philoſophy, it would be unfair to impute to Ariſtotle all the faults, all the obſcurities, and all the contradictions that are to be found in his writings. The greateſt part, and perhaps the beſt part, of his writings is loſt. There is reaſon to doubt whether ſome of thoſe we aſcribe to him be really his; and whether what are his be not much vitiated and interpolated. Theſe ſuſpicions are juſtified by the fate of Ariſtotle's writings, which is judiciouſly related, from the beſt autho⯑rities, in Bayle's dictionary, under the article Tyrannion, to which I refer.
[194] His books in logic which remain, are, 1. One book of the Categories. 2. One of Interpretati⯑on. 3. Firſt Analytics, two books. 4. Laſt Analytics, two books. 5. Topics, eight books. 6. Of Sophiſms, one book. Diogenes Laertius mentions many others that are loſt. Thoſe I have mentioned have commonly been publiſhed toge⯑ther, under the name of Ariſtotle's Organon, or his Logic; and for many ages, Porphyry's Intro⯑duction to the Categories has been prefixed to them.
In this Introduction, which is addreſſed to Chryſoarius, the author obſerves, That in order to underſtand Ariſtotle's doctrine concerning the categories, it is neceſſary to know what a genus is, what a ſpecies, what a ſpecific difference, what a property, and what an accident; that the know⯑ledge of theſe is alſo very uſeful in definition, in diviſion, and even in demonſtration: therefore he propoſes, in this little tract, to deliver ſhortly and ſimply the doctrine of the ancients, and chiefly of the Peripatetics, concerning theſe five predica⯑bles; avoiding the more intricate queſtions con⯑cerning them; ſuch as, Whether genera and ſpe⯑cies do really exiſt in nature? or, Whether they are only conceptions of the human mind? If they exiſt in nature, Whether they are corporeal or incorporeal? and, Whether they are inherent in the objects of ſenſe, or disjoined from them? Theſe, he ſays, are very difficult queſtions, and require accurate diſcuſſion; but that he is not to meddle with them.
After this preface, he explains very minutely each of the five words above mentioned, divides [195] and ſubdivides each of them, and then purſues all the agreements and differences between one and another through ſixteen chapters.
The book begins with an explication of what is meant by univocal words, what by equivocal, and what by denominative. Then it is obſerved, that what we ſay is either ſimple, without com⯑poſition or ſtructure, as man, horſe; or it has compoſition and ſtructure, as a man fights, the horſe runs. Next comes a diſtinction between a ſubject of predication; that is, a ſubject of which any thing is aſtirmed or denied, and a ſub⯑ject of inheſion. Theſe things are ſaid to be in⯑herent in a ſubject, which although they are not a part of the ſubject, cannot poſſibly exiſt with⯑out it, as figure in the thing figured. Of things that are, ſays Ariſtotle, ſome may be predicated of a ſubject, but are in no ſubject; as, man may be predicated of James or John, but it is not in any ſubject. Some again are in a ſubject, but can be predicated of no ſubject. Thus, my knowledge in grammar is in me as its ſubject, but it can be predicated of no ſubject; becauſe it is an individual thing. Some are both in a ſub⯑ject, and may be predicated of a ſubject, as ſcience; which is in the mind as its ſubject, and may be predicated of geometry. Laſtly, Some things can neither be in a ſubject, nor be predica⯑ted of any ſubject. Such are all individual ſub⯑ſtances, which cannot be predicated, becauſe they are individuals; and cannot be in a ſubject, becauſe they are ſubſtances. After ſome other ſubtilties a⯑bout predicates and ſubjects, we come to the cate⯑gories themſelves; the things above mentioned be⯑ing [196] called by the ſchoolmen the antepraedicamenta. It may be obſerved, however, that notwithſtanding the diſtinction now explained, the being in a ſubject, and the being predicated truly of a ſubject, are in the Analytics uſed as ſynonymous phraſes; and this variation of ſtyle has led ſome perſons to think that the Categories were not wrote by Ariſtotle.
Things which may be expreſſed without com⯑poſition or ſtructure, are, ſays the author, redu⯑cible to the following heads. They are either ſubſtance, or quantity, or quality, or relatives, or place, or time, or having, or doing, or ſuffering. Theſe are the predicaments or categories. The firſt four are largely treated of in four chapters; the others are ſlightly paſſed over, as ſufficiently clear of themſelves. As a ſpecimen, I ſhall give a ſummary of what he ſays on the category of ſubſtance.
Subſtances are either primary, to wit, indivi⯑dual ſubſtances, or ſecondary, to wit, the gene⯑ra and ſpecies of ſubſtances. Primary ſubſtances neither are in a ſubject, nor can be predicated of a ſubject; but all other things that exiſt, either are in primary ſubſtances, or may be predicated of them. For whatever can be predicated of that which is in a ſubject, may alſo be predica⯑ted of the ſubject itſelf. Primary ſubſtances are more ſubſtances than the ſecondary; and of the ſecondary, the ſpecies is more a ſubſtance than the genus. If there were no primary, there could be no ſecondary ſubſtances.
The properties of ſubſtance are theſe: 1. No ſubſtance is capable of intenſion or remiſſion. 2. No ſubſtance can be in any other thing as its ſub⯑ject of inheſion. 3. No ſubſtance has a contra⯑ry; for one ſubſtance cannot be contrary to ano⯑ther; nor can there be contrariety between a ſubſtance and that which is no ſubſtance. 4. The [197] moſt remarkable property of ſubſtance, is, that one and the ſame ſubſtance may, by ſome change in itſelf, become the ſubject of things that are contrary. Thus, the ſame body may be at one time hot, at another cold.
Let this ſerve as a ſpecimen of Ariſtotle's man⯑ner of treating the categories. After them, we have ſome chapters, which the ſchoolmen call poſtpraedicamenta; wherein, firſt, the four kinds of oppoſition of terms are explained; to wit, re⯑lative, privative, of contrariely, and of contradic⯑tion. This is repeated in all ſyſtems of logic. Laſt of all we have diſtinctions of the four Greek words which anſwer to the Latin ones, prius, ſi⯑mul, motus, and habere.
We are to conſider, ſays Ariſtotle, what a noun is, what a verb, what affirmation, what negation, what ſpeech. Words are the ſigns of what paſſeth in the mind; writing is the ſign of words. The ſigns both of writing and of words are different in different nations, but the operati⯑ons of mind ſignified by them are the ſame. There are ſome operations of thought which are neither true nor falſe. Theſe are expreſſed by nouns or verbs ſingly, and without compoſition.
A noun is a ſound which by compact ſignifies ſomething without reſpect to time, and of which no part has ſignification by itſelf. The cries of beaſts may have a natural ſignification, but they are not nouns. We give that name only to ſounds which have their ſignification by compact. The caſes of a noun, as the genitive, dative, are not nouns. Non homo is not a noun, but, for diſtinction's ſake, may be called a nomen infinitum.
[198] A verb ſignifies ſomething by compact with re⯑lation to time. Thus, valet is a verb; but vale⯑tuds is a noun, becauſe its ſignification has no re⯑lation to time. It is only the preſent tenſe of the indicative that is properly called a verb; the o⯑ther tenſes and moods are variations of the verb. Non valet may be called a verbum infinitum.
Speech is ſound ſignificant by compact, of which ſome part is alſo ſignificant. And it is either enunciative, or not enunciative. Enunci⯑ative ſpeech is that which affirms or denies. As to ſpeech which is not enunciative, ſuch as a pray⯑er or wiſh, the conſideration of it belongs to ora⯑tory, or poetry. Every enunciative ſpeech muſt have a verb, or ſome variation of a verb. Affir⯑mation is the enunciation of one thing concerning another. Negation is the enunciation of one thing from another. Contradiction is an affirma⯑tion and negation that are oppoſite. This is a ſummary of the firſt ſix chapters.
The ſeventh and eighth treat of the various kinds of enunciations or propoſitions, univerſal, particular, indefinite, and ſingular; and of the various kinds of oppoſition in propoſitions, and the axioms concerning them. Theſe things are repeated in every ſyſtem of logic. In the ninth chapter he endeavours to prove, by a long meta⯑phyſical reaſoning, that propoſitions reſpecting future contingencies are not, determinately, ei⯑ther true or falſe; and that if they were, it would follow, that all things happen neceſſarily, and could not have been otherwiſe than as they are. The remaining chapters contain many mi⯑nute obſervations concerning the equipollency of propoſitions both pure and modal.
CHAP. II.
Remarks.
[199]THE writers on logic have borrowed their materials almoſt entirely from Ariſtotle's Organon, and Porphyry's Introduction. The Organon however was not wrote by Ariſtotle as one work. It comprehends various tracts, wrote without the view of making them parts of one whole, and afterwards thrown together by his edi⯑tors under one name on account of their affi⯑nity. Many of his books that are loſt would have made a part of the Organon, if they had been ſaved.
The three treatiſes of which we have given a brief account, are unconnected with each other, and with thoſe that follow. And although the firſt was undoubtedly compiled by Porphyry, and the two laſt probably by Ariſtotle, yet I conſider them as the venerable remains of a philoſophy more ancient than Ariſtotle. Archytas of Taren⯑tum, an eminent mathematician and philoſopher of the Pythagorean ſchool, is ſaid to have wrote upon the ten categories. And the five predicables probably had their origin in the ſame ſchool. Ariſtotle, though abundantly careful to do juſtice [200] to himſelf, does not claim the invention of either. And Porphyry, without aſcribing the latter to Ariſtotle, profeſſes only to deliver the doctrine of the ancients, and chiefly of the Peripatetics, con⯑cerning them.
The writers on logic have divided that ſci⯑ence into three parts; the firſt treating of ſimple apprehenſion, and of terms; the ſecond, of judgment, and of propoſitions; and the third, of reaſoning, and of ſyllogiſms. The materials of the firſt part are taken from Porphyry's Introduc⯑tion, and the Categories; and thoſe of the ſecond from the book of Interpretation.
A predicable, according to the grammatical form of the word, might ſeem to ſignify, what⯑ever may be predicated, that is, affirmed or de⯑nied, of ſome ſubject. And in this ſenſe every predicate would be a predicable. But the logici⯑ans give a different meaning to the word. They divide propoſitions into certain claſſes, according to the relation which the predicate of the propo⯑ſition bears to the ſubject. The firſt claſs is that wherein the predicate is the genus of the ſubject; as when we ſay, This is a triangle, Jupiter is a planet. In the ſecond claſs, the predicate is a ſpecies of the ſubject; as when we ſay, This triangle is right-angled. A third claſs is when the predicate is the ſpecific difference of the ſubject; as when we ſay, Every triangle has three ſides and three angles. A fourth when the predicate is a property of the ſubject; as when we ſay, The angles of every triangle are equal to two right an⯑gles. And a fifth claſs is when the predicate is ſomething accidental to the ſubject; as when we ſay, This triangle is neatly drawn.
Each of theſe claſſes comprehends a great va⯑riety of propoſitions, having different ſubjects, and different predicates; but in each claſs the re⯑lation [201] between the predicate and the ſubject is the ſame. Now it is to this relation that logicians have given the name of a predicable. Hence it is, that although the number of predicates be infinite, yet the number of predicables can be no greater than that of the different relations which may be in propoſitions between the predicate and the ſub⯑ject. And if all propoſitions belong to one or other of the five claſſes above mentioned, there can be but five predicables, to wit, genus, ſpecies, differentia, proprium, and accidens. Theſe might, with more propriety perhaps, have been called the five claſſes of predicates; but uſe has determined them to be called the five predicables.
It may alſo be obſerved, that as ſome objects of thought are individuals, ſuch as, Julius Caeſar, the city Rome; ſo others are common to many in⯑dividuals, as good, great, virtuous, vicious. Of this laſt kind are all things expreſſed by adjectives. Things common to many individuals were by the ancients called univerſals. All predicates are uni⯑verſals, for they all have the nature of adjec⯑tives; and, on the other hand, all univerſals may be predicates. On this account univerſals may be divided into the ſame claſſes as predicates; and as the five claſſes of predicates above mentioned have been called the five predicables, ſo by the ſame kind of phraſeology they have been called the five univerſals; although they may more properly be called the five claſſes of univer⯑ſals.
The doctrine of the five univerſals or predica⯑bles makes an eſſential part of every ſyſtem of lo⯑gic, and has been handed down without any change to this day. The very name of predicables ſhews, that the author of this diviſion, whoever he was, intended it as a complete enumeration of all the kinds of things that can be affirmed of any ſub⯑ject; [202] and ſo it has always been underſtood. So that it is implied in this diviſion, that all that can be affirmed of any thing whatſoever, is either the genus of the thing, or its ſpecies, or its ſpecific difference, or ſome property or accident belonging to it.
Burgerſdick, a very acute writer in logic, ſeems to have been aware, that ſtrong objections might be made to the five predicables, conſidered as a complete enumeration; but unwilling to allow any imperfection in this ancient diviſion, he en⯑deavours to reſtrain the meaning of the word predicable, ſo as to obviate objections. Thoſe things only, ſays he, are to be accounted predi⯑cables, which may be affirmed of many individu⯑als, truly, properly, and immediately. The con⯑ſequence of putting ſuch limitations upon the word predicable is, that in many propoſitions, perhaps in moſt, the predicate is not a predicable. But admitting all his limitations, the enumeration will ſtill be very incomplete: for of many things we may affirm truly, properly, and immediately, their exiſtence, their end, their cauſe, their effect, and various relations which they bear to other things. Theſe, and perhaps many more, are predicables in the ſtrict ſenſe of the word, no leſs than the five which have been ſo long famous.
Although Porphyry, and all ſubſequent writers, make the predicables to be, in number, five; yet Ariſtotle himſelf, in the beginning of the Topics, reduces them to four; and demonſtrates, that they can be no more. We ſhall give his demonſtration when we come to the Topics; and ſhall only here obſerve, that as Burgerſdick juſtifies the fivefold diviſion, by reſtraining the meaning of the word predicable; ſo Ariſtotle juſtifies the fourfold divi⯑ſion, [203] by enlarging the meaning of the words pro⯑perty and accident.
After all, I apprehend, that this ancient diviſion of predicables, with all its imperfections, will bear a compariſon with thoſe which have been ſubſtituted in its ſtead by the moſt celebrated mo⯑dern philoſophers.
Locke, in his Eſſay on the Human Underſtand⯑ing, having laid it down as a principle, That all our knowledge conſiſts in perceiving certain agree⯑ments and diſagreements between our ideas, re⯑duces theſe agreements and diſagreements to four heads: to wit, 1. Identity and Diverſity; 2. Re⯑lation; 3. Coexiſtence; 4. Real Exiſtencea. Here are four predicables given as a complete enumeration, and yet not one of the ancient pre⯑dicables is included in the number.
The author of the Treatiſe of Human Nature, proceeding upon the ſame principle, That all our knowledge is only a perception of the relations of our ideas, obſerves, ‘"That it may perhaps be eſteemed an endleſs taſk, to enumerate all thoſe qualities which admit of compariſon, and by which the ideas of philoſophical relation are produced: but if we diligently conſider them, we ſhall find, that without difficulty they may be compriſed under ſeven general heads: 1. Reſemblance; 2. Identity; 3. Relations of Space and Time; 4. Relations of Quantity and Number; 5. Degrees of Quality; 6. Contra⯑riety; 7. Cauſationb."’ Here again are ſeven predicables given as a complete enumerati⯑on, [204] wherein all the predicables of the ancients, as well as two of Locke's, are left out.
The ancients in their diviſion attended only to categorical propoſitions which have one ſub⯑ject and one predicate; and of theſe, only to ſuch as have a general term for their ſubject. The moderns, by their definition of knowledge, have been led to attend only to relative propo⯑ſitions, which expreſs a relation between two ſubjects, and thoſe ſubjects they ſuppoſe to be always ideas.
The intention of the categories or predicaments is, to muſter every object of human apprehenſion under ten heads: for the categories are given as a complete enumeration of every thing which can be expreſſed without compoſition and ſtructure; that is, of every thing which can be either the ſubject or the predicate of a propoſition. So that as every ſoldier belongs to ſome company, and every company to ſome regiment; in like manner every thing that can be the object of human thought, has its place in one or other of the ten categories; and by dividing and ſubdividing properly the ſe⯑veral categories, all the notions that enter into the human mind may be muſtered in rank and file, like an army in the day of battle.
The perfection of the diviſion of categories into ten heads, has been ſtrenuouſly defended by the followers of Ariſtotle, as well as that of the five predicables. They are indeed of kin to each other. They breathe the ſame ſpirit, and probab⯑ly had the ſame origin. By the one we are taught to marſhal every term that can enter into [205] a propoſition, either as ſubject or predicate; and by the other, we are taught all the poſſible relations which the ſubject can have to the pre⯑dicate. Thus, the whole furniture of the hu⯑man mind is preſented to us at one view, and contracted as it were, into a nut-ſhell. To attempt, in ſo early a period, a methodical de⯑lineation of the vaſt region of human know⯑ledge, actual and poſſible, and to point out the limits of every diſtrict, was indeed magnani⯑mous in a high degree, and deſerves our admirati⯑on, while we lament that the human powers are unequal to ſo bold a flight.
A regular diſtribution of things under pro⯑per claſſes or heads, is without doubt, a great help both to memory and judgment. And as the philoſopher's province includes all things human and divine that can be objects of en⯑quiry, he is naturally led to attempt ſome ge⯑neral diviſion, like that of the categories. And the invention of a diviſion of this kind, which the ſpeculative part of mankind acquieſced in for two thouſand years, marks a ſuperiority of genius in the inventer, whoever he was. Nor does it appear, that the general diviſions which, ſince the decline of the Peripatetic philoſophy, have been ſubſtituted in place of the ten catego⯑ries, are more perfect.
Locke has reduced all things to three catego⯑ries; to wit, ſubſtances, modes, and relations. In this diviſion, time, ſpace, and number, three great objects of human thought, are omitted.
The author of the Treatiſe of Human Nature has reduced all things to two categories; to wit, ideas, and impreſſions: a diviſion which is very well adapted to his ſyſtem; and which puts me in mind of another made by an excellent mathe⯑matician in a printed theſis I have ſeen. In it the [206] author, after a ſevere cenſure of the ten catego⯑ries of the Peripatetics, maintains, that there nei⯑ther are nor can be more than two categories of things; to wit, data, and quaeſita.
There are two ends that may be propoſed by ſuch diviſions The firſt is, to methodize or di⯑geſt in order what a man actually knows. This is neither unimportant nor impracticable; and in proportion to the ſolidity and accuracy of a man's judgment, his diviſions of things which he knows, will be elegant and uſeful. The ſame ſubject may admit, and even require, various diviſions, according to the different points of view from which we contemplate it: nor does it follow, that becauſe one diviſion is good, therefore ano⯑ther is naught. To be acquainted with the di⯑viſions of the logicians and metaphyſicians, with⯑out a ſuperſtitious attachment to them, may be of uſe in dividing the ſame ſubjects, or even thoſe of a different nature. Thus, Quintilian borrows from the ten categories his diviſion of the topics of rhetorical argumentation. Of all me⯑thods of arrangement, the moſt antiphiloſophical ſeems to be the invention of this age; I mean, the arranging the arts and ſciences by the letters of the alphabet, in dictionaries and encyclope⯑dies. With theſe authors the categories are, A, B, C, &c.
Another end commonly propoſed by ſuch divi⯑ſions, but very rarely attained, is, to exhauſt the ſubject divided; ſo that nothing that belongs to it ſhall be omitted. It is one of the general rules of diviſion in all ſyſtems of logic, That the divi⯑ſion ſhould be adequate to the ſubject divided: a good rule, without doubt; but very often be⯑yond the reach of human power. To make a perfect diviſion, a man muſt have a perfect com⯑prehenſion of the whole ſubject at one view. [207] When our knowledge of the ſubject is imperfect, any diviſion we can make of it, muſt be like the firſt ſketch of a painter, to be extended, con⯑tracted, or mended, as the ſubject ſhall be found to require. Yet nothing is more common, not only among the ancient, but even among modern philoſophers, than to draw from their incomplete diviſions, concluſions which ſuppoſe them to be perfect.
A diviſion is a repoſitory which the philoſo⯑pher frames for holding his ware in convenient order. The philoſopher maintains, that ſuch or ſuch a thing is not good ware, becauſe there is no place in his ware-room that fits it. We are apt to yield to this argument in philoſophy, but it would appear ridiculous in any other traffic.
Peter Ramus, who had the ſpirit of a refor⯑mer in philoſophy, and who had a force of ge⯑nius ſufficient to ſhake the Ariſtotelian fabric in many parts, but inſufficient to erect any thing more ſolid in its place, tried to remedy the im⯑perfection of philoſophical diviſions, by introdu⯑cing a new manner of dividing. His diviſions always conſiſted of two members, one of which was contradictory of the other; as if one ſhould divide England into Middleſex and what is not Middleſex. It is evident that theſe two members comprehend all England: for the logicians ob⯑ſerve, that a term, along with its contradictory, comprehend all things. In the ſame manner, we may divide what is not Middleſex into Kent and what is not Kent. Thus one may go on by di⯑viſions and ſubdiviſions that are abſolutely com⯑plete. This example may ſerve to give an idea of the ſpirit of Ramean diviſions, which were in no ſmall reputation about two hundred years ago.
[208] Ariſtotle was not ignorant of this kind of divi⯑ſion. But he uſed it only as a touchſtone to prove by induction the perfection of ſome other diviſion, which indeed is the beſt uſe that can be made of it; when applied to the common pur⯑poſe of diviſion, it is both inelegant, and bur⯑denſome to the memory; and, after it has put one out of breath by endleſs ſubdiviſions, there is ſtill a negative term left behind, which ſhows that you are no nearer the end of your journey than when you began.
Until ſome more effectual remedy be found for the imperfection of diviſions, I beg leave to pro⯑poſe one more ſimple than that of Ramus. It is this: When you meet with a diviſion of any ſubject imperfectly comprehended, add to the laſt member an et caetera. That this et caetera makes the diviſion complete, is undeniable; and there⯑fore it ought to hold its place as a member, and to be always underſtood, whether expreſſed or not, until clear and poſitive proof be brought, that the diviſion is complete without it. And this ſame et caetera ſhall be the repoſitory of all mem⯑bers that ſhall in any future time ſhew a good and valid right to a property in the ſubject.
Having ſaid ſo much of logical diviſions, we ſhall next make ſome remarks upon diſtinctions.
Since the philoſophy of Ariſtotle fell into diſ⯑repute, it has been a common topic of wit and raillery, to inveigh againſt metaphyſical diſtinc⯑tions. Indeed the abuſe of them in the ſchola⯑ſtic ages, ſeems to juſtify a general prejudice againſt them: and ſhallow thinkers and writers have good reaſon to be jealous of diſtinctions, [209] becauſe they make ſad work when applied to their flimſy compoſitions. But every man of true judgment, while he condemns diſtinctions that have no foundation in the nature of things, muſt perceive, that indiſcriminately to decry diſtinc⯑tions, is, to renounce all pretenſions to juſt rea⯑ſoning: for as falſe reaſoning commonly proceeds from confounding things that are different, ſo without diſtinguiſhing ſuch things, it is impoſſi⯑ble to avoid error, or detect ſophiſtry. The au⯑thority of Aquinas, or Suarez, or even of Ari⯑ſtotle, can neither ſtamp a real value upon diſ⯑tinctions of baſe metal, nor ought it to hinder the currency of thoſe that have intrinſic value.
Some diſtinctions are verbal, others are real. The firſt kind diſtinguiſh the various meanings of a word; ſome of which may be proper, others metaphorical. Diſtinctions of this kind make a part of the grammar of a language, and are of⯑ten abſurd when tranſlated into another language. Real diſtinctions are equally good in all lan⯑guages, and ſuffer no hurt by tranſlation. They diſtinguiſh the different ſpecies contained under ſome general notion, or the different parts con⯑tained in one whole.
Many of Ariſtotle's diſtinctions are verbal merely; and therefore more proper materials for a dictionary of the Greek language than for a philoſophical treatiſe. At leaſt they ought never to have been tranſlated into other languages, when the idiom of the language will not juſtify them: for this is to adulterate the language, to introduce foreign idioms into it without neceſſity or uſe, and to make it ambiguous where it was not. The diſtinctions in the end of the Catego⯑ries of the four words prius, ſimul, motus, and habere, are all verbal.
[210] The modes or ſpecies of prius, according to Ariſtotle, are five. One thing may be prior to another; firſt, in point of time; ſecondly, in point of dignity; thirdly, in point of order; and ſo forth. The modes of ſimul are only three. It ſeems this word was not uſed in the Greek with ſo great latitude as the other, although they are rela⯑tive terms.
The modes or ſpecies of motion he makes to be fix, to wit, generation, corruption, in⯑creaſe, decreaſe, alteration, and change of place.
The modes or ſpecies of having are eight. 1. Having a quality or habit, as having wiſdom. 2. Having quantity or magnitude. 3. Having things adjacent, as having a ſword. 4. Having things as parts, as having hands or feet. 5. Ha⯑ving in a part or on a part, as having a ring on one's finger. 6. Containing, as a caſk is ſaid to have wine. 7. Poſſeſſing, as having lands or houſes. 8. Having a wife.
Another diſtinction of this kind is Ariſtotle's diſtinction of cauſes; of which he makes four kinds, efficient, material, formal, and final. Theſe diſtinctions may deſerve a place in a dictionary of the Greek language; but in Eng⯑liſh or Latin they adulterate the language. Yet ſo fond were the ſchoolmen of diſtinctions of this kind, that they added to Ariſtotle's enu⯑meration, an impulſive cauſe, an exemplary cauſe, and I do not know how many more. We ſeem to have adopted into Engliſh a final cauſe; but it is merely a term of art, borrow⯑ed from the Peripatetic philoſophy, without neceſſity or uſe: for the Engliſh word end is as good as final cauſe, though not ſo long nor ſo learned.
It remains that we make ſome remarks on Ariſtotle's definitions, which have expoſed him to much cenſure and ridicule. Yet I think it muſt be allowed, that in things which need de⯑finition, and admit of it, his definitions are com⯑monly judicious and accurate; and had he at⯑tempted to define ſuch things only, his enemies had wanted great matter of triumph. I believe it may likewiſe be ſaid in his favour, that until Locke's eſſay was wrote, there was nothing of importance delivered by philoſophers with regard to definition, beyond what Ariſtotle has ſaid upon that ſubject.
He conſiders a definition as a ſpeech declaring what a thing is. Every thing eſſential to the thing defined, and nothing more, muſt be con⯑tained in the definition. Now the eſſence of a thing conſiſts of theſe two parts: Firſt, What is common to it with other things of the ſame kind; and, ſecondly, What diſtinguiſhes it from other things of the ſame kind. The firſt is called the genus of the thing, the ſecond its ſpecific dif⯑ference. The definition therefore conſiſts of theſe two parts. And for finding them, we muſt have recourſe to the ten categories; in one or other of which every thing in nature is to be found. Each category is a genus, and is divided into ſo many ſpecies, which are diſtinguiſhed by their ſpecific differences. Each of theſe ſpecies is again ſubdivided into ſo many ſpecies, with regard to which it is a genius. This diviſion and ſubdi⯑viſion continues until we come to the loweſt ſpe⯑cies, which can only be divided into individuals, diſtinguiſhed from one another, not by any ſpeci⯑fic [212] difference, but by accidental differences of time, place, and other circumſtances.
The category itſelf being the higheſt genus, is in no reſpect a ſpecies, and the loweſt ſpecies is in no reſpect a genus; but every intermedi⯑ate order is a genus compared with thoſe that are below it, and a ſpecies compared with thoſe above it. To find the definition of any thing, therefore, you muſt take the genus which is im⯑mediately above its place in the category, and the ſpecific difference, by which it is diſtinguiſhed from other ſpecies of the ſame genus. Theſe two make a perfect definition. This I take to be the ſubſtance of Ariſtotle's ſyſtem; and pro⯑bably the ſyſtem of the Pythagorean ſchool be⯑fore Ariſtotle, concerning definition.
But notwithſtanding the ſpecious appearance of this ſyſtem, it has its defects. Not to repeat what was before ſaid, of the imperfection of the diviſion of things into ten categories, the ſubdi⯑viſions of each category are no leſs imperfect. Ariſtotle has given ſome ſubdiviſions of a few of them; and as far as he goes, his followers pretty unanimouſly take the ſame road. But when they attempt to go farther, they take very different roads. It is evident, that if the ſeries of each category could be completed, and the diviſion of things into categories could be made perfect, ſtill the higheſt genus in each category could not be defined, becauſe it is not a ſpecies; nor could individuals be defined, becauſe they have no ſpecific difference. There are alſo many ſpe⯑cies of things, whoſe ſpecific difference cannot be expreſſed in language, even when it is evi⯑dent to ſenſe, or to the underſtanding. Thus, green, red, and blue, are very diſtinct ſpecies of colour; but who can expreſs in words where⯑in green differs from red or blue?
[213] Without borrowing light from the ancient ſyſtem, we may perceive, that every definition muſt conſiſt of words that need no definition; and that to define the common words of a lan⯑guage that have no ambiguity, is trifling, if it could be done; the only uſe of a definition being to give a clear and adequate conception of the meaning of a word.
The logicians indeed diſtinguiſh between the definition of a word, and the definition of a thing; conſidering the former as the mean office of a lexicographer, but the laſt as the grand work of a philoſopher. But what they have ſaid about the definition of a thing, if it has a mean⯑ing, is beyond my comprehenſion. All the rules of definition agree to the definition of a word: and if they mean by the definition of a thing, the giving an adequate conception of the nature and eſſence of any thing that exiſts; this is impoſſible, and is the vain boaſt of men unconſcious of the weakneſs of human under⯑ſtanding.
The works of God are all imperfectly known by us. We ſee their outſide, or perhaps we diſcover ſome of their qualities and relations, by obſervation and experiment, aſſiſted by reaſon⯑ing; but we can give no definition of the mean⯑eſt of them which comprehends its real eſſence. It is juſtly obſerved by Locke, that nominal eſ⯑ſences only, which are the creatures of our own minds, are perfectly comprehended by us, or can be properly defined; and even of theſe there are many too ſimple in their nature to admit of definition. When we cannot give preciſion to our notions by a definition, we muſt endeavour to do it by attentive reflection upon them, by obſerving minutely their agreements and differ⯑ences, and eſpecially by a right underſtanding of [214] the powers of our own minds by which ſuch notions are formed.
The principles laid down by Locke with re⯑gard to definition, and with regard to the abuſe of words, carry conviction along with them; and I take them to be one of the moſt important improvements made in logic ſince the days of Ariſtotle; not ſo much becauſe they enlarge our knowledge, as becauſe they make us ſenſible of our ignorance, and ſhew that a great part of what ſpeculative men have admired as profound philoſophy, is only a darkening of knowledge by words without underſtanding.
If Ariſtotle had underſtood thoſe principles, many of his definitions, which furniſh matter of triumph to his enemies, had never ſeen the light: let us impute them to the times rather than to the man. The ſublime Plato, it is ſaid, thought it neceſſary to have the definition of a man, and could find none better than Animal implume bipes; upon which Diogenes ſent to his ſchool a cock with his feathers plucked off, deſiring to know whether it was a man or not.
The few hints contained in the beginning of the book concerning Interpretation, relating to the ſtructure of ſpeech, have been left out on treati⯑ſes of logic, as belonging rather to grammar; yet I apprehend this is a rich field of philoſophical ſpeculation. Language being the expreſs image of human thought, the analyſis of the one muſt correſpond to that of the other. Nouns adjective and ſubſtantive, verbs active and paſſive, with their various moods, tenſes, and perſons, muſt be expreſſive of a like variety in the modes of [215] thought. Things which are diſtinguiſhed in all languages, ſuch as ſubſtance and quality, action and paſſion, cauſe and effect, muſt be diſtinguiſh⯑ed by the natural powers of the human mind. The philoſophy of grammar, and that of the hu⯑man underſtanding, are more nearly allied than is commonly imagined.
The ſtructure of language was purſued to a conſiderable extent, by the ancient commentators upon this book of Ariſtotle. Their ſpeculations upon this ſubject, which are neither the leaſt in⯑genious nor the leaſt uſeful part of the Peripate⯑tic philoſophy, were neglected for many ages, and lay buried in ancient manuſcripts, or in books little known, till they were lately brought to light by the learned Mr Harris in his Hermes.
The definitions given by Ariſtotle, of a noun, of a verb, and of ſpeech, will hardly bear exa⯑mination. It is eaſy in practice to diſtinguiſh the various parts of ſpeech; but very diffi⯑cult, if at all poſſible, to give accurate definiti⯑ons of them.
He obſerves juſtly, that beſides that kind of ſpeech called a propoſition, which is always either true or falſe, there are other kinds which are nei⯑ther true nor falſe; ſuch as, a prayer, or wiſh; to which we may add, a queſtion, a command, a promiſe, a contract, and many others. Theſe Ariſtotle pronounces to have nothing to do with his ſubject, and remits them to oratory, or poe⯑try; and ſo they have remained baniſhed from the regions of philoſophy to this day: yet I appre⯑hend, that an analyſis of ſuch ſpeeches, and of the operations of mind which they expreſs, would be of real uſe, and perhaps would diſcover how imperfect an enumeration the logicians have gi⯑ven of the powers of human underſtanding when [216] they reduce them to ſimple apprehenſion, judg⯑ment, and reaſoning.
Mathematicians uſe the word propoſition in a larger ſenſe than logicians. A problem is called a propoſition in mathematics, but in logic it is not a propoſition: it is one of thoſe ſpeeches which are not enunciative, and which Ariſtotle remits to oratory or poetry.
A propoſition, according to Ariſtotle, is a ſpeech wherein one thing is affirmed or denied of another. Hence it is eaſy to diſtinguiſh the thing affirmed or denied, which is called the predicate, from the thing of which it is affirmed or denied, which is called the ſubject; and theſe two are called the terms of the propoſition. Hence likewiſe it ap⯑pears, that propoſitions are either affirmative or negative; and this is called their quality. All af⯑firmative propoſitions have the ſame quality, ſo likewiſe have all the negative; but an affirmative and a negative are contrary in their quality.
When the ſubject of a propoſition is a general term, the predicate is affirmed or denied, either of the whole, or of a part. Hence propoſitions are diſtinguiſhed into univerſal and particular. All men are mortal, is an univerſal propoſition; Some men are learned, is a particular, and this is called the quantity of the propoſition. All univer⯑ſal propoſitions agree in quantity, as alſo all par⯑ticular: while an univerſal and a particular are ſaid to differ in quantity. A propoſition is called indefinite, when there is no mark either of uni⯑verſality or particularity annexed to the ſubject: thus, Man is of few days, is an indefinite pro⯑poſition; but it muſt be underſtood either as uni⯑verſal or as particular, and therefore is not a [217] third ſpecies, but by interpretation is brought un⯑der one of the other two.
There are alſo ſingular propoſitions, which have not a general term but an individual for their ſubject; as, Alexander was a great conque⯑ror. Theſe are conſidered by logicians as uni⯑verſal, becauſe, the ſubject being indiviſible, the predicate is affirmed or denied of the whole, and not of a part only. Thus all propoſitions, with regard to quality, are either affirmative or nega⯑tive; and with regard to quantity, are univerſal or particular; and taking in both quantity and quality, they are univerſal affirmatives, or uni⯑verſal negatives, or particular affirmatives, or particular negatives. Theſe four kinds, after the days of Ariſtotle, came to be named by the names of the four firſt vowels, A, E, I, O, according to the following diſtich:
When the young logician is thus far inſtructed in the nature of propoſitions, he is apt to think there is no difficulty in analyſing any propoſition, and ſhewing its ſubject and predicate, its quantity and quality; and indeed, unleſs he can do this, he will be unable to apply the rules of logic to uſe. Yet he will find, there are ſome difficulties in this analyſis, which are overlooked by Ariſtotle altogether; and although they are ſometimes touched, they are not removed by his followers. For, 1. There are propoſitions in which it is difficult to find a ſubject and a predicate; as in theſe, It rains, It ſnows. 2. In ſome propoſiti⯑ons either term may be made a ſubject or the predicate as you like beſt; as in this, Virtue is the [218] road to happineſs. 3. The ſame example may ſerve to ſhew, that it is ſometimes difficult to ſay, whether a propoſition be univerſal or particular. 4. The quality of ſome propoſitions is ſo dubious, that logicians have never been able to agree whether they be affirmative or negative; as in this propoſition, Whatever is inſentient is not an animal. 5. As there is one claſs of propoſitions which have only two terms, to wit, one ſubject and one predicate, which are called categorical propoſitions; ſo there are many claſſes that have more than two terms. What Ariſtotle delivers in this book is applicable only to categorical propoſiti⯑ons; and to them only the rules concerning the con⯑verſion of propoſitions, and concerning the figures and modes of ſyllogiſms, are accommodated. The ſubſequent writers of logic have taken notice of ſome of the many claſſes of complex propoſitions, and have given rules adapted to them; but find⯑ing this work endleſs, they have left us to manage the reſt by the rules of common ſenſe.
CHAP. III.
Account of the Firſt Analytics.
[219]IN attempting to give ſome account of the Analytics and of the Topics of Ariſtotle, in⯑genuity requires me to confeſs, that though I have often purpoſed to read the whole with care, and to underſtand what is intelligible, yet my courage and patience always failed before I had done. Why ſhould I throw away ſo much time and painful attention upon a thing of ſo little real uſe? If I had lived in thoſe ages when the know⯑ledge of Ariſtotle's Organon intitled a man to the higheſt rank in philoſophy, ambition might have induced me to employ upon it ſome years painful ſtudy; and leſs, I conceive, would not be ſuffi⯑cient. Such reflections as theſe, always got the better of my reſolution, when the firſt ardor be⯑gan to cool. All I can ſay is, that I have read ſome parts of the different books with care, ſome ſlightly, and ſome perhaps not at all. I have glanced over the whole often, and when any thing attracted my attention, have dipped into it till my appetite was ſatisfied. Of all reading [220] it is the moſt dry and the moſt painful, employ⯑ing an infinite labour of demonſtration, about things of the moſt abſtract nature, delivered in a laconic ſtyle, and often, I think, with affected obſcurity; and all to prove general propoſitions, which when applied to particular inſtances appear ſelf-evident.
There is probably but little in the Categories, or in the book of Interpretation, which Ariſtotle could claim as his own invention: but the whole theory of ſyllogiſms he claims as his own, and as the fruit of much time and labour. And indeed it is a ſtately fabrick, a monument of a great genius, which we could wiſh to have been more uſefully employed. There muſt be ſomething however adapted to pleaſe the human underſtand⯑ing, or to flatter human pride, in a work which occupied men of ſpeculation for more than a thouſand years. Theſe books are called Analy⯑tics, becauſe the intention of them is to reſolve all reaſoning into its ſimple ingredients.
The firſt book of the Firſt Analitics, conſiſt⯑ing of forty-ſix chapters, may be divided into four parts; the firſt treating of the converſion of propoſitions; the ſecond, of the ſtructure of ſyl⯑logiſms in all the different figures and modes; the third, of the invention of a middle term; and the laſt, of the reſolution of ſyllogiſms. We ſhall give a brief account of each.
To convert a propoſition, is to infer from it another propoſition, whoſe ſubject is the predi⯑cate of the firſt, and whoſe predicate is the ſub⯑ject of the firſt. This is reduced by Ariſtotle to three rules. 1. An univerſal negative may be converted into an univerſal negative: thus, No man is a quadruped; therefore, No quadruped is a man. 2. An univerſal affirmative can be con⯑verted only into a particular affirmative: thus, [221] All men are mortal; therefore, Some mortal beings are men. 3. A particular affirmative may be con⯑verted into a particular affirmative: as, Some men are juſt; therefore, Some juſt perſons are men. When a propoſition may be converted without changing its quantity, this is called ſimple converſion; but when the quantity is diminiſhed, as in the univerſal affirmative, it is called con⯑verſion per accidens.
There is another kind of converſion, omitted in this place by Ariſtotle, but ſupplied by his followers, called converſion by contrapoſition, in which the term which is contradictory to the pre⯑dicate is put for the ſubject, and the quality of the propoſition is changed; as, All animals are ſentient; therefore, What is inſentient is not an animal. A fourth rule of converſion therefore is, That an univerſal affirmative, and a particular negative, may be converted by contrapoſition.
A ſyllogiſm is an argument, or reaſoning, con⯑ſiſting of three propoſitions, the laſt of which, called the concluſion, is inferred from the two pre⯑ceding, which are called the premiſes. The con⯑cluſion having two terms, a ſubject and a predi⯑cate, its predicate is called the major term, and its ſubject the minor term. In order to prove the concluſion, each of its terms is in the pre⯑miſes compared with a third term, called the middle term. By this means one of the premiſes will have for its two terms the major term and the middle term; and this premiſe is called the major premiſe, or the major propoſition of the ſyllogiſm. The other premiſe muſt have for its [222] two terms the minor term and the middle term, and it is called the minor propoſition. Thus the ſyllogiſm conſiſts of three propoſitions, diſtin⯑guiſhed by the names of the major, the minor, and the concluſion: and although each of theſe has two terms, a ſubject and a predicate, yet there are only three different terms in all. The major term is always the predicate of the con⯑cluſion, and is alſo either the ſubject or predicate of the major propoſition. The minor term is al⯑ways the ſubject of the concluſion, and is alſo either the ſubject or predicate of the minor pro⯑poſition. The middle term never enters into the concluſion, but ſtands in both premiſes, ei⯑ther in the poſition of ſubject or of predicate.
According to the various poſitions which the middle term may have in the premiſes, ſyllogiſms are ſaid to be of various figures. Now all the poſſible poſitions of the middle term are only four: for, firſt, it may be the ſubject of the major propoſition, and the predicate of the mi⯑nor, and then the ſyllogiſm is of the firſt fi⯑gure; or it may be the predicate of both pre⯑miſes, and then the ſyllogiſm is of the ſecond fi⯑gure; or it may be the ſubject of both, which makes a ſyllogiſm of the third figure; or it may be the predicate of the major propoſition, and the ſubject of the minor, which makes the fourth figure. Ariſtotle takes no notice of the fourth figure. It was added by the famous Galen, and is often called the Galenical figure.
There is another diviſion of ſyllogiſms accord⯑ing to their modes. The mode of a ſyllogiſm is determined by the quality and quantity of the propoſitions of which it conſiſts. Each of the three propoſitions muſt be either an univerſal af⯑firmative, or an univerſal negative, or a parti⯑cular affirmative, or a particular negative. Theſe [223] four kinds of propoſitions, as was before obſerv⯑ed, have been named by the four vowels, A, E, I, O; by which means the mode of a ſyllogiſm is marked by any three of thoſe four vowels. Thus, A, A, A, denotes that mode in which the major, minor, and concluſion, are all uni⯑verſal affirmatives; E, A, E, denotes that mode in which the major and concluſion are univerſal negatives, and the minor is an univerſal affirma⯑tive.
To know all the poſſible modes of ſyllogiſm, we muſt find how many different combinations may be made of three out of the four vowels, and from the art of combination the number is found to be ſixty-four. So many poſſible modes there are in every figure, conſequently in the three figures of Ariſtotle there are one hundred and ninety-two, and in all the four figures two hundred and fifty-ſix.
Now the theory of ſyllogiſm requires, that we ſhew what are the particular modes in each fi⯑gure, which do, or do not, form a juſt and con⯑cluſive ſyllogiſm, that ſo the legitimate may be adopted, and the ſpurious rejected. This Ari⯑ſtotle has ſhewn in the firſt three figures, exa⯑mining all the modes one by one, and paſſing ſentence upon each; and from this examination he collects ſome rules which may aid the memory in diſtinguiſhing the falſe from the true, and point out the properties of each figure.
The firſt figure has only four legitimate modes. The major propoſition in this figure muſt be uni⯑verſal, and the minor affirmative; and it has this property, that it yields concluſions of all kinds, affirmative and negative, univerſal and par⯑ticular.
The ſecond figure has alſo four legitimate modes. Its major propoſition muſt be univerſal, [224] and one of the premiſes muſt be negative. It yields concluſions both univerſal and particular, but all negative.
The third figure has ſix legitimate modes. Its minor muſt always be affirmative; and it yields concluſions both affirmative and negative, but all particular.
Beſides the rules that are proper to each figure, Ariſtotle has given ſome that are common to all, by which the legitimacy of ſyllogiſms may be tried. Theſe may, I think, be reduced to five. 1. There muſt be only three terms in a ſyllogiſm. As each term occurs in two of the propoſitions, it muſt be preciſely the ſame in both: if it be not, the ſyllogiſm is ſaid to have four terms, which makes a vitious ſyllogiſm. 2. The middle term muſt be taken univerſally in one of the pre⯑miſes. 3. Both premiſes muſt not be particular propoſitions, nor both negative. 4. The con⯑cluſion muſt be particular, if either of the pre⯑miſes be particular; and negative, if either of the premiſes be negative. 5. No term can be taken univerſally in the concluſion, if it be not taken univerſally in the premiſes.
For underſtanding the ſecond and fifth of theſe rules, it is neceſſary to obſerve, that a term is ſaid to be taken univerſally, not only when it is the ſubject of an univerſal propoſition, but when it is the predicate of a negative propoſition; on the other hand, a term is ſaid to be taken par⯑ticularly, when it is either the ſubject of a par⯑ticular, or the predicate of an affirmative pro⯑poſition.
The third part of this book contains rules ge⯑neral and ſpecial for the invention of a middle term; and this the author conceives to be of great utility. The general rules amount to this, That you are to conſider well both terms of the propo⯑ſition to be proved; their definition, their pro⯑perties, the things which may be affirmed or de⯑nied of them, and thoſe of which they may be affirmed or denied: thoſe things collected together, are the materials from which your middle term is to be taken.
The ſpecial rules require you to conſider the quantity and quality of the propoſition to be proved, that you may diſcover in what mode and figure of ſyllogiſm the proof is to proceed. Then from the materials before collected, you muſt ſeek a middle term which has that relation to the ſub⯑ject and predicate of the propoſition to be prov⯑ed, which the nature of the ſyllogiſm requires. Thus, ſuppoſe the propoſition I would prove is an univerſal affirmative, I know by the rules of ſyl⯑logiſms, that there is only one legitimate mode in which an univerſal affirmative propoſition can be proved; and that is the firſt mode of the firſt figure. I know likewiſe, that in this mode both the premiſes muſt be univerſal affirmatives; and that the middle term muſt be the ſubject of the major, and the predicate of the minor. There⯑fore of the terms collected according to the ge⯑neral rule, I ſeek out one or more which have theſe two properties; firſt, That the predicate of the propoſition to be proved can be univerſally affirmed of it; and, ſecondly, That it can be univerſally affirmed of the ſubject of the propo⯑ſition [226] to be proved. Every term you can find which has thoſe two properties, will ſerve you as a middle term, but no other. In this way, the author gives ſpecial rules for all the various kinds of propoſitions to be proved; points out the va⯑rious modes in which they may be proved, and the properties which the middle term muſt have to make it fit for anſwering that end. And the rules are illuſtrated, or rather, in my opinion, pur⯑poſely darkened, by putting letters of the alphabet for the ſeveral terms.
The reſolution of ſyllogiſms requires no other principles but thoſe before laid down for conſtruct⯑ing them. However it is treated of largely, and rules laid down for reducing reaſoning to ſyl⯑logiſms, by ſupplying one of the premiſes when it is underſtood, by rectifying inverſions and putting the propoſitions in the proper order.
Here he ſpeaks alſo of hypothetical ſyllo⯑giſms; which, he acknowledges, cannot be re⯑ſolved into any of the figures, although there be many kinds of them which ought diligently to be obſerved; and which he promiſes to handle afterwards. But this promiſe is not fulfilled, as far as I know, in any of his works that are extant.
The ſecond book treats of the powers of ſyl⯑logiſms, and ſhows, in twenty-ſeven chapters, [227] how we may perform many feats by them, and what figures and modes are adapted to each. Thus, in ſome ſyllogiſms ſeveral diſtinct concluſions may be drawn from the ſame premiſes: in ſome, true concluſions may be drawn from falſe premi⯑ſes: in ſome, by aſſuming the concluſion and one premiſe, you may prove the other; you may turn a direct ſyllogiſm into one leading to an ab⯑ſurdity.
We have likewiſe precepts given in this book, both to the aſſailant in a ſyllogiſtical diſpute, how to carry on his attack with art, ſo as to obtain the victory; and to the defendant, how to keep the enemy at ſuch a diſtance as that he ſhall never be obliged to yield. From which we learn, that Ariſtotle introduced in his own ſchool, the practice of diſputing ſyllogiſtical⯑ly, inſtead of the rhetorical diſputations which the ſophiſts were wont to uſe in more ancient times.
CHAP. IV.
Remarks.
[228]WE have given a ſummary view of the theory of pure ſyllogiſms as delivered by Ariſtotle, a theory of which he claims the ſole invention. And I believe it will be difficult, in any ſcience, to find ſo large a ſyſtem of truths of ſo very abſtract and ſo general a nature, all fortified by demonſtration, and all invented and perfected by one man. It ſhows a force of ge⯑nius, and labour of inveſtigation, equal to the moſt arduous attempts. I ſhall now make ſome remarks upon it.
As to the converſion of propoſitions, the writers on logic commonly ſatisfy themſelves with illuſ⯑trating each of the rules by an example, con⯑ceiving them to be ſelf-evident when applied to particular caſes. But Ariſtotle has given demon⯑ſtrations of the rules he mentions. As a ſpeci⯑men, I ſhall give his demonſtration of the firſt rule. ‘"Let A B be an univerſal negative pro⯑poſition; I ſay, that if A is in no B, it will [229] follow that B is in no A. If you deny this conſequence, let B be in ſome A, for example, in C; then the firſt ſuppoſition will not be true; for C is of the B's."’ In this demon⯑ſtration, if I underſtand it, the third rule of con⯑verſion is aſſumed, that if B is in ſome A, then A muſt be in ſome B, which indeed is contrary to the firſt ſuppoſition. If the third rule be aſſumed for proof of the firſt, the proof of all the three goes round in a circle; for the ſecond and third rules are proved by the firſt. This is a fault in reaſoning which Ariſtotle condemns, and which I ſhould be very unwilling to charge him with, if I could find any better meaning in his demonſtra⯑tion. But it is indeed a fault very difficult to be avoided, when men attempt to prove things that are ſelf-evident.
The rules of converſion cannot be applied to all propoſitions, but only to thoſe that are cate⯑gorical; and we are left to the direction of com⯑mon ſenſe in the converſion of other propoſitions. To give an example: Alexander was the ſon of Philip; therefore Philip was the father of Alex⯑ander: A is greater than B; therefore B is leſs than A. Theſe are converſions which, as far as I know, do not fall within any rule in logic; nor do we find any loſs for want of a rule in ſuch caſes.
Even in the converſion of categorical propoſi⯑tions, it is not enough to tranſpoſe the ſubject and predicate. Both muſt undergo ſome change, in order to fit them for their new ſtation: for in every propoſition the ſubject muſt be a ſubſtan⯑tive, or have the force of a ſubſtantive; and the predicate muſt be an adjective, or have the force of an adjective. Hence it follows, that when the ſubject is an individual, the propo⯑ſition admits not of converſion. How for in⯑ſtance, [230] ſhall we convert this propoſition, God is omniſcient?
Theſe obſervations ſhow, that the doctrine of the converſion of propoſitions is not ſo complete as it appears. The rules are laid down without any limitation; yet they are fitted only to one claſs of propoſitions, to wit, the categorical; and of theſe only to ſuch as have a general term for their ſubject.
Although the logicians have enlarged the firſt and ſecond parts of logic, by explaining ſome technical words and diſtinctions which Ariſtotle had omitted, and by giving names to ſome kinds of propoſitions which he overlooks; yet in what concerns the theory of categorical ſyllogiſms, he is more full, more minute and particular, than any of them: ſo that they ſeem to have thought this capital part of the Organon rather redundant than deficient.
It is true, that Galen added a fourth figure to the three mentioned by Ariſtotle. But there is reaſon to think that Ariſtotle omitted the fourth figure, not through ignorance or inattention, but of deſign, as containing only ſome indirect modes, which, when properly expreſſed, fall into the firſt figure.
It is true alſo, that Peter Ramus, a profeſſed enemy of Ariſtotle, introduced ſome new modes that are adapted to ſingular propoſitions; and that Ariſtotle takes no notice of ſingular propoſitions, either in his rules of converſion, or in the modes of ſyllogiſm. But the friends of Ariſtotle have ſhewn, that this improvement of Ramus is more ſpecious than uſeful. Singular propoſitions have [231] the force of univerſal propoſitions, and are ſub⯑ject to the ſame rules. The definition given by Ariſtotle of an univerſal propoſition applies to them; and therefore he might think, that there was no occaſion to multiply the modes of ſyllogiſm upon their account.
Theſe attempts, therefore, ſhow rather incli⯑nation than power, to diſcover any material defect in Ariſtotle's theory.
The moſt valuable addition made to the theory of categorical ſyllogiſms, ſeems to be the inventi⯑on of thoſe technical names given to the legiti⯑mate modes, by which they may be eaſily remem⯑bered, and which have been compriſed in theſe barbarous verſes.
In theſe verſes, every legitimate mode belonging to the three figures has a name given to it, by which it may be diſtinguiſhed and remember⯑ed. And this name is ſo contrived as to de⯑note its nature: for the name has three vowels, which denote the kind of each of its propoſi⯑tions.
Thus, a ſyllogiſm in Bocardo muſt be made up of the propoſitions denoted by the three vowels, O, A, O; that is, its major and concluſion muſt be particular negative propoſitions, and its minor an univerſal affirmative; and being in the third figure, the middle term muſt be the ſubject of both premiſes.
This is the myſtery contained in the vowels of thoſe barbarous words. But there are other myſ⯑teries [232] contained in their conſonants: for by their means, a child may be taught to reduce any ſyl⯑logiſm of the ſecond or third figure to one of the firſt. So that the four modes of the firſt figure being directly proved to be concluſive, all the modes of the other two are proved at the ſame time, by means of this operation of re⯑duction. For the rules and manner of this reduction, and the different ſpecies of it, called oſtenſive and per impoſſible, I refer to the logi⯑cians, that I may not diſcloſe all their myſte⯑ries.
The invention contained in theſe verſes is ſo in⯑genious, and ſo great an adminicle to the dextrous management of ſyllogiſms, that I think it very probable that Ariſtotle had ſome contrivance of this kind, which was kept as one of the ſecret doctrines of his ſchool, and handed down by tra⯑dition, until ſome body brought it to light. This is offered only as a conjecture, leaving it to thoſe who are better acquainted with the moſt ancient commentators on the Analytics, either to refute or to confirm it.
We may obſerve, that Ariſtotle hardly ever gives examples of real ſyllogiſms to illuſtrate his rules. In demonſtrating the legitimate modes, he takes A, B, C, for the terms of the ſyllogiſm. Thus, the firſt mode of the firſt figure is demonſtrated by him in this manner. ‘"For,"’ ſays he, ‘"if A is attributed to every B, and B to every C, it fol⯑lows neceſſarily, that A may be attributed to eve⯑ry C."’ For diſproving the illegitimate modes, he uſes the ſame manner; with this difference, [233] that he commmonly for an example gives three real terms, ſuch as, bonum, habitus, prudentia; of which three terms you are to make up a ſyllogiſm of the figure and mode in queſtion, which will appear to be inconcluſive.
The commentators, and ſyſtematical writers in logic, have ſupplied this defect; and given us real examples of every legitimate mode in all the figures. This we muſt acknowledge to be chari⯑tably done, to aſſiſt the imagination in the concep⯑tion of matters ſo very abſtract; but whether it was prudently done for the honour of the art, may be doubted. I am afraid this was to unco⯑ver the nakedneſs of the theory; and has contri⯑buted much to bring it into contempt: for when one conſiders the ſilly and uninſtructive reaſonings that have been brought forth by this grand organ of ſcience, he can hardly forbear crying out, Parturiunt montes, et naſcitur ridiculus mus. Ma⯑ny of the writers of logic are acute and ingenious, and much practiſed in the ſyllogiſtical art; and there muſt be ſome reaſon why the examples they have given of ſyllogiſms are ſo lean.
We ſhall ſpeak of the reaſon afterwards; and ſhall now give a ſyllogiſm in each figure as an example
- No work of God is bad;
- The natural paſſions and appetites of men are the work of God;
- Therefore none of them is bad.
In this ſyllogiſm, the middle term, work of God, is the ſubject of the major and the predicate of the minor; ſo that the ſyllogiſm is of the firſt fi⯑gure. The mode is that called Celarent; the major and concluſion being both univerſal nega⯑tives, and the minor an univerſal affirmative. It agrees to the rules of the figure, as the major is univerſal, and the minor affirmative; it is alſo [234] agreeable to all the general rules; ſo that it main⯑tains its character in every trial. And to ſhow of what ductile materials ſyllogiſms are made, we may, by converting ſimply the major propo⯑ſition, reduce it to a good ſyllogiſm of the ſecond figure, and of the mode Ceſare, thus:
- Whatever is bad is not the work of God;
- All the natural paſſions and appetites of men are the work of God;
- Therefore they are not bad.
Another example:
- Every thing virtuous is praiſe-worthy;
- Some pleaſures are not praiſe-worthy;
- Therefore ſome pleaſures are not virtuous.
Here the middle term praiſe-worthy being the predicate of both premiſes, the ſyllogiſm is of the ſecond figure; and ſeeing it is made up of the propoſitions, A, O, O, the mode is Baroco. It will be found to agree both with the general and ſpecial rules: and it may be reduced into a good ſyllogiſm of the firſt figure upon converting the major by contrapoſition, thus:
- What is not praiſe-worthy is not virtuous:
- Some pleaſures are not praiſe-worthy;
- Therefore ſome pleaſures are not virtuous.
That this ſyllogiſm is concluſive, common ſenſe pronounces, and all logicians muſt allow; but it is ſomewhat unpliable to rules, and re⯑quires a little ſtraining to make it tally with them.
That it is of the firſt figure is beyond diſpute; but to what mode of that figure ſhall we refer it? This is a queſtion of ſome difficulty. For, in the firſt place, the premiſes ſeem to be both ne⯑gative, which contradicts the third general rule; and moreover, it is contrary to a ſpecial rule of the firſt figure, That the minor ſhould be nega⯑tive. Theſe are the difficulties to be removed.
[235] Some logicians think, that the two negative particles in the major are equivalent to an affir⯑mative; and that therefore the major propoſition, What is not praiſe-worthy, is not virtuous, is to be accounted an affirmative propoſition. This if granted, ſolves one difficulty; but the other re⯑mains. The moſt ingenious ſolution, therefore, is this: Let the middle term be not praiſe-wor⯑thy. Thus making the negative particle a part of the middle term, the ſyllogiſm ſtands thus:
- Whatever is not praiſe-worthy is not virtuous;
- Some pleaſures are not praiſe-worthy;
- Therefore ſome pleaſures are not virtuous.
By this analyſis, the major becomes an univerſal negative, the minor a particular affirmative, and the concluſion a particular negative, and ſo we have a juſt ſyllogiſm in Ferio.
We ſee, by this example, that the quality of propoſitions is not ſo invariable, but that, when occaſion requires, an affirmative may be degra⯑ded into a negative, or a negative exalted to an affirmative. Another example:
- All Africans are black;
- All Africans are men;
- Therefore ſome men are black.
This is of a third figure, and of the mode Darap⯑ti; and it may be reduced to Darii in the firſt figure, by converting the minor.
- All Africans are black;
- Some men are Africans;
- Therefore ſome men are black.
By this time I apprehend the reader has got as many examples of ſyllogiſms as will ſtay his ap⯑petite for that kind of entertainment.
Ariſtotle and his followers have thought it ne⯑ceſſary, in order to bring this theory of categori⯑cal ſyllogiſms to a ſcience, to demonſtrate, both that the fourteen authoriſed modes conclude juſt⯑ly, and that none of the reſt do. Let us now ſee how this has been executed.
As to the legitimate modes, Ariſtotle, and thoſe who follow him the moſt cloſely, demon⯑ſtrate the four modes of the firſt figure directly from an axiom called the Dictum de omni et nullo. The amount of the axiom is, That what is affir⯑med of a whole genus, may be affirmed of all the ſpe⯑cies and individuals belonging to the genus; and that what is denied of the whole genus, may be denied of its ſpecies and individuals. The four modes of the firſt figure are evidently included in this axiom. And as to the legitimate modes of the other figures, they are proved by reducing them to ſome mode of the firſt. Nor is there any other principle aſſumed in theſe reductions but the axioms concerning the converſion of propoſiti⯑ons, and in ſome caſes the axioms concerning the oppoſition of propoſitions.
As to the illegitimate modes, Ariſtotle has ta⯑ken the labour to try and condemn them one by one in all the three figures: but this is done in ſuch a manner that it is very painful to follow him. To give a ſpecimen. In order to prove, that thoſe modes of the firſt figure in which the major is particular, do not conclude, he proceeds thus: ‘"If A is or is not in ſome B, and B, in every C, no concluſion follows. Take for the terms in the affirmative caſe, good, habit, pru⯑dence, in the negative, good, habit, igno⯑rance."’ [237] This laconic ſtyle, the uſe of ſym⯑bols not familiar, and in place of giving an exam⯑ple, his leaving us to form one from three aſſign⯑ed terms, give ſuch embarraſſment to a reader, that he is like one reading a book of riddles.
Having thus aſcertained the true and falſe modes of a figure, he ſubjoins the particular rules of that figure, which ſeem to be deduced from the particular caſes before determined. The ge⯑neral rules come laſt of all, as a general corollary from what goes before.
I know not whether it is from a diffidence of Ariſtotle's demonſtrations, or from an apprehen⯑ſion of their obſcurity, or from a deſire of im⯑proving upon his method, that almoſt all the writers in logic I have met with, have inverted his order, beginning where he ends, and ending where he begins. They firſt demonſtrate the ge⯑neral rules, which belong to all the figures, from three axioms; then from the general rules and the nature of each figure, they demonſtrate the ſpecial rules of each figure. When this is done, no⯑thing remains but to apply theſe general and ſpecial rules, and to reject every mode which contradicts them.
This method has a very ſcientific appearance; and when we conſider, that by a few rules once demonſtrated, an hundred and ſeventy-eight falſe modes are deſtroyed at one blow, which Ari⯑ſtotle had the trouble to put to death one by one, it ſeems to be a great improvement. I have only one objection to the three axioms.
The three axioms are theſe: 1. Things which agree with the ſame third, agree with one ano⯑ther. 2. When one agrees with the third, and the other does not, they do not agree with one another. 3. When neither agrees with the third, you cannot thence conclude, either that they do, [238] or do not agree with one another. If theſe axi⯑oms are applied to mathematical quantities, to which they ſeem to relate when taken literally, they have all the evidence which an axiom ought to have: but the logicians apply them in an analogical ſenſe to things of another nature. In order, therefore, to judge whether they are tru⯑ly axioms, we ought to ſtrip them of their figu⯑rative dreſs, and to ſet them down in plain Eng⯑liſh, as the logicians underſtand them. They amount therefore to this. 1. If two things be affirmed of a third, or the third be affirmed of them; or if one be affirmed of the third, and the third affirmed of the other; then they may be affirmed one of the other. 2. If one is af⯑firmed of the third, or the third of it, and the other denied of the third, or the third of it, they may be denied one of the other. 3. If both are denied of the third, or the third of them; or if one is denied of the third, and the third denied of the other; nothing can be inferred.
When the three axioms are thus put in plain Engliſh, they ſeem not to have that degree of evidence which axioms ought to have; and if there is any defect of evidence in the axioms, this defect will be communicated to the whole edifice raiſed upon them.
It may even be ſuſpected, that an attempt, by any method, to demonſtrate, that a ſyllogiſm is concluſive, is an impropriety ſomewhat like that of attempting to demonſtrate an axiom. In a juſt ſyllogiſm, the connection between the pre⯑miſes and the concluſion is not only real, but im⯑mediate; ſo that no propoſition can come be⯑tween them to make their connection more appa⯑rent. The very intention of a ſyllogiſm is, to leave nothing to be ſupplied that is neceſſary to a complete demonſtration. Therefore a man of [239] common underſtanding, who has a perfect com⯑prehenſion of the premiſes, finds himſelf under a neceſſity of admitting the concluſion, ſuppoſing the premiſes to be true; and the concluſion is connected with the premiſes with all the force of intuitive evidence. In a word, an immediate concluſion ſeen in the premiſes, by the light of common ſenſe; and where that is wanting, no kind of reaſoning will ſupply its place.
The ſlow progreſs of uſeful knowledge, during the many ages in which the ſyllogiſtic art was moſt highly cultivated as the only guide to ſci⯑ence, and its quick progreſs ſince that art was diſ⯑uſed, ſuggeſt a preſumption againſt it; and this preſumption is ſtrengthened by the puerility of the examples which have always been brought to illuſtrate its rules.
The ancients ſeem to have had too high noti⯑ons, both of the force of the reaſoning power in man, and of the art of ſyllogiſm as its guide. Mere reaſoning can carry us but a very little way in moſt ſubjects. By obſervation, and experi⯑ments properly conducted, the ſtock of human knowledge may be enlarged without end; but the power of reaſoning alone, applied with vi⯑gour through a long life, would only carry a man round, like a horſe in a mill, who labours hard, but makes no progreſs. There is indeed an ex⯑ception to this obſervation in the mathematical ſciences. The relations of quantity are ſo vari⯑ous, and ſo ſuſceptible of exact menſuration, that long trains of accurate reaſoning on that ſubject may be formed, and concluſions drawn very re⯑mote [240] from the firſt principles. It is in this ſci⯑ence, and thoſe which depend upon it, that the power of reaſoning triumphs: in other matters its trophies are inconſiderable. If any man doubt this, let him produce, in any ſubject unconnec⯑ted with mathematics, a train of reaſoning of ſome length, leading to a concluſion, which with⯑out this train of reaſoning would never have been brought within human ſight. Every man ac⯑quainted with mathematics can produce thouſands of ſuch trains of reaſoning. I do not ſay, that none ſuch can be produced in other ſciences; but I believe they are few, and not eaſily found; and that if they are found, it will not be in ſub⯑jects that can be expreſſed by categorical propo⯑ſitions, to which alone the theory of figure and mode extends.
In matters to which that theory extends, a man of good ſenſe, who can diſtinguiſh things that differ, and avoid the ſnares of ambiguous words, and is moderately practiſed in ſuch mat⯑ters, ſees at once all that can be inferred from his premiſes; or finds, that there is but a very ſhort ſtep to the concluſion.
When the power of reaſoning is ſo feeble by nature, eſpecially in ſubjects to which this theo⯑ry can be applied, it would be unreaſonable to expect great effects from it. And hence we ſee the reaſon why the examples brought to illuſtrate it by the moſt ingenious logicians, have rather tended to bring it into contempt.
If it ſhould be thought, that the ſyllogiſtic art may be an uſeful engine in mathematics, in which pure reaſoning has ample ſcope: Firſt, It may be obſerved, That facts are unfavourable to this opinion: for it does not appear, that Euclid, or Apollonius, or Archimedes, or Hugens, or Newton, ever made the leaſt uſe of this art; and [241] I am even of opinion, that no uſe can be made of it in mathematics. I would not wiſh to advance this raſhly, ſince Ariſtotle has ſaid, that mathe⯑maticians reaſon for the moſt part in the firſt figure. What led him to think ſo was, that the firſt figure only yields concluſions that are uni⯑verſal and affirmative, and the concluſions of ma⯑thematics are commonly of that kind. But it is to be obſerved, that the propoſitions of ma⯑thematics are not categorical propoſitions, con⯑ſiſting of one ſubject and one predicate. They expreſs ſome relation which one quantity bears to another, and on that account muſt have three terms. The quantities compared make two, and the relation between them is a third. Now to ſuch propoſitions we can neither apply the rules concerning the converſion of propoſitions, nor can they enter into a ſyllogiſm of any of the figures or modes. We obſerved before, that this con⯑verſion, A is greater than B, therefore B is leſs than A, does not fall within the rules of conver⯑ſion given by Ariſtotle or the logicians; and we now add, that this ſimple reaſoning, A is equal to B, and B to C; therefore A is equal to C, can⯑not be brought into any ſyllogiſm in figure and mode. There are indeed ſyllogiſms into which mathematical propoſitions may enter, and of ſuch we ſhall afterwards ſpeak: but they have nothing to do with the ſyſtem of figure and mode.
When we go without the circle of the mathe⯑matical ſciences, I know nothing in which there ſeems to be ſo much demonſtration as in that part of logic which treats of the figures and modes of ſyllogiſm; but the few remarks we have made, ſhew, that it has ſome weak places: and be⯑ſides, this ſyſtem cannot be uſed as an engine to rear itſelf.
[242] The compaſs of the ſyllogiſtic ſyſtem as an en⯑gine of ſcience, may be diſcerned by a compen⯑dious and general view of the concluſion drawn, and the argument uſed to prove it, in each of the three figures.
In the firſt figure, the concluſion affirms or de⯑nies ſomething, of a certain ſpecies or individu⯑al; and the argument to prove this concluſion is, That the ſame thing may be affirmed or denied of the whole genus to which that ſpecies or indi⯑vidual belongs.
In the ſecond figure, the concluſion is, That ſome ſpecies or individual does not belong to ſuch a genus; and the argument is, That ſome attri⯑bute common to the whole genus does not belong to that ſpecies or individual.
In the third figure, the concluſion is, That ſuch an attribute belongs to part of a genus; and the argument is, That the attribute in queſtion belongs to a ſpecies or individual which is part of that genus.
I apprehend, that, in this ſhort view, every concluſion that falls within the compaſs of the three figures, as well as the mean of proof, is comprehended. The rules of all the figures might be eaſily deduced from it; and it appears, that there is only one principle of reaſoning in all the three; ſo that it is not ſtrange, that a ſyllo⯑giſm of one figure ſhould be reduced to one of another figure.
The general principle in which the whole ter⯑minates, and of which every categorical ſyllogiſm is only a particular application, is this, That what is affirmed or denied of the whole genus, may be affirmed or denied of every ſpecies and individual belonging to it. This is a principle of undoubted certainty indeed, but of no great depth. Ariſtotle and all the logicians aſſume it as [243] an axiom or firſt principle, from which the ſyl⯑logiſtic ſyſtem, as it were, takes its departure: and after a tedious voyage, and great expence of demonſtrations, it lands at laſt in this prin⯑ciple as its ultimate concluſion. O curas homi⯑num! O quantum eſt in rebus inane!
Categorical propoſitions, beſides their quantity and quality, have another affection, by which they are divided into pure and modal. In a pure propoſition, the predicate is barely affirmed or denied of the ſubject; but in a modal propoſi⯑tion, the affirmation or negation is modified, by being declared to be neceſſary or contingent, or poſſible or impoſſible. Theſe are the four modes obſerved by Ariſtotle, from which he denomi⯑nates a propoſition modal. His genuine diſciples maintain, that theſe are all the modes that can affect an affirmation or negation, and that the enumeration is complete. Othes maintain, that this enumeration is incomplete; and that when an affirmation or negation is ſaid to be certain or uncertain, probable or improbable, this makes a modal propoſition, no leſs than the four modes of Ariſtotle. We ſhall not enter into this diſpute; but proceed to obſerve, that the epithets of pure and modal are applied to ſyllogiſms as well as to propoſitions. A pure ſyllogiſm is that in which both premiſes are pure propoſitions. A modal ſyllogiſm is that in which either of the premiſes is a modal propoſition.
The ſyllogiſms of which we have already ſaid ſo much, are thoſe only which are pure as well as categorical. But when we conſider, that through all the figures and modes, a ſyllogiſm [244] may have one premiſe modal of any of the four modes, while the other is pure, or it may have both premiſes modal, and that they may be ei⯑ther of the ſame mode or of different modes; what prodigious variety ariſes from all theſe com⯑binations? Now it is the buſineſs of a logician, to ſhew how the concluſion is affected in all this variety of caſes. Ariſtotle has done this in his Firſt Analytics, with immenſe labour; and it will not be thought ſtrange, that when he had employed only four chapters in diſcuſſing one hundred and ninety-two modes, true and falſe, of pure ſyllogiſms, he ſhould employ fifteen up⯑on modal ſyllogiſms.
I am very willing to excuſe myſelf from enter⯑ing upon this great branch of logic, by the judg⯑ment and example of thoſe who cannot be char⯑ged either with want of reſpect to Ariſtotle, or with a low eſteem of the ſyllogiſtic art.
Keckerman, a famous Dantzican profeſſor, who ſpent his life in teaching and writing logic, in his huge folio ſyſtem of that ſcience, publiſhed ann. 1600, calls the doctrine of the modals the crux logicorum. With regard to the ſcholaſtic doctors, among whom this was a proverb, De modalibus non guſtabit aſinus, he thinks it very du⯑bious, whether they tortured moſt the modal ſyllogiſms, or were moſt tortured by them. But thoſe crabbed geniuſes, ſays he, made this doc⯑trine ſo very thorny, that it is fitter to tear a man's wits in pieces than to give them ſolidity. He deſires it to be obſerved, that the doctrine of modals is adapted to the Greek language. The modal terms were frequently uſed by the Greeks in their diſputations; and, on that account, are ſo fully handled by Ariſtotle: but in the Latin tongue you ſhall hardly ever meet with them. Nor do I remember, in all my experience, ſays [245] he, to have obſerved any man in danger of being foiled in a diſpute, through his ignorance of the modals.
This author, however, out of reſpect to Ari⯑ſtotle, treats pretty fully of modal propoſitions, ſhewing how to diſtinguiſh their ſubject and predicate, their quantity and quality. But the modal ſyllogiſms he paſſes over altogether.
Ludovicus Vives, whom I mention, not as a devotee of Ariſtotle, but on account of his own judgment and learning, thinks that the doctrine of modals ought to be baniſhed out of logic, and remitted to grammar; and that if the grammar of the Greek tongue had been brought to a ſyſ⯑tem in the time of Ariſtotle, that moſt acute philoſopher would have ſaved the great labour he has beſtowed on this ſubject.
Burgerſdick, after enumerating five claſſes of modal ſyllogiſms, obſerves, that they require ma⯑ny rules and cautions, which Ariſtotle hath hand⯑led diligently; but as the uſe of them is not great, and their rules are very difficult, he thinks it not worth while to enter into the diſcuſſion of them; recommending to thoſe who would underſtand them, the moſt learned paraphraſe of Joannes Monlorius, upon the firſt book of the Firſt Ana⯑lytics.
All the writers of logic for two hundred years back that have fallen into my hands, have paſſed over the rules of modal ſyllogiſms with as little ceremony. So that this great branch of the doc⯑trine of ſyllogiſm, ſo diligently handled by Ari⯑ſtotle, fell into neglect, if not contempt, even while the doctrine of pure ſyllogiſms continued in the higheſt eſteem. Moved by theſe authori⯑ties, I ſhall let this doctrine reſt in peace, with⯑out giving the leaſt diſturbance to its aſhes.
Ariſtotle gives ſome obſervations upon imper⯑fect ſyllogiſms: ſuch as, the Enthimema, in which one of the premiſes is not expreſſed but underſtood: Induction, wherein we collect an univerſal from a full enumeration of particulars: and Examples, which are an imperfect induction. The logicians have copied Ariſtotle upon theſe kinds of reaſoning, without any conſiderable im⯑provement. But to compenſate the modal ſyllo⯑giſms, which they have laid aſide, they have given rules for ſeveral kinds of ſyllogiſm, of which Ariſtotle takes no notice. Theſe may be reduced to two claſſes.
The firſt claſs comprehends the ſyllogiſms into which any excluſive, reſtrictive, exceptive, or reduplicative propoſition enters. Such propoſi⯑tions are by ſome called exponible, by others imperfectly modal. The rules given with regard to theſe are obvious, from a juſt interpretation of the propoſitions.
The ſecond claſs is that of hypothetical ſyllo⯑giſms, which take that denomination from having a hypothetical propoſition for one or both premi⯑ſes. Moſt logicians give the name of hypothetical to all complex propoſitions which have more terms than one ſubject and one predicate. I uſe the word in this large ſenſe; and mean by hypotheti⯑cal ſyllogiſms, all thoſe in which either of the pre⯑miſes conſiſts of more terms than two. How many various kinds there may be of ſuch ſyllogiſms, has never been aſcertained. The logicians have given names to ſome; ſuch as, the copulative, the con⯑ditional, [247] by ſome called hypothetical, and the diſ⯑junctive.
Such ſyllogiſms cannot be tried by the rules of figure and mode. Every kind would require rules peculiar to it. Logicians have given rules for ſome kinds; but there are many that have not ſo much as a name.
The Dilemma is conſidered by moſt logicians as a ſpecies of the disjunctive ſyllogiſm. A re⯑markable property of this kind is, that it may ſometimes be happily retorted: it is, it ſeems, like a hand-grenade, which, by dextrous management, may be thrown back, ſo as to ſpend its force upon the aſſailant. We ſhall conclude this tedious account of ſyllogiſms, with a dilemma mentioned by A. Gellius, and from him by many logicians, as inſoluble in any other way.
‘"Euathlus, a rich young man, deſirous of learning the art of pleading, applied to Prota⯑goras, a celebrated ſophiſt, to inſtruct him, promiſing a great ſum of money as his reward; one half of which was paid down; the other half he bound himſelf to pay as ſoon as he ſhould plead a cauſe before the judges, and gain it. Protagoras found him a very apt ſcho⯑lar; but, after he had made good progreſs, he was in no haſte to plead cauſes. The maſter, conceiving that he intended by this means to ſhift off his ſecond payment, took, as he thought, a ſure method to get the better of his delay. He ſued Euathlus before the judges; and, having opened his cauſe at the bar, he pleaded to this purpoſe. O moſt fooliſh young man, do you not ſee, that in any event, I muſt gain my point? for if the judges give ſentence for me, you muſt pay by their ſentence; if againſt me, the condition of our bargain is ful⯑filled, and you have no plea left for your de⯑lay, [248] after having pleaded and gained a cauſe. To which Euathlus anſwered. O moſt wiſe maſter, I might have avoided the force of your argument, by not pleading my own cauſe. But, giving up this advantage, do you not ſee, that whatever ſentence the judges paſs, I am ſafe? If they give ſentence for me, I am acquitted by their ſentence; if againſt me, the condition of our bargain is not fulfilled, by my pleading a cauſe, and loſing it. The judges, thinking the arguments unanſwe⯑rable on both ſides, put off the cauſe to a long day."’
CHAP. V.
Account of the remaining books of the Organon.
IN the Firſt Analytics, ſyllogiſms are conſider⯑ed in reſpect of their form; they are now to be conſidered in reſpect of their matter. The form lies in the neceſſary connection between the premiſes and the concluſion; and where ſuch a connection is wanting, they are ſaid to be informal, or vicious in point of form.
But where there is no fault in the form, there may be in the matter; that is, in the propoſi⯑tions of which they are compoſed, which may be true or falſe, probable or improbable.
[249] When the premiſes are certain, and the con⯑cluſion drawn from them in due form, this is demonſtration, and produces ſcience. Such ſyl⯑logiſms are called apodictical; and are handled in the two books of the Laſt Analytics. When the premiſes are not certain, but probable only, ſuch ſyllogiſms are called dialectical; and of them he treats in the eight books of the Topics. But there are ſome ſyllogiſms which ſeem to be perfect both in matter and form, when they are not really ſo: as, a face may ſeem beautiful which is but painted. Theſe being apt to de⯑ceive, and produce a falſe opinion, are called ſo⯑phiſtical; and they are the ſubject of the book concerning Sophiſms.
To return to the Laſt Analytics, which treat of demonſtration and of ſcience: We ſhall not pre⯑tend to abridge thoſe books; for Ariſtotle's wri⯑tings do not admit of abridgment: no man can ſay what he ſays in fewer words; and he is not often guilty of repetition. We ſhall only give ſome of his capital concluſions, omitting his long reaſonings and nice diſtinctions, of which his ge⯑nius was wonderfully productive.
All demonſtration muſt be built upon princi⯑ples already known; and theſe upon others of the ſame kind; until we come at laſt to firſt principles, which neither can be demonſtrated, nor need to be, being evident of themſelves.
We cannot demonſtrate things in a circle, ſupporting the concluſion by the premiſes, and the premiſes again by the concluſion. Nor can there be an infinite number of middle terms between the firſt principle and the con⯑cluſion.
In all demonſtration, the firſt principles, the concluſion, and all the intermediate propoſiti⯑ons, muſt be neceſſary, general, and eternal [250] truths: for of things fortuitous, contingent, or mutable, or of individual things, there is no de⯑monſtration.
Some demonſtrations prove only, that the thing is thus affected; others prove, why it is thus af⯑fected. The former may be drawn from a re⯑mote cauſe, or from an effect: but the latter muſt be drawn from an immediate cauſe; and are the moſt perfect.
The firſt figure is beſt adapted to demonſtrati⯑on, becauſe it affords concluſions univerſally af⯑firmative; and this figure is commonly uſed by the mathematicians.
The demonſtration of an affirmative pro⯑poſition is preferable to that of a negative; the demonſtration of an univerſal to that of a particu⯑lar; and direct demonſtration to that ad abſurdum.
The principles are more certain than the con⯑cluſion.
There cannot be opinion and ſcience of the ſame thing at the ſame time.
In the ſecond book we are taught, that the queſ⯑tions that may be put, with regard to any thing, are four: 1. Whether the thing be thus affected. 2. Why it is thus affected. 3. Whether it exiſts. 4. What it is.
The laſt of theſe queſtions Ariſtotle, in good Greek, calls the What is it of a thing. The ſchoolmen, in very barbarous Latin, called this, the quiddity of a thing. This quiddity, he proves by many arguments, cannot be demonſtrated, but muſt be fixed by a definition. This gives oc⯑caſion to treat of definition, and how a right defi⯑nition ſhould be formed. As an example he gives a definition of the number three, and defines it to be the firſt odd number.
In this book he treats alſo of the four kinds of cauſes; efficient, material, formal and final.
[251] Another thing treated of in this book is, the manner in which we acquire firſt principles, which are the foundation of all demonſtration. Theſe are not innate, becauſe we may be for a great part of life ignorant of them: nor can they be deduced demonſtratively from any antecedent knowledge, otherwiſe they would not be firſt principles. Therefore he concludes, that firſt principles are got by induction, from the informa⯑tions of ſenſe. The ſenſes give us informations of individual things, and from theſe by induction we draw general concluſions: for it is a max⯑im with Ariſtotle, That there is nothing in the underſtanding which was not before in ſome ſenſe.
The knowledge of firſt principles, as it is not acquired by demonſtration, ought not to be called ſcience; and therefore he calls it intelli⯑gence.
The profeſſed deſign of the Topics, is, to ſhew a method by which a man may be able to reaſon with probability and conſiſtency upon every queſ⯑tion that may occur.
Every queſtion is either about the genus of the ſubject, or its ſpecific difference, or ſome thing proper to it, or ſomething accidental.
To prove that this diviſion is complete, Ariſto⯑tle reaſons thus: Whatever is attributed to a ſub⯑ject, it muſt either be, that the ſubject can be re⯑ciprocally attributed to it, or that it cannot. If the ſubject and attribute can be reciprocated, the attribute either declares what the ſubject is, and then it is a definition; or it does not declare what the ſubject is, and then it is a property. If the attribute cannot be reciprocated, it muſt be ſome⯑thing [252] contained in the definition, or not. If it is contained in the definition of the ſubject, it muſt be the genus of the ſubject, or its ſpecific diffe⯑rence; for the definition conſiſts of theſe two. If it is not contained in the definition of the ſub⯑ject, it muſt be an accident.
The furniture proper to fit a man for arguing dialectically may be reduced to theſe four heads: 1. Probable propoſitions of all ſorts, which may on occaſion be aſſumed in an argument. 2. Diſ⯑tinctions of words which are nearly of the ſame ſignification. 3. Diſtinctions of things which are not ſo far aſunder but that they may be taken for one and the ſame. 4. Similitudes.
The ſecond and the five following books are taken up in enumerating the topics or heads of argument that may be uſed in queſtions about the genus, the definition, the properties, and the ac⯑cidents of a thing; and occaſionally he introduces the topics for proving things to be the ſame, or different; and the topics for proving one thing to be better or worſe than another.
In this enumeration of topics, Ariſtotle has ſhewn more the fertility of his genius, than the accuracy of method. The writers of logic ſeem to be of this opinion: for I know none of them that has followed him cloſely upon this ſubject. They have conſidered the topic of argumentation as reducible to certain axioms. For inſtance, when the queſtion is about the genus of a thing, it muſt be determined by ſome axiom about genus and ſpecies; when it is about definition, it muſt be determined by ſome axiom relating to definiti⯑on, and things defined: and ſo of other queſtions. They have therefore reduced the doctrine of the topics to certain axioms or canons, and diſpoſed theſe axioms in order under certain heads.
[253] This method ſeems to be more commodious and elegant than that of Ariſtotle. Yet it muſt be acknowledged, that Ariſtotle has furniſhed the materials from which all the logicians have bor⯑rowed their doctrine of topics: and even Cicero, Quintilian, and other rhetorical writers, have been much indebted to the topics of Ariſtotle.
He was the firſt, as far as I know, who made an attempt of this kind: and in this he acted up to the magnanimity of his own genius, and that of ancient philoſophy. Every ſubject of human thought had been reduced to ten categories; eve⯑ry thing that can be attributed to any ſubject, to five predicables: he attempted to reduce all the forms of reaſoning to fixed rules of figure and mode, and to reduce all the topics of argumentation under certain heads; and by that means to collect as it were into one ſtore all that can be ſaid on one ſide or the other of every queſtion, and provide a grand arſenal, from which all future combatants might be furniſhed with arms offenſive and defen⯑ſive in every cauſe, ſo as to leave no room to fu⯑ture generations to invent any thing new.
The laſt book of the Topics is a code of the laws, according to which a ſyllogiſtical diſputation ought to be managed, both on the part of the aſſailant and defendant. From which it is evi⯑dent, that this philoſopher trained his diſciples to contend, not for the truth merely, but for victo⯑ry.
A ſyllogiſm which leads to a falſe concluſion, muſt be vicious either in matter or form: for from true principles nothing but truth can be juſtly dedu⯑ced. If the matter be faulty, that is, if either of the premiſes be falſe, that premiſe muſt be deni⯑ed [254] by the defendant. If the form be faulty, ſome rule of ſyllogiſm is tranſgreſſed; and it is the part of the defendant to ſhew, what general or ſpecial rule it is that is tranſgreſſed. So that, if he is an able logician, he will be impregnable in the defence of truth, and may reſiſt all the at⯑tacks of the ſophiſt. But as there are ſyllogiſms which may ſeem to be perfect both in matter and form, when they are not really ſo, as a piece of money may ſeem to be good coin, when it is adulterate; ſuch fallacious ſyllogiſms are conſide⯑red in this treatiſe, in order to make a defendant more expert in the uſe of his defenſive weapons.
And here the author, with his uſual magnani⯑mity, attempts to bring all the fallacies that can enter into a ſyllogiſm under thirteen heads; of which ſix lie in the diction or language, and ſeven not in the diction.
The fallacies in diction are, 1. When an ambigu⯑ous word is taken at one time in one ſenſe, and at another time in another. 2. When an ambiguous phraſe is taken in the ſame manner. 3. and 4. are ambiguities in ſyntax; when words are conjoined in ſyntax that ought to be disjoined; or disjoined when they ought to be conjoined. 5. is an am⯑biguity in proſody, accent, or pronunciation. 6. An ambiguity ariſing from ſome figure of ſpeech.
When a ſophiſm of any of theſe kinds is tran⯑ſlated into another language, or even rendered into unambiguous expreſſions in the ſame lan⯑guage, the fallacy is evident, and the ſyllogiſm appears to have four terms.
The ſeven fallacies which are ſaid not to be in the diction, but in the thing, have their proper names in Greek and in Latin, by which they are diſtinguiſhed. Without minding their names, we ſhall give a brief account of their nature.
[255] 1. The firſt is, Taking an accidental conjunc⯑tion of things for a natural or neceſſary connecti⯑on: as, when from an accident we infer a pro⯑perty; when from an example we infer a rule; when from a ſingle act we infer a habit.
2. Taking that abſolutely which ought to be taken comparatively, or with a certain limitation. The conſtruction of language often leads into this fallacy: for in all languages it is common to uſe abſolute terms, to ſignify things which carry in them ſome ſecret compariſon; or to uſe unlimi⯑ted terms, to ſignify what from its nature muſt be limited.
3. Taking that for the cauſe of a thing which was only an occaſion, or concomitant.
4. Begging the queſtion. This is done, when the thing to be proved, or ſome thing equivalent, is aſſumed in the premiſes.
5. Miſtaking the queſtion. When the con⯑cluſion of the ſyllogiſm is not the thing that ought to be proved, but ſomething elſe that is miſtaken for it.
6. When that which is not a conſequence is miſtaken for a conſequence; as if, becauſe all Africans are black, it were taken for granted that all the blacks are Africans.
7. The laſt fallacy lies in propoſitions that are complex, and imply two affirmations, whereof one may be true, and the other falſe; ſo that whether you grant the propoſition, or deny it, you are intangled: as when it is affirmed, that ſuch a man has left off playing the fool. If it be granted, it implies, that he did play the fool for⯑merly. If it be denied, it implies, or ſeems to imply, that he plays the fool ſtill.
In this enumeration, we ought, in juſtice to Ariſtotle, to expect only the fallacies incident to categorical ſyllogiſms. And I do not find, [256] that the logicians have made any additions to it when taken in this view; although they have gi⯑ven ſome other fallacies that are incident to ſyllo⯑giſms of the hypothetical kind, particularly the fallacy of an incomplete enumeration in disjunc⯑tive ſyllogiſms and dilemmas.
The different ſpecies of ſophiſms above men⯑tioned are not ſo preciſely defined by Ariſtotle, or by ſubſequent logicians, but that they allow of great latitude in the application; and it is often dubious under what particular ſpecies a ſophiſti⯑cal ſyllogiſm ought to be claſſed. We even find the ſame example brought under one ſpecies by one author, and under another ſpecies by another. Nay, what is more ſtrange, Ariſtotle himſelf employs a long chapter in proving by a particular induction, that all the ſeven may be brought un⯑der that which we have called miſtaking the queſti⯑on, and which is commonly called ignoratio elenchi. And indeed the proof of this is eaſy, without that laborious detail which Ariſtotle uſes for the pur⯑poſe: for if you lop off from the concluſion of a ſophiſtical ſyllogiſm all that is not ſupported by the premiſes, the concluſion, in that caſe, will always be found different from that which ought to have been proved; and ſo it falls under the ignoratio elenchi.
It was probably Ariſtotle's aim, to reduce all the poſſible variety of ſophiſms, as he had at⯑tempted to do of juſt ſyllogiſms, to certain defi⯑nite ſpecies: but he ſeems to be ſenſible that he had fallen ſhort in this laſt attempt. When a ge⯑nus is properly divided into its ſpecies, the ſpecies ſhould not only, when taken together, exhauſt the whole genus; but every ſpecies ſhould have its own precinct ſo accurately defined, that one ſhall not encroach upon another. And when an individual can be ſaid to belong to two or three [257] different ſpecies, the diviſion is imperfect; yet this is the caſe of Ariſtotle's diviſion of the ſophiſms, by his own acknowledgment. It ought not therefore to be taken for a diviſion ſtrictly logical. It may rather be compared to the ſeveral ſpecies or forms of action invented in law for the redreſs of wrongs. For every wrong there is a remedy in law by one action or another: but ſometimes a man may take his choice among ſeveral different actions. So every ſophiſtical ſyllogiſm may, by a little art, be brought under one or other of the ſpecies men⯑tioned by Ariſtotle, and very often you may take your choice of two or three.
Beſides the enumeration of the various kinds of ſophiſms, there are many other things in this treatiſe concerning the art of managing a ſyllogiſ⯑tical diſpute with an antagoniſt. And indeed, if the paſſion for this kind of litigation, which reigned for ſo many ages, ſhould ever again lift up its head, we may predict, that the Organon of Ariſtotle will then become a faſhionable ſtudy: for it contains ſuch admirable materials and docu⯑ments for this art, that it may be ſaid to have brought it to a ſcience.
The concluſion of this treatiſe ought not to be overlooked: it manifeſtly relates, not to the pre⯑ſent treatiſe only, but alſo to the whole analytics and topics of the author. I ſhall therefore give the ſubſtance of it.
"We have therefore employed much time and labour upon this ſubject; and if our ſyſtem appears to you not to be in the number of thoſe things, which, being before carried a certain length, were left to be perfected; we hope for your favourable acceptance of what is done, and your indulgence in what is left im⯑perfect."
CHAP. VI.
Reflections on the Utility of Logic, and the Means of its Improvement.
[259]MEN rarely leave one extreme without running into the contrary. It is no wonder, therefore, that the exceſſive admiration of Ariſ⯑totle, which continued for ſo many ages, ſhould end in an undue contempt; and that the high eſteem of logic as the grand engine of ſcience, ſhould at laſt make way for too unfavourable an opinion, which ſeems now prevalent, of its being unworthy of a place in a liberal education. Thoſe who think according to the faſhion, as the greateſt part of men do, will be as prone to go into this extreme, as their grandfathers were to go into the contrary.
Laying aſide prejudice, whether faſhionable or unfaſhionable, let us conſider whether logic is, or may be made ſubſervient to any good purpoſe. Its profeſſed end is, to teach men to think, to judge, and to reaſon, with preciſion and accura⯑cy. No man will ſay that this is a matter of no importance; the only thing, therefore, that ad⯑mits of doubt, is, whether it can be taught.
[260] To reſolve this doubt, it may be obſerved, that our rational faculty is the gift of God, given to men in very different meaſure. Some have a larger portion, ſome a leſs; and where there is a remarkable defect of the natural power, it can⯑not be ſupplied by any culture whatſoever. But this natural power, even where it is ſtrongeſt, may lie dead for want of the means of improve⯑ment; and a ſavage may have been born with as good faculties as a Bacon or a Newton. The amazing difference that appears in advanced life, is owing to this, that the talent of one was bu⯑ried, being never put to uſe, while that of the other was cultivated to the beſt advantage.
It may likewiſe be obſerved, that the chief mean of improving our rational power, is the vigorous exerciſe of it, in various ways, and in different ſubjects, by which the habit is ac⯑quired of exerciſing it properly. Without ſuch exerciſe, and good ſenſe over and above, a man who has ſtudied logic all his life may, after all, be only a petulant wrangler, without true judgment, or ſkill of reaſoning, in any ſcience.
I take this to be Locke's meaning, when, in his Thoughts on Education, he ſays, ‘"If you would have your ſon to reaſon well, let him read Chillingworth."’ The ſtate of things is much altered ſince Locke wrote. Logic has been much improved, chiefly by his writings; and yet much leſs ſtreſs is laid upon it, and leſs time conſumed in it. His counſel, therefore, was judicious and ſeaſonable; to wit, That the improvement of our reaſoning power is to be expected much more from an intimate acquaintance with the authors who reaſon beſt, than from ſtudying voluminous ſyſtems of logic. But if he had meant, that the ſtudy of logic was of no uſe, nor deſerved any at⯑tention, he ſurely would not have taken the pains [261] to have made ſo conſiderable an addition to it, by his Eſſay on the Human Underſtanding, and by his Thoughts on the Conduct of the Underſtanding. Nor would he have remitted his pupil to Chillingworth, the acuteſt logician, as well as the beſt reaſoner, of his age; and one who, in innumerable places of his excellent book, without pedantry even in that pedantic age, makes the happieſt application of the rules of logic, for unravelling the ſophiſtical reaſoning of his antagoniſt.
Our reaſoning power makes no appearance in infancy; but as we grow up, it unfolds itſelf by degrees, like the bud of a tree. When a child firſt draws an inference, or perceives the force of an inference drawn by another perſon, we may call this the birth of his reaſon: but it is yet like a new-born babe, weak and tender; it muſt be cheriſhed, and carried in arms, and have food of eaſy digeſtion, till it gathers ſtrength.
I believe no man remembers this birth of his rea⯑ſon; but it is probable that his deciſions will at firſt be weak and wavering; and, compared with that ſteady conviction which he acquires in ripe years, will be like the dawn of the morning com⯑pared with noon-day. We ſee that the reaſon of children yields to authority, as a reed to the wind; nay, that it clings to it, and leans upon it, as if conſcious of its own weakneſs.
When reaſon acquires ſuch ſtrength as to ſtand on its own bottom, without the aid of authority, or even in oppoſition to authority, this may be called its manly age. But in moſt men, it hardly ever arrives at this period. Many, by their ſitu⯑ation in life, have not the opportunity of cultiva⯑ting their rational powers. Many from the habit they have acquired, of ſubmitting their opini⯑ons to the authority of others, or from ſome other principle which operates more powerfully than the [262] love of truth, ſuffer their judgment to be carried along to the end of their days, either by the au⯑thority of a leader, or of a party, or of the mul⯑titude, or by their own paſſions. Such perſons, however learned, however acute, may be ſaid to be all their days children in underſtanding. They reaſon, they diſpute, and perhaps write; but it is not that they may find the truth; but that they may defend opinions which have deſcended to them by inheritance, or into which they have fal⯑len by accident, or been led by affection.
I agree with Mr. Locke, that there is no ſtudy better fitted to exerciſe and ſtrengthen the reaſon⯑ing powers, than that of the mathematical ſcien⯑ces; for two reaſons; firſt, Becauſe there is no other branch of ſcience which gives ſuch ſcope to long and accurate trains of reaſoning; and ſecond⯑ly, Becauſe in mathematics there is no room for authority, or for prejudice of any kind, which may give a falſe bias to the judgment.
When a youth of moderate parts begins to ſtu⯑dy Euclid, every thing at firſt is new to him. His apprehenſion is unſteady; his judgment is fee⯑ble; and reſts partly upon the evidence of the thing, and partly upon the authority of his teach⯑er. But every time he goes over the definitions, the axioms, the elementary propoſitions, more light breaks in upon him; the language becomes familiar, and conveys clear and ſteady conceptions; the judgment is confirmed; he begins to ſee what demonſtration is; and it is impoſſible to ſee it without being charmed with it. He perceives it to be a kind of evidence which has no need of autho⯑rity to ſtrengthen it. He finds himſelf emancipa⯑ted from that bondage, and exults ſo much in this new ſtate of independence, that he ſpurns at au⯑thority, and would have demonſtration for every thing; until experience teaches him, that this is a [263] kind of evidence which cannot be had in moſt things; and that in his moſt important concerns, he muſt reſt contented with probability.
As he goes on in mathematics, the road of de⯑monſtrations becomes ſmooth and eaſy; he can walk in it firmly, and take wider ſteps: and, at laſt, he acquires the habit, not only of under⯑ſtanding a demonſtration, but of diſcovering and demonſtrating mathematical truths.
Thus, a man without rules of logic, may ac⯑quire the habit of reaſoning juſtly in mathematics; and, I believe, he may, by like means, acquire the habit of reaſoning juſtly in mechanics, in ju⯑riſprudence, in politics, or in any other ſcience. Good ſenſe, good examples, and aſſiduous exer⯑ciſe, may bring a man to reaſon juſtly and acute⯑ly in his own profeſſion, without rules.
But if any man think, that from this con⯑ceſſion he may infer the inutility of logic, he be⯑trays a great want of that art by this inference: for it is no better reaſoning than this, That be⯑cauſe a man may go from Edinburgh to London by the way of Paris, therefore any other road is uſeleſs.
There is perhaps no practical art which may not be acquired, in a very conſiderable degree, by example and practice, without reducing it to rules. But practice, joined with rules, may carry a man on in his art farther and more quickly, than practice without rules. Every ingenious artiſt knows the utility of having his art reduced to rules, and by that means made a ſcience. He is thereby enlightened in his practice, and works with more aſſurance. By rules, he ſometimes corrects his own errors, and often detects the er⯑rors of others: he finds them of great uſe to con⯑firm his judgment, to juſtify what is right, and to condemn what is wrong.
[264] Is it of no uſe in reaſoning, to be well acquaint⯑ed with the various powers of the human under⯑ſtanding, by which we reaſon? Is it of no uſe, to reſolve the various kinds of reaſoning into their ſimple elements; and to diſcover, as far as we are able, the rules by which thoſe elements are com⯑bined in judging and in reaſoning? Is it of no uſe, to mark the various fallacies in reaſoning, by which even the moſt ingenious men have been led into error? It muſt ſurely betray great want of underſtanding, to think theſe things uſeleſs or unimportant. Theſe are the things which logi⯑cians have attempted; and which they have exe⯑cuted; not indeed ſo completely as to leave no room for improvement, but in ſuch a manner as to give very conſiderable aid to our reaſoning powers. That the principles laid down with re⯑gard to definition and diviſion, with regard to the converſion and oppoſition of propoſitions and the general rules of reaſoning, are not without uſe, is ſufficiently apparent from the blunders commit⯑ted by thoſe who diſdain any acquaintance with them.
Although the art of categorical ſyllogiſm is bet⯑ter fitted for ſcholaſtic litigation, than for real im⯑provement in knowledge, it is a venerable piece of antiquity, and a great effort of human genius. We admire the pyramids of Egypt, and the wall of China, though uſeleſs burdens upon the earth. We can bear the moſt minute deſcription of them, and travel hundreds of leagues to ſee them. If any perſon ſhould, with ſacrilegious hands, de⯑ſtroy or deface them, his memory would be had in abhorrence. The predicaments and predica⯑bles, the rules of ſyllogiſm, and the topics, have a like title to our veneration as antiquities: they are uncommon efforts, not of human power, but [265] of human genius; and they make a remarkable period in the progreſs of human reaſon.
The prejudice againſt logic has probably been ſtrengthened by its being taught too early in life. Boys are often taught logic as they are taught their creed, when it is an exerciſe of memory on⯑ly, without underſtanding. One may as well ex⯑pect to underſtand grammar before he can ſpeak, as to underſtand logic before he can reaſon. It muſt even be acknowledged, that commonly we are capabable of reaſoning in mathematics more early than in logic. The objects preſented to the mind in this ſcience, are of a very abſtract nature, and can be diſtinctly conceived only when we are capable of attentive reflection upon the operations of our own underſtanding, and after we have been accuſtomed to reaſon. There may be an elementary logic, level to the capacity of thoſe who have been but little exerciſed in reaſoning; but the moſt important parts of this ſcience require a ripe underſtanding, capable of reflecting upon its own operations. Therefore to make logic the firſt branch of ſcience that is to be taught, is an old error that ought to be corrected.
In compoſitions of human thought expreſ⯑ſed by ſpeech or by writing, whatever is excel⯑lent and whatever is faulty, fall within the pro⯑vince, either of grammar, or of rhetoric, or of logic. Propriety of expreſſion is the province of grammar; grace, elegance, and force, in thought and in expreſſion, are the province of rhetoric; juſtneſs and accuracy of thought are the province of logic.
[266] The faults in compoſition, therefore, which fall under the cenſure of logic, are obſcure and indiſtinct conceptions, falſe judgment, inconclu⯑ſive reaſoning, and all improprieties in diſtincti⯑ons, definitions, diviſion, or method. To aid our rational powers, in avoiding theſe faults and in attaining the oppoſite excellencies, is the end of logic; and whatever there is in it that has no tendency to promote this end, ought to be thrown out.
The rules of logic being of a very abſtract na⯑ture, ought to be illuſtrated by a variety of real and ſtriking examples taken from the writings of good authors. It is both inſtructive and enter⯑taining, to obſerve the virtues of accurate com⯑poſition in writers of fame. We cannot ſee them, without being drawn to the imitation of them, in a more powerful manner than we can be by dry rules. Nor are the faults of ſuch writers leſs inſtructive or leſs powerful monitors. A wreck, left upon a ſhoal, or upon a rock, is not more uſeful to the ſailor, than the faults of good writ⯑ers, when ſet up to view, are to thoſe who come after them. It was a happy thought in a late in⯑genious writer on Engliſh Grammar, to collect under the ſeveral rules, examples of bad Engliſh found in the moſt approved authors. It were to be wiſhed that the rules of logic were illuſtrated in the ſame manner. By this means, a ſyſtem of logic would become a repoſitory; wherein what⯑ever is moſt acute in judging and in reaſoning, whatever is moſt accurate in dividing, diſtinguiſh⯑ing, and defining, ſhould be laid up and diſpoſed in order for our imitation; and wherein the falſe ſteps of eminent authors ſhould be recorded for our admonition.
After men had laboured in the ſearch of truth near two thouſand years, by the help of ſyllo⯑giſms, [267] Lord Bacon propoſed the method of in⯑duction, as a more effectual engine, for that pur⯑poſe. His Novum Organum gave a new turn to the thoughts and labours of the inquiſitive, more re⯑markable, and more uſeful, than that which the Organum of Ariſtotle had given before; and may be conſidered as a ſecond grand aera in the progreſs of human reaſon.
The art of ſyllogiſm produced numberleſs diſ⯑putes, and numberleſs ſects, who fought againſt each other with much animoſity, without gaining or loſing ground; but did nothing conſiderable for the benefit of human life. The art of induc⯑tion, firſt delineated by Lord Bacon, produced numberleſs laboratories and obſervatories, in which Nature has been put to the queſtion by thouſands of experiments, and forced to confeſs many of her ſecrets, which before were hid from mortals. And by theſe, arts have been improved, and hu⯑man knowledge wonderfully increaſed.
In reaſoning by ſyllogiſm, from general prin⯑ciples we deſcend to a concluſion virtually con⯑tained in them. The proceſs of induction is more arduous; being an aſcent from particular premi⯑ſes to a general concluſion. The evidence of ſuch general concluſions is not demonſtrative, but probable: but when the induction is ſufficiently copious, and carried on according to the rules of art, it forces conviction no leſs than demonſtrati⯑on itſelf does.
The greateſt part of human knowledge reſts upon evidence of this kind. Indeed we can have no other for general truths which are contingent in their nature, and depend upon the will and or⯑dination of the Maker of the world. He governs the world he has made, by general laws. The effects of theſe laws in particular phenomena are open to our obſervation; and by obſerving a [268] train of uniform effects with due caution, we may at laſt decypher the law of nature by which they are regulated.
Lord Bacon has diſplayed no leſs force of ge⯑nius in reducing to rules this method of reaſoning, than Ariſtotle did in the method of ſyllogiſm. His Novum Organum ought therefore to be held as a moſt important addition to the ancient logic. Thoſe who underſtand it, and enter into the ſpi⯑rit of it, will be able to diſtinguiſh the chaff from the wheat in philoſophical diſquiſitions into the works of God. They will learn to hold in due contempt all hypotheſes and theories, the crea⯑tures of human imagination, and to reſpect no⯑thing but facts ſufficiently vouched, or concluſi⯑ons drawn from them by a fair and chaſte inter⯑pretation of nature.
Moſt arts have been reduced to rules, after they had been brought to a conſiderable degree of perfection by the natural ſagacity of artiſts; and the rules have been drawn from the beſt ex⯑amples of the art that had been before exhibited: but the art of philoſophical induction was deli⯑neated by Lord Bacon in a very ample manner, before the world had ſeen any tolerable example of it. This, although it adds greatly to the merit of the author, muſt have produced ſome obſcuri⯑ty in the work, and a defect of proper examples for illuſtration. This defect may now be eaſily ſupplied, from thoſe authors who, in their philo⯑ſophical diſquiſitions, have moſt ſtrictly purſu⯑ed the path pointed out in the Novum Organum, Among theſe Sir Iſaac Newton ſeems to hold the firſt rank, having, in the third book of his Princi⯑pia, and in his Optics, had the rules of the No⯑vum Organum conſtantly in his eye.
I think Lord Bacon was alſo the firſt who en⯑deavoured to reduce to a ſyſtem the prejudices or [269] biaſſes of the mind, which are the cauſes of falſe judgment, and which he calls the idols of the hu⯑man underſtanding. Some late writers of logic have very properly introduced this into their ſyſtem; but it deſerves to be more copiouſly handled, and to be illuſtrated by real examples.
It is of great conſequence to accurate reaſoning, to diſtinguiſh firſt principles which are to be ta⯑ken for granted, from propoſitions which require proof. All the real knowledge of mankind may be divided into two parts: the firſt conſiſting of ſelf-evident propoſitions; the ſecond, of thoſe which are deduced by juſt reaſoning from ſelf-evi⯑dent propoſitions. The line which divides theſe two parts ought to be marked as diſtinctly as poſ⯑ſible, and the principles that are ſelf-evident re⯑duced, as far as can be done, to general axioms. This has been done in mathematics from the be⯑ginning, and has tended greatly to the emolument of that ſcience. It has lately been done in natu⯑ral philoſophy: and by this means that ſcience has advanced more in an hundred and fifty years, than it had done before in two thouſand. Every ſci⯑ence is in an unformed ſtate until its firſt principles are aſcertained: after that is done, it advances re⯑gularly, and ſecures the ground it has gained.
Although firſt principles do not admit of direct proof, yet there muſt be certain marks and cha⯑racters, by which thoſe that are truly ſuch may be diſtinguiſhed from counterfeits. Theſe marks ought to be deſcribed, and applied, to diſtinguiſh the genuine from the ſpurious.
In the ancient philoſophy there is a redundance, rather than a defect, of firſt principles. Many things were aſſumed under that character without a juſt title: That nature abhors a vacuum; That bodies do not gravitate in their proper place; That the heavenly bodies undergo no change; [270] That they move in perfect circles, and with an equable motion. Such principles as theſe were aſſumed in the Peripatetic philoſophy, without proof, as if they were ſelf-evident.
Des Cartes, ſenſible of this weakneſs in the ancient philoſophy, and deſirous to guard againſt it in his own ſyſtem, reſolved to admit nothing until his aſſent was forced by irreſiſtible evidence. The firſt thing which he found to be certain and evident was, that he thought, and reaſoned, and doubted. He found himſelf under a neceſſity of believing the exiſtence of thoſe operations of mind of which he was conſcious: and having thus found ſure footing in this one principle of conſci⯑ouſneſs, he reſted ſatisfied with it, hoping to be able to build the whole fabric of his knowledge upon it; like Archimedes, who wanted but one fixed point to move the whole earth. But the foundation was too narrow; and in his progreſs he unawares aſſumes many things leſs evident than thoſe which he attempts to prove. Although he was not able to ſuſpect the teſtimony of conſciouſ⯑neſs, yet he thought the teſtimony of ſenſe, of me⯑mory, and of every other faculty, might be ſuſ⯑pected, and ought not to be received until proof was brought that they are not fallacious. Therefore he applies theſe faculties, whoſe character is yet in queſtion, to prove, That there is an infinitely perfect Being who made him, and who made his ſenſes, his memory, his reaſon, and all his faculties; That this Being is no deceiver, and therefore could not give him faculties that are fallacious; and that on this account they deſerve credit.
It is ſtrange, that this philoſopher, who found himſelf under a neceſſity of yielding to the teſti⯑mony of conſciouſneſs, did not find the ſame ne⯑ceſſity of yielding to the teſtimony of his ſenſes, [271] his memory, and his underſtanding: and that while he was certain that he doubted, and reaſon⯑ed, he was uncertain whether two and three made five, and whether he was dreaming or awake. It is more ſtrange, that ſo acute a reaſoner ſhould not perceive, that his whole train of reaſoning to prove that his faculties were not fallacious, was mere ſophiſtry: for if his faculties were falla⯑cious, they might deceive him in this train of reaſoning; and ſo the concluſion, That they were not fallacious, was only the teſtimony of his faculties in their own favour, and might be a fallacy.
It is difficult to give any reaſon for diſtruſting our other faculties, that will not reach conſciouſ⯑neſs itſelf. And he who diſtruſts thoſe faculties of judging and reaſoning which God hath given him, muſt even reſt in his ſcepticiſm till he come to a ſound mind, or until God give him new fa⯑culties to ſit in judgment upon the old. If it be not a firſt principle, That our faculties are not fallacious, we muſt be abſolute ſceptics: for this principle is incapable of proof; and if it is not certain, nothing elſe can be certain.
Since the time of Des Cartes, it has been faſhionable with thoſe who dealt in abſtract philoſophy, to employ their invention in find⯑ing philoſophical arguments, either to prove thoſe truths which ought to be received as firſt principles, or to overturn them: and it is not eaſy to ſay, whether the authority of firſt prin⯑ciples is more hurt by the firſt of theſe attempts, or by the laſt; for ſuch principles can ſtand ſecure only upon their own bottom; and to place them upon any other foundation than that of their intrinſic evidence, is in effect to overturn them.
[272] I have lately met with a very ſenſible and judi⯑cious treatiſe, wrote by Father Buffier about fifty years ago, concerning firſt principles, and the ſource of human judgments, which, with great propriety, he prefixed to his treatiſe of logic. And indeed I apprehend it is a ſubject of ſuch con⯑ſequence, that if inquiſitive men can be brought to the ſame unanimity in the firſt principles of the other ſciences, as in thoſe of mathematics and natural philoſophy, (and why ſhould we deſpair of a general agreement in things that are ſelf-evident?), this might be conſidered as a third grand aera in the progreſs of human reaſon.
- Citation Suggestion for this Object
- TextGrid Repository (2020). TEI. 4514 Sketches of the history of man In four volumes By Henry Home Lord Kaims pt 3. University of Oxford Text Archive. . https://hdl.handle.net/21.T11991/0000-001A-5D86-5